首页 > 最新文献

EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY最新文献

英文 中文
Presentations and evaluations: A new look at Husserl's distinction between objectifying and non‐objectifying acts 呈现与评价:重新审视胡塞尔对客观化与非客观化行为的区分
2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-11-13 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12913
Andrea Sebastiano Staiti
Abstract In this paper, I take a fresh look at Husserl's key distinction between objectifying and non‐objectifying acts, which roughly amounts to a distinction between presentational and evaluative experiences. My goal is to provide a clear and unified reconstruction of Husserl's argument for the thesis that non‐objectifying acts are necessarily founded in objectifying acts, a thesis that is highly controversial in and beyond Husserlian scholarship. In the first section, I reconstruct Husserl's view in the Logical Investigations , according to which only objectifying acts establish an independent intentional relation to their objects, and argue that it is justified by the positing function of objectifying acts. In the second section, I address two problematic interpretations of this view and, after criticizing them, I present what I take to be Husserl's core argument for his position. In the third section, I turn to the revision of the view of the Logical Investigations that Husserl proposes in the wake of his transcendental turn, especially in Ideas I and II . On Husserl's revised view, all acts are objectifying, including emotional acts [ Gemütsakte ]. This revision has led scholars to consider Husserl's view aporetic. I propose an alternative interpretation that dispels the purported aporia . I conclude with some remarks on the costs and benefits of my reading, as well as the strengths and weaknesses of Husserl's view in general.
在本文中,我重新审视胡塞尔对客观化和非客观化行为的关键区分,这大致相当于对表象经验和评价经验的区分。我的目标是为胡塞尔的论点提供一个清晰而统一的重建,即非客观化行为必然建立在客观化行为的基础上,这一论点在胡塞尔学术界内外都是极具争议的。在第一节中,我重构了胡塞尔在《逻辑研究》中的观点,根据胡塞尔的观点,只有对象化的行为才能与它们的对象建立一种独立的意向性关系,并论证了对象化行为的假设功能证明了这一点。在第二部分,我提出了对这一观点的两种有问题的解释,在批评它们之后,我提出了胡塞尔对其立场的核心论点。在第三部分,我将转向对胡塞尔在其先验转向之后,特别是在理念一和理念二中提出的逻辑研究观点的修正。在胡塞尔修正后的观点中,所有的行为都是物化的,包括情感行为[gem tsakte]。这种修正导致学者们认为胡塞尔的观点是虚假的。我提出了另一种解释,消除了所谓的恐慌。最后,我对我阅读的成本和收益,以及胡塞尔观点的优点和缺点做了一些评论。
{"title":"Presentations and evaluations: A new look at Husserl's distinction between objectifying and <scp>non‐objectifying</scp> acts","authors":"Andrea Sebastiano Staiti","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12913","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12913","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract In this paper, I take a fresh look at Husserl's key distinction between objectifying and non‐objectifying acts, which roughly amounts to a distinction between presentational and evaluative experiences. My goal is to provide a clear and unified reconstruction of Husserl's argument for the thesis that non‐objectifying acts are necessarily founded in objectifying acts, a thesis that is highly controversial in and beyond Husserlian scholarship. In the first section, I reconstruct Husserl's view in the Logical Investigations , according to which only objectifying acts establish an independent intentional relation to their objects, and argue that it is justified by the positing function of objectifying acts. In the second section, I address two problematic interpretations of this view and, after criticizing them, I present what I take to be Husserl's core argument for his position. In the third section, I turn to the revision of the view of the Logical Investigations that Husserl proposes in the wake of his transcendental turn, especially in Ideas I and II . On Husserl's revised view, all acts are objectifying, including emotional acts [ Gemütsakte ]. This revision has led scholars to consider Husserl's view aporetic. I propose an alternative interpretation that dispels the purported aporia . I conclude with some remarks on the costs and benefits of my reading, as well as the strengths and weaknesses of Husserl's view in general.","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"50 9","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"136348310","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The metaphysics science needs: Deleuze's naturalism 科学需要的形而上学:德勒兹的自然主义
IF 0.7 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-11-07 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12909
George Webster

This article is aimed at those interested in the philosophy of Gilles Deleuze and the sciences—and this includes philosophers of science working out of the analytic tradition. Deleuze's writings are riddled with references to science and mathematics. And yet, the relation between these references and his philosophical thought is not well understood. In this essay, I investigate the nature of this relation—and I do so by asking whether it is naturalistic. Importantly, I draw on insights from contemporary philosophy of science to contribute to a proper understanding of this issue. I show that and how commentators are hamstrung by their lack of engagement with the philosophy of science; I present an interpretation of Deleuze's philosophical project as attempting to articulate an immanent and primitive form of objective modality; I draw together parts of Deleuze's corpus that are relevant to his treatment of the sciences but are nonetheless rarely studied in conjunction (including his and Guattari's distinction between ‘major’ and ‘minor’ science and his under-scrutinized statement of interest in ‘the metaphysics science needs’); and I propose a naturalistic interpretation of his engagements with science.

本文的读者对象是那些对吉勒-德勒兹的哲学和科学感兴趣的人--其中包括从分析传统中走出来的科学哲学家。德勒兹的著作中充满了对科学和数学的引用。然而,人们对这些引用与他的哲学思想之间的关系却不甚了解。在这篇文章中,我将探究这种关系的本质--并提出这种关系是否是自然主义的。重要的是,我借鉴了当代科学哲学的见解,以促进对这一问题的正确理解。我将德勒兹的哲学项目解释为试图阐明一种内在的、原始的客观模态;我汇集了德勒兹文集中与他对科学的论述相关、但却很少被一并研究的部分(包括他与瓜塔里对 "主要 "与 "次要 "科学的区分,以及他对 "科学所需的形而上学 "兴趣不大的论述);我对他与科学的关系提出了一种自然主义的解释。
{"title":"The metaphysics science needs: Deleuze's naturalism","authors":"George Webster","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12909","DOIUrl":"10.1111/ejop.12909","url":null,"abstract":"<p>This article is aimed at those interested in the philosophy of Gilles Deleuze and the sciences—and this includes philosophers of science working out of the analytic tradition. Deleuze's writings are riddled with references to science and mathematics. And yet, the relation between these references and his philosophical thought is not well understood. In this essay, I investigate the nature of this relation—and I do so by asking whether it is naturalistic. Importantly, I draw on insights from contemporary philosophy of science to contribute to a proper understanding of this issue. I show that and how commentators are hamstrung by their lack of engagement with the philosophy of science; I present an interpretation of Deleuze's philosophical project as attempting to articulate an immanent and primitive form of objective modality; I draw together parts of Deleuze's corpus that are relevant to his treatment of the sciences but are nonetheless rarely studied in conjunction (including his and Guattari's distinction between ‘major’ and ‘minor’ science and his under-scrutinized statement of interest in ‘the metaphysics science needs’); and I propose a naturalistic interpretation of his engagements with science.</p>","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"32 3","pages":"820-846"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2023-11-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/ejop.12909","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135475948","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The critical limits of phenomenology: Husserlian phenomenology as a modest metaphysics of appearance 现象学的批判限度:胡塞尔现象学作为一种适度的表象形而上学
IF 0.7 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-11-07 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12910
Emiliano Diaz

Although Husserlian phenomenology appears to require that practitioners bracket all metaphysical questions and claims, this requirement runs against the evidence of experience in which objects themselves are presented as constituents of experience. Moreover, to completely bracket metaphysical considerations would suggest that phenomenology is compatible with metaphysical views it should in principle deny. Nonetheless, permitting metaphysical claims threatens to contravene the critical limits of phenomenology, to invite claims that would require a perspective different in kind than our own to verify. These tensions raise an important question, namely, what are the metaphysical implications of the phenomenologically intuitive claim that objects themselves are constituents of experience? To answer this question, I draw on a broad swath of thought on transcendental idealism and phenomenology. I argue that a modest metaphysics of appearance is warranted within the critical limits of Husserlian phenomenology. Through discussing and addressing the problems that typically plague transcendental arguments, I show that Husserlian phenomenology permits stronger claims about objects of experience than deflationary accounts allow but does not permit claims about intrinsic properties allowed by some forms of transcendental idealism.

尽管胡塞尔现象学似乎要求实践者屏蔽所有形而上学的问题和主张,但这一要求与经验的证据相悖,因为在经验中,对象本身就是经验的构成要素。此外,完全摒弃形而上学的考虑会表明,现象学与它原则上应该否认的形而上学观点是相容的。然而,允许形而上学的主张就有可能违背现象学的批判限度,就有可能招致需要与我们的观点不同的观点来验证的主张。这些紧张关系提出了一个重要的问题,即 "对象本身是经验的构成要素 "这一现象学直观主张的形而上学含义是什么?为了回答这个问题,我借鉴了关于超验唯心主义和现象学的大量思想。我认为,在胡塞尔现象学的批判限度内,适度的表象形而上学是有道理的。通过讨论和解决通常困扰超验论证的问题,我表明胡塞尔现象学允许对经验对象提出比通缩论更强的主张,但不允许某些形式的超验唯心主义所允许的对内在属性的主张。
{"title":"The critical limits of phenomenology: Husserlian phenomenology as a modest metaphysics of appearance","authors":"Emiliano Diaz","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12910","DOIUrl":"10.1111/ejop.12910","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Although Husserlian phenomenology appears to require that practitioners bracket all metaphysical questions and claims, this requirement runs against the evidence of experience in which objects themselves are presented as constituents of experience. Moreover, to completely bracket metaphysical considerations would suggest that phenomenology is compatible with metaphysical views it should in principle deny. Nonetheless, permitting metaphysical claims threatens to contravene the critical limits of phenomenology, to invite claims that would require a perspective different in kind than our own to verify. These tensions raise an important question, namely, what are the metaphysical implications of the phenomenologically intuitive claim that objects themselves are constituents of experience? To answer this question, I draw on a broad swath of thought on transcendental idealism and phenomenology. I argue that a modest metaphysics of appearance is warranted within the critical limits of Husserlian phenomenology. Through discussing and addressing the problems that typically plague transcendental arguments, I show that Husserlian phenomenology permits stronger claims about objects of experience than deflationary accounts allow but does not permit claims about intrinsic properties allowed by some forms of transcendental idealism.</p>","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"32 3","pages":"778-800"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2023-11-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135432227","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Sex, truth, and law: Rereading Foucault's History of Sexuality after volume 4, The Confessions of the Flesh 性、真理与法律:重读福柯的《性史》第4卷《肉的自白》
IF 0.9 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-10-08 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12900
Tuomo Tiisala
<p>Foucault's historical studies were motivated by problems he identified in the present and there is no reason to think that <i>History of Sexuality</i> is different in this regard.<sup>1</sup> But that raises a question no reader of <i>The Confessions of the Flesh</i> can escape: How is a scholarly 426-page treatise on the Church Fathers relevant to the contemporary world, or, at least, to concerns that emerged from Foucault's own historical present?<sup>2</sup> The question is only highlighted by the absence of explicit links between the past and the present in Foucault's text, which was published posthumously, in 2018, as the fourth and final volume of <i>History of Sexuality</i>. This book had been advertised as forthcoming already in 1984, when volumes 2 and 3 were published weeks before Foucault's death.<sup>3</sup> Therefore, it is hardly an exaggeration to say that only now, in light of the perspective the long-awaited final volume offers, are we in a position to assess Foucault's <i>History of Sexuality</i> project as a whole. At the same time, this broader context is vital for understanding the philosophical significance of volume 4, which remains, no doubt due to its unfinished state, strikingly silent about the <i>philosophical</i> aim of the meticulous historical work, as Foucault himself understood it. Therefore, the question of contemporary significance needs to be examined both with respect to the project overall and, specifically, by asking what role the analyses of baptism, repentance, libido, virginity, and marriage, which fill out volume 4, might play in it.</p><p>Foucault's <i>History of Sexuality</i> is <i>critical</i> history in Nietzsche's (<span>1997</span>: 75-77) sense of using history to liberate us from elements of the past that continue to define the present. It is well known that, according to Foucault, the genealogical aim of critical work is to enlarge the scope of discursive possibility that sets limits to the work of freedom subjects can undertake. Such critique might be characterized as “the critique of constitution,” because it undertakes to investigate how the given limits of intelligibility have been constituted in order to destabilize their apparent inevitability (Säynäjoki & Tiisala, <span>2023</span>). It is not difficult to recognize this orientation in Foucault's <i>History of Sexuality</i>, which studies how sexual relations have been constituted as a topic of ethical significance, not always and everywhere, but in the history of Western culture, through a series of different problematizations. In short, Foucault asks, how is sex constituted as a topic of ethics <i>for us</i>? And, relatedly, how is the subject constituted as an ethical subject of sexual desire?</p><p>Foucault identifies three historically successive problematizations that constitute different ethical experiences of sexual relations, including the self's relation to itself: (1) the problem of the use of pleasures (sexual and other
在堕落之前,亚当服从上帝的意志,就像亚当的阴茎在他自己的自愿控制之下一样。没有性欲。但当人类从善与恶的知识之树中进食时,这条指挥链被打破了。在接下来的罪恶困境中,人类被性欲所困扰,这是一种惩罚,同时也是对最初不服从行为的提醒。通过违背亚当的意愿勃起,他的阴茎再现了人类违背上帝意愿的行为。因此,当邪恶通过违背上帝意愿进入世界时,性欲成为一个道德问题,因为它是邪恶的长期表现。尽管基督教性伦理的核心是消除邪恶,即救赎罪恶,但性欲并没有被消除,但人们需要找到一种与之共存的方式。福柯解释说,童贞和婚姻是两种确保救赎的伦理策略,但当然只有后者,可以随着时间的推移扩展到整个社会:“婚姻本质上是一种限制婚姻是一种方式,仅次于童贞,或者更确切地说,低于童贞,来规范纳妾问题,纳妾问题同样是婚姻道德的核心,也是那些拒绝一切婚姻关系的人的禁欲主义程序的核心。同意是婚姻地位规则和行使童贞技巧的共同目标。”(福柯,2018,第273页)。因此,婚姻是一种“救赎之谜”(福柯,2018,第278页),其中配偶的命运是通过对称的责任来协调的,以限制另一方的冲动。因此,婚姻制度为性关系作为一个伦理问题提供了法律解决方案。在现代生物政治背景下,将同性恋等性行为定为犯罪,根据精神病学理论,这些行为表现出对性本能的扭曲,这是这一法律策略的进一步发展。重要的是要认识到,在古老的性关系问题化中,就快乐的道德使用而言,真理也发挥着作用。因此,早期基督教中出现的是真理作为伦理经验元素的一个新角色。新颖性是双重的:它涉及自我作为自我认识对象的地位,以及寻求和说出关于自己的真相的义务。一方面,自我以一种脱离实际推理的方式被构成为自我认识的对象。新的不是自我认识本身在伦理上的重要性,而是这种转变更加具体。例如,在斯多葛道德心理学的精神练习中,也需要反思自己的思想、情感和欲望。福柯认为,改变的是,为了这个,一个人有义务审视自己的思想。反思的动机不再是灌输美德行为的倾向,而是从能动性中去除了这种动机。一个人有义务审视自己的思想,以揭示自己作为罪人的真相,从而放弃有罪的自我,并通过服从上帝的意志来寻求救赎。正如福柯在多伦多举行的“自我揭露的话语”课程第五讲中所解释的那样,这种自我揭露的任务需要一种新的方式来将自己作为自我认识的对象,1982年:“我想表明的是,自知之明原则上是一种控制真理获取和同化的程序。因此,它可以发挥永久的作用,发挥永久的功能。但这种自知之知并不构成真正话语中特定和自主的自我。它的任务不是发现我们所隐藏的现实。”。”(福柯,2017,第134页)。因此,根据福柯的说法,基督教带来的是一种自我概念,它是一种特定的、自主的话语对象,当被发现时,它揭示了一个人的隐藏现实,即一个罪人——在现代语境中,正如我们将看到的,一个犯罪者或变态者。另一方面,与此相关的是,基督教引入了自我检查和交流其结果的任务,作为一种新的工作类型,一个人需要作为一个伦理主体来承担。通过最初仅在修道院发展的忏悔实践,认识和实践的转变得到了协调和加强:自我作为解释学研究的对象,并对这一知识领域进行了持续的探索。因此,福柯认为,一种新形式的伦理主体性正在形成。从道德上讲,一个人需要将自己作为无休止调查的对象,其结果需要定期向权威人士报告。 “根据福柯在《肉的自白》中的分析,这不是在早期基督教的真理义务中产生的自我认识模式中定义自我与自身关系的思维模式吗?后来,在现代生物政治背景下,在正常性理论的基础上进行了阐述?只有在完成了《性史与肉的自白》之后,人们才能在福柯的总体论点中清楚地看到这一线索:即使我们已经失去了宗教信仰,基督教的传统仍然存在于我们在性关系中信奉恶意的倾向中。
{"title":"Sex, truth, and law: Rereading Foucault's History of Sexuality after volume 4, The Confessions of the Flesh","authors":"Tuomo Tiisala","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12900","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12900","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;p&gt;Foucault's historical studies were motivated by problems he identified in the present and there is no reason to think that &lt;i&gt;History of Sexuality&lt;/i&gt; is different in this regard.&lt;sup&gt;1&lt;/sup&gt; But that raises a question no reader of &lt;i&gt;The Confessions of the Flesh&lt;/i&gt; can escape: How is a scholarly 426-page treatise on the Church Fathers relevant to the contemporary world, or, at least, to concerns that emerged from Foucault's own historical present?&lt;sup&gt;2&lt;/sup&gt; The question is only highlighted by the absence of explicit links between the past and the present in Foucault's text, which was published posthumously, in 2018, as the fourth and final volume of &lt;i&gt;History of Sexuality&lt;/i&gt;. This book had been advertised as forthcoming already in 1984, when volumes 2 and 3 were published weeks before Foucault's death.&lt;sup&gt;3&lt;/sup&gt; Therefore, it is hardly an exaggeration to say that only now, in light of the perspective the long-awaited final volume offers, are we in a position to assess Foucault's &lt;i&gt;History of Sexuality&lt;/i&gt; project as a whole. At the same time, this broader context is vital for understanding the philosophical significance of volume 4, which remains, no doubt due to its unfinished state, strikingly silent about the &lt;i&gt;philosophical&lt;/i&gt; aim of the meticulous historical work, as Foucault himself understood it. Therefore, the question of contemporary significance needs to be examined both with respect to the project overall and, specifically, by asking what role the analyses of baptism, repentance, libido, virginity, and marriage, which fill out volume 4, might play in it.&lt;/p&gt;&lt;p&gt;Foucault's &lt;i&gt;History of Sexuality&lt;/i&gt; is &lt;i&gt;critical&lt;/i&gt; history in Nietzsche's (&lt;span&gt;1997&lt;/span&gt;: 75-77) sense of using history to liberate us from elements of the past that continue to define the present. It is well known that, according to Foucault, the genealogical aim of critical work is to enlarge the scope of discursive possibility that sets limits to the work of freedom subjects can undertake. Such critique might be characterized as “the critique of constitution,” because it undertakes to investigate how the given limits of intelligibility have been constituted in order to destabilize their apparent inevitability (Säynäjoki &amp; Tiisala, &lt;span&gt;2023&lt;/span&gt;). It is not difficult to recognize this orientation in Foucault's &lt;i&gt;History of Sexuality&lt;/i&gt;, which studies how sexual relations have been constituted as a topic of ethical significance, not always and everywhere, but in the history of Western culture, through a series of different problematizations. In short, Foucault asks, how is sex constituted as a topic of ethics &lt;i&gt;for us&lt;/i&gt;? And, relatedly, how is the subject constituted as an ethical subject of sexual desire?&lt;/p&gt;&lt;p&gt;Foucault identifies three historically successive problematizations that constitute different ethical experiences of sexual relations, including the self's relation to itself: (1) the problem of the use of pleasures (sexual and other","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"31 3","pages":"836-843"},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2023-10-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/ejop.12900","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"50125267","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Plurigenealogies: Marriage and address to women in Foucault's Confessions of the Flesh 多元性:福柯《肉的自白》中的婚姻与对女性的称呼
IF 0.9 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-10-08 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12899
Penelope Deutscher

How does the publication of Confessions of the Flesh impact feminist critique of Foucault's History of Sexuality project? The paper addresses this question in two ways: by asking how reflection on continuities and ruptures has, and can, be productive for feminist critique; and by revisiting the role of women in all four volumes. The terms of their inclusion have been considered an omission, particularly because the project omits same-sex eros between women. Where women appear, they are framed as spouses, or as subordinated to some form of authority. And yet, insofar as the project contains more than one genealogical dimension, Foucault's “marriages” also belong to proximate plurigenealogies. In Confession's focus on the conditions for a juridical and divided self's subjectivation by will and desire, even the limited parameters within which women appear in the project incite the following question. What are the implications of Confessions of the Flesh's juridical self for genealogies of female subjectivation?

《肉的自白》的出版对福柯性史项目的女权主义批判有何影响?本文通过两种方式来解决这个问题:通过询问对连续性和断裂性的反思如何对女权主义批判产生影响,以及如何能够产生影响;以及在所有四卷中重新审视妇女的作用。他们的加入条款被认为是一种遗漏,特别是因为该项目遗漏了女性之间的同性性爱。在女性出现的地方,她们被诬陷为配偶,或服从某种形式的权威。然而,只要该项目包含不止一个谱系维度,福柯的“婚姻”也属于接近的多谱系。在Confession对司法和分裂的自我通过意志和欲望进行主观化的条件的关注中,即使是女性在项目中出现的有限参数也引发了以下问题。《肉的法律自我的自白》对女性主观主义谱系的含义是什么?
{"title":"Plurigenealogies: Marriage and address to women in Foucault's Confessions of the Flesh","authors":"Penelope Deutscher","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12899","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12899","url":null,"abstract":"<p>How does the publication of <i>Confessions of the Flesh</i> impact feminist critique of Foucault's <i>History of Sexuality</i> project? The paper addresses this question in two ways: by asking how reflection on continuities and ruptures has, and can, be productive for feminist critique; and by revisiting the role of women in all four volumes. The terms of their inclusion have been considered an omission, particularly because the project omits same-sex eros between women. Where women appear, they are framed as spouses, or as subordinated to some form of authority. And yet, insofar as the project contains more than one genealogical dimension, Foucault's “marriages” also belong to proximate plurigenealogies. In Confession's focus on the conditions for a juridical and divided self's subjectivation by will and desire, even the limited parameters within which women appear in the project incite the following question. What are the implications of Confessions of the Flesh's juridical self for genealogies of female subjectivation?</p>","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"31 3","pages":"820-835"},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2023-10-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/ejop.12899","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"50125265","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Hello darkness my old friend: What is wrong with being friends with people with immoral beliefs? 你好,黑暗,我的老朋友:与信仰不道德的人做朋友有什么错?
IF 0.7 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-10-05 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12907
Jake Wagner

Many persons find it intuitive that being friends with someone with immoral beliefs is wrong as such. I contest this claim, instead I argue that there is nothing necessarily wrong with such friendships. In coming to this conclusion I examine a number of arguments, including two of the most notable contributions put forward by Mason (2021) and Isserow (2018), that attempt to elucidate the wrongness involved in such friendships and find they do not successfully do so. I conclude by offering some arguments as to why such friendships are not necessarily wrong.

许多人直觉地认为,与信仰不道德的人做朋友本身就是错误的。我对这种说法提出质疑,相反,我认为这种友谊并没有什么必然的错误。在得出这一结论的过程中,我研究了一些论点,包括梅森(2021 年)和伊瑟洛(2018 年)提出的两个最著名的论点,这些论点试图阐明这种友谊所涉及的错误性,但我发现它们并没有成功地做到这一点。最后,我将提出一些论据,说明为什么这种友谊不一定是错误的。
{"title":"Hello darkness my old friend: What is wrong with being friends with people with immoral beliefs?","authors":"Jake Wagner","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12907","DOIUrl":"10.1111/ejop.12907","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Many persons find it intuitive that being friends with someone with immoral beliefs is wrong as such. I contest this claim, instead I argue that there is nothing necessarily wrong with such friendships. In coming to this conclusion I examine a number of arguments, including two of the most notable contributions put forward by Mason (2021) and Isserow (2018), that attempt to elucidate the wrongness involved in such friendships and find they do not successfully do so. I conclude by offering some arguments as to why such friendships are not necessarily wrong.</p>","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"32 3","pages":"905-918"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2023-10-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135481733","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Critical Idealism as Method: Ernst Cassirer and the Philosophy of Symbolic Forms 作为方法的批判唯心主义恩斯特-卡西勒与符号形式哲学
IF 0.9 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-10-02 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12903
Esther Oluffa Pedersen

To commemorate the centenary of Ernst Cassirer's Philosophy of Symbolic Forms this essay focuses on how Cassirer in the development of a distinctive philosophical method analyzed the newest development within philosophy and science. Discussing Einstein's theory of relativity and Russell's formal logic Cassirer found tools to expand the critique of reason into a critique of culture. The course of argumentation is as follows. At the outset Cassirer's outline of the idea of The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms in the 1920 book Einstein's Theory of Relativity is presented as a reaction to the increasing distance between theoretical physics and ordinary experience. The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms can be read as an answer to an inner methodological demand within critical idealism. I encircle this motif in Cassirer's comment that Plato's idealism, understood as the dianoia of thought, is reiterated in Kant's transcendental philosophy and Herman Cohen's reception of Kant. This leads to a discussion of how Cassirer breaks away from Cohen by the positive reception of Russell's symbolic logic. Finally, I present the theory of functional concepts developed by Cassirer (1910) in the book Substance and Function as a prerequisite for the conception of a plural but systematic philosophy of symbolic forms.

为了纪念恩斯特·卡西尔的《符号形式哲学》诞生一百周年,本文着重探讨卡西尔如何以独特的哲学方法来分析哲学和科学的最新发展。通过讨论爱因斯坦的相对论和罗素的形式逻辑,卡西尔找到了将对理性的批判扩展到对文化的批判的工具。论证的过程如下。一开始,卡西尔在1920年出版的《爱因斯坦的相对论》一书中概述了符号形式哲学的思想,这是对理论物理学与日常经验之间日益增长的距离的一种反应。《象征形式哲学》可以被解读为对批判唯心主义内部方法论需求的回答。我在卡西尔的评论中围绕着这个主题,柏拉图的唯心主义,被理解为思想的癫狂,在康德的先验哲学和赫尔曼·科恩对康德的接受中得到了重申。这导致了卡西尔如何通过积极接受罗素的符号逻辑而脱离科恩的讨论。最后,我提出了卡西尔(1910)在《物质与功能》一书中提出的功能概念理论,作为多元但系统的符号形式哲学概念的先决条件。
{"title":"Critical Idealism as Method: Ernst Cassirer and the Philosophy of Symbolic Forms","authors":"Esther Oluffa Pedersen","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12903","DOIUrl":"10.1111/ejop.12903","url":null,"abstract":"<p>To commemorate the centenary of Ernst Cassirer's <i>Philosophy of Symbolic Forms</i> this essay focuses on how Cassirer in the development of a distinctive philosophical method analyzed the newest development within philosophy and science. Discussing Einstein's theory of relativity and Russell's formal logic Cassirer found tools to expand the critique of reason into a critique of culture. The course of argumentation is as follows. At the outset Cassirer's outline of the idea of <i>The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms</i> in the 1920 book <i>Einstein's Theory of Relativity</i> is presented as a reaction to the increasing distance between theoretical physics and ordinary experience. <i>The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms</i> can be read as an answer to an inner methodological demand within critical idealism. I encircle this motif in Cassirer's comment that Plato's idealism, understood as the <i>dianoia</i> of thought, is reiterated in Kant's transcendental philosophy and Herman Cohen's reception of Kant. This leads to a discussion of how Cassirer breaks away from Cohen by the positive reception of Russell's symbolic logic. Finally, I present the theory of functional concepts developed by Cassirer (1910) in the book <i>Substance and Function</i> as a prerequisite for the conception of a plural but systematic philosophy of symbolic forms.</p>","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"31 4","pages":"1105-1114"},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2023-10-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/ejop.12903","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135830222","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Carnap and the a priori 卡尔纳普与先验论
IF 0.7 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-26 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12906
Benjamin Marschall

What are Carnap's views on the epistemology of mathematics? Did he believe in a priori justification, and if so, what is his account of it? One might think that such questions are misguided, since in the 1930s Carnap came to reject traditional epistemology as a confused mixture of logic and psychology. But things are not that simple. Drawing on recent work by Richardson and Uebel, I will show that Carnap's mature metaphilosophy leaves room for two distinct notions of a priori justification: one propositional, the other doxastic. The latter is especially interesting since it comes closest to a traditional understanding of a priority. On the other hand, Carnap has little to say about doxastic justification in his writings. This lacuna can be filled by drawing on an unpublished exchange with Irving M. Copi. In it, so I will show, Carnap endorses the view that agents can come to know all mathematical truths a priori. This fact, so I will further argue, can be used to adjudicate a dispute between Ricketts and Friedman about the nature and viability of Carnap's philosophy of mathematics—specifically his reliance on infinitary methods.

卡尔纳普对数学认识论有什么看法?他是否相信先验的合理性?人们可能会认为这些问题是误导,因为在 20 世纪 30 年代,卡尔纳普开始反对传统的认识论,认为它是逻辑学和心理学的混乱混合物。但事情并非如此简单。我将借鉴理查森和乌贝尔的最新研究成果,说明卡尔纳普成熟的形而上学为两种不同的先验正当性概念留出了空间:一种是命题的,另一种是逻各斯的。后者尤其有趣,因为它最接近于对优先权的传统理解。另一方面,卡尔纳普在他的著作中却很少谈及逻各斯的正当性。这一空白可以通过与欧文-科皮(Irving M. Copi)未发表的交流来填补。我将在文中指出,卡尔纳普赞同代理人可以先验地知道所有数学真理的观点。我将进一步论证,这一事实可以用来裁决里基茨和弗里德曼之间关于卡尔纳普数学哲学--特别是他对无限方法的依赖--的性质和可行性的争论。
{"title":"Carnap and the a priori","authors":"Benjamin Marschall","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12906","DOIUrl":"10.1111/ejop.12906","url":null,"abstract":"<p>What are Carnap's views on the epistemology of mathematics? Did he believe in a priori justification, and if so, what is his account of it? One might think that such questions are misguided, since in the 1930s Carnap came to reject traditional epistemology as a confused mixture of logic and psychology. But things are not that simple. Drawing on recent work by Richardson and Uebel, I will show that Carnap's mature metaphilosophy leaves room for two distinct notions of a priori justification: one <i>propositional</i>, the other <i>doxastic</i>. The latter is especially interesting since it comes closest to a traditional understanding of a priority. On the other hand, Carnap has little to say about doxastic justification in his writings. This lacuna can be filled by drawing on an unpublished exchange with Irving M. Copi. In it, so I will show, Carnap endorses the view that agents can come to know all mathematical truths a priori. This fact, so I will further argue, can be used to adjudicate a dispute between Ricketts and Friedman about the nature and viability of Carnap's philosophy of mathematics—specifically his reliance on infinitary methods.</p>","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"32 3","pages":"801-819"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2023-09-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/ejop.12906","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"134885535","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Reflections on the concept of institution 关于制度概念的思考
IF 0.9 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-21 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12896
Vincent Descombes
{"title":"Reflections on the concept of institution","authors":"Vincent Descombes","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12896","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12896","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"31 3","pages":"549-562"},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2023-09-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"50153185","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Veridiction and juridiction in Confessions of the Flesh 《肉的自白》中的确证与裁判
IF 0.9 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2023-09-21 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12901
Niki Kasumi Clements

In an archived draft at the Bibliothèque nationale de France, Foucault describes two questions haunting him since 1963: “Why are we obliged to tell the truth about ourselves? Which truth?” Foucault poses these two questions in 1980 in drafts for his lectures at the University of California, Berkeley, and I see in these two questions two argumentative threads that weave through Foucault's changing History of Sexuality series over his last decade. These two threads correspond to the dimorphism Foucault frames in Part III of Confessions of the Flesh between confessing monks and married men, that correlates with the distinction between “veridiction” and “juridiction” as two forms relating subjectivity and sexuality. To help tease out these threads, I make two recommendations for how to read Confessions of the Flesh in this following review essay: (1) situate Confessions of the Flesh in relation to Foucault's History of Sexuality series which spans his last decade from 1974 to 1984 and (2) untangle two major threads of Confessions of the Flesh in Foucault's treatment of Cassian and Augustine, as progenitors of veridiction and juridiction respectively, which together produce the conditions for modern disciplinary subjects.

在法国国家图书馆的一份存档草稿中,福柯描述了自1963年以来困扰他的两个问题:“为什么我们必须说出关于自己的真相?哪个真相?”1980年,福柯在加州大学伯克利分校的演讲草稿中提出了这两个问题,在这两个问题中,我看到了福柯在过去十年中不断变化的《性史》系列中的两条争论线索。这两条线索对应了福柯在《肉的自白》第三部分中对忏悔僧侣和已婚男子的二态性框架,这与“真理”和“司法”作为主体性和性的两种形式之间的区别有关。为了梳理这些线索,我在下面的评论文章中对如何阅读《肉的自白》提出了两个建议:(1)将《肉的自白》与福柯的《性史》系列联系起来,该系列跨越了福柯从1974年到1984年的最后十年,分别作为真理论和法学的先驱,共同创造了现代学科主体的条件。
{"title":"Veridiction and juridiction in Confessions of the Flesh","authors":"Niki Kasumi Clements","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12901","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12901","url":null,"abstract":"<p>In an archived draft at the Bibliothèque nationale de France, Foucault describes two questions haunting him since 1963: “Why are we obliged to tell the truth about ourselves? Which truth?” Foucault poses these two questions in 1980 in drafts for his lectures at the University of California, Berkeley, and I see in these two questions two argumentative threads that weave through Foucault's changing <i>History of Sexuality</i> series over his last decade. These two threads correspond to the dimorphism Foucault frames in Part III of <i>Confessions of the Flesh</i> between confessing monks and married men, that correlates with the distinction between “veridiction” and “juridiction” as two forms relating subjectivity and sexuality. To help tease out these threads, I make two recommendations for how to read <i>Confessions of the Flesh</i> in this following review essay: (1) situate <i>Confessions of the Flesh</i> in relation to Foucault's <i>History of Sexuality</i> series which spans his last decade from 1974 to 1984 and (2) untangle two major threads of <i>Confessions of the Flesh</i> in Foucault's treatment of Cassian and Augustine, as progenitors of veridiction and juridiction respectively, which together produce the conditions for modern disciplinary subjects.</p>","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"31 3","pages":"809-819"},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2023-09-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"50153186","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1