首页 > 最新文献

EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY最新文献

英文 中文
Obscure representations from a pragmatic point of view 从实用角度看晦涩难懂的表述
IF 0.9 2区 哲学 N/A PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-07-05 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12986
Francey Russell
Kant's most sustained discussion of obscure representations can be found in the first book of his Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View. What is puzzling is that in the middle of the section devoted to the topic, Kant asserts that “because this field can only be perceived in his passive side as a play of sensations, the theory of obscure representations belongs only to physiological anthropology, and so it is properly disregarded here.” So, do obscure representations belong to pragmatic anthropology or not? Kant's official position is that they do not, yet the textual evidence—we find discussions of obscure representations in 20 years of his work on pragmatic anthropology—suggests that they do, in fact, belong here. Most of the literature on obscure representations focuses on their contribution to cognition and none has clarified what it would mean to assume a “pragmatic point of view” on obscure representations, and to study them in the context of pragmatic anthropology. My aim in this paper is to provide such clarification, focusing on Kant's discussion of our propensity to “play with” obscure representations and what he calls our “art of obscuring.”
康德对朦胧表象最持久的论述见于他的《从实用主义观点看人类学》第一卷。令人费解的是,在专门讨论这一主题的章节中间,康德断言:"由于这一领域只能在他被动的一面作为感觉的游戏而被感知,朦胧表象的理论只属于生理学人类学,因此在这里被适当地忽略了。那么,朦胧表象到底属不属于实用人类学呢?康德的官方立场是不属于,然而文本证据--我们在他 20 年的实用人类学著作中发现了关于朦胧表象的讨论--表明朦胧表象实际上属于这里。大多数关于晦涩表象的文献都集中在它们对认知的贡献上,却没有一篇阐明对晦涩表象采取 "语用学观点 "并在语用人类学的语境中研究它们意味着什么。我在本文中的目的就是提供这样的澄清,重点讨论康德关于我们 "玩弄 "晦涩表象的倾向以及他所说的我们的 "晦涩艺术"。
{"title":"Obscure representations from a pragmatic point of view","authors":"Francey Russell","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12986","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12986","url":null,"abstract":"Kant's most sustained discussion of obscure representations can be found in the first book of his <jats:italic>Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View</jats:italic>. What is puzzling is that in the middle of the section devoted to the topic, Kant asserts that “because this field can only be perceived in his passive side as a play of sensations, the theory of obscure representations belongs only to physiological anthropology, and so it is properly disregarded here.” So, do obscure representations belong to pragmatic anthropology or not? Kant's official position is that they do not, yet the textual evidence—we find discussions of obscure representations in 20 years of his work on pragmatic anthropology—suggests that they do, in fact, belong here. Most of the literature on obscure representations focuses on their contribution to cognition and none has clarified what it would mean to assume a “pragmatic point of view” on obscure representations, and to study them in the context of pragmatic anthropology. My aim in this paper is to provide such clarification, focusing on Kant's discussion of our propensity to “play with” obscure representations and what he calls our “art of obscuring.”","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2024-07-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141574825","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The generality problem of perception 感知的普遍性问题
IF 0.9 2区 哲学 N/A PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-07-05 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12984
Farid Zahnoun, Luca Roccioletti, Erik Myin
Much of contemporary philosophy of perception revolves around the question of whether perceptual experience has representational content. On one side of the debate, we find representationalists claiming that perceptual experience is representational in that it always presents the world as being a certain way. Perceptual experience is therefore said to have content, which can be evaluated for truth or accuracy. Against the idea that perception has content, relationalists have leveled an argument based on the generality of content, which we shall here refer to as the generality problem of perception (GPP). We will analyze and assess existing replies to the GPP. Based on these analyses, we will conclude that representationalists have as yet not offered a convincing answer to the problem and that, after almost 20 years, the problem still stands.
当代知觉哲学的大部分内容都围绕着知觉经验是否具有表征内容这一问题展开。在争论的一方,我们发现表象主义者声称知觉经验是表象的,因为它总是以某种方式呈现世界。因此,知觉经验被认为是有内容的,可以对其真实性或准确性进行评估。针对知觉具有内容这一观点,关系主义者提出了一个基于内容普遍性的论点,我们在此称之为知觉的普遍性问题(GPP)。我们将分析和评估现有的对 GPP 的答复。在这些分析的基础上,我们将得出结论:表象主义者至今尚未对这一问题给出令人信服的答案,而且在将近 20 年之后,这一问题依然存在。
{"title":"The generality problem of perception","authors":"Farid Zahnoun, Luca Roccioletti, Erik Myin","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12984","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12984","url":null,"abstract":"Much of contemporary philosophy of perception revolves around the question of whether perceptual experience has representational content. On one side of the debate, we find representationalists claiming that perceptual experience is representational in that it always presents the world as being a certain way. Perceptual experience is therefore said to have content, which can be evaluated for truth or accuracy. Against the idea that perception has content, relationalists have leveled an argument based on the generality of content, which we shall here refer to as the generality problem of perception (GPP). We will analyze and assess existing replies to the GPP. Based on these analyses, we will conclude that representationalists have as yet not offered a convincing answer to the problem and that, after almost 20 years, the problem still stands.","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2024-07-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141574822","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Kantian origin of Adorno's concept of metaphysical experience 阿多诺形而上学经验概念的康德起源
IF 0.9 2区 哲学 N/A PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-07-05 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12985
Farshid Baghai
Metaphysical experience is one of the most obscure concepts in Adorno's Negative Dialectics. The obscurity stems partly from the way in which metaphysical experience is antinomic. To describe the antinomic character of metaphysical experience, Adorno situates it in relation to Kant's first Critique. He distinguishes two conceptions of antinomy in the first Critique: first, the explicit conception of antinomy that the transcendental dialectic exposes and resolves; and second, the implicit conception of antinomy that remains insoluble and structures the first Critique and Adorno's own concept of metaphysical experience. Yet Adorno does not clarify what he means by the antinomic structure of the first Critique and how this structure underlies his own concept of metaphysical experience. Nor does the scholarship on Adorno. This article reconstructs Adorno's response to these questions, and, in so doing, demonstrates the Kantian origin of Adorno's concept of metaphysical experience in Negative Dialectics.
形而上学经验是阿多诺《否定辩证法》中最晦涩难懂的概念之一。这种晦涩部分源于形而上学经验的反原子方式。为了描述形而上学经验的反二元性,阿多诺将其与康德的第一次批判联系起来。他区分了第一批判中的两种反传统概念:第一种是超越论辩证法所揭露和解决的显性反传统概念;第二种是仍然无法解决的隐性反传统概念,它构建了第一批判和阿多诺自己的形而上学经验概念。然而,阿多诺并没有阐明他所说的第一批判的反二元结构是什么意思,以及这种结构是如何支撑他自己的形而上学经验观的。关于阿多诺的学术研究也是如此。本文重构了阿多诺对这些问题的回答,并以此证明了阿多诺在《否定辩证法》中形而上学经验概念的康德渊源。
{"title":"The Kantian origin of Adorno's concept of metaphysical experience","authors":"Farshid Baghai","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12985","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12985","url":null,"abstract":"Metaphysical experience is one of the most obscure concepts in Adorno's <jats:italic>Negative Dialectics</jats:italic>. The obscurity stems partly from the way in which metaphysical experience is antinomic. To describe the antinomic character of metaphysical experience, Adorno situates it in relation to Kant's first <jats:italic>Critique</jats:italic>. He distinguishes two conceptions of antinomy in the first <jats:italic>Critique</jats:italic>: first, the explicit conception of antinomy that the transcendental dialectic exposes and resolves; and second, the implicit conception of antinomy that remains insoluble and structures the first <jats:italic>Critique</jats:italic> and Adorno's own concept of metaphysical experience. Yet Adorno does not clarify what he means by the antinomic structure of the first <jats:italic>Critique</jats:italic> and how this structure underlies his own concept of metaphysical experience. Nor does the scholarship on Adorno. This article reconstructs Adorno's response to these questions, and, in so doing, demonstrates the Kantian origin of Adorno's concept of metaphysical experience in <jats:italic>Negative Dialectics</jats:italic>.","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2024-07-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141574823","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Who are Nietzsche's slaves? 谁是尼采的奴隶?
IF 0.9 2区 哲学 N/A PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-07-05 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12979
Ken Gemes
This paper argues that Nietzsche is deliberately imprecise in his characterization of what he calls the slave revolt in morality. In particular, none of the people or groups he nominates as instigators of the slave revolt, namely, Jewish priests, the Jewish people, the prophets, Jesus, and Paul, were literally slaves. Analysis of Nietzsche's texts, including his usage of the term “slaves,” and his sources concerning those he nominates as the instigators of the slave revolt, make clear that Nietzsche knew none of these were literally slaves. He calls it a slave revolt because he means that the propagators of that revolt preached what he takes to be the slavish values, including, humility, compassion, obedience, and lack of egoism. He uses the high loaded term “slave” both to disparage those values and, most importantly, to bring home to his readers the message that they, as inheritors of Judeo‐Christian values, actual adhere to and practice the debased slavish values preached, but not necessarily practiced, by the original instigators of the slave revolt. For Nietzsche, his readers are strangers to themselves, thus he notes “slavery is everywhere visible, although it does not call itself as such.”
本文认为,尼采在描述他所谓的道德奴隶起义时故意不够精确。特别是,他所提到的奴隶起义的煽动者,即犹太祭司、犹太人、先知、耶稣和保罗,没有一个人或群体是真正的奴隶。分析尼采的文本,包括他对 "奴隶 "一词的用法,以及他提名的奴隶起义煽动者的资料来源,可以清楚地看出,尼采知道这些人都不是真正的奴隶。他之所以称之为奴隶起义,是因为他的意思是,起义的宣传者宣扬他所认为的奴性价值观,包括谦卑、同情、服从和缺乏利己主义。他用 "奴隶 "这个高大上的词来贬低这些价值观,最重要的是,他要让读者明白,他们作为犹太教-基督教价值观的继承者,实际遵守并践行的是奴隶起义最初的煽动者所宣扬的、但不一定践行的低劣的奴性价值观。对尼采来说,他的读者对自己是陌生的,因此他指出:"奴隶制随处可见,尽管它并不自称为奴隶制"。
{"title":"Who are Nietzsche's slaves?","authors":"Ken Gemes","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12979","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12979","url":null,"abstract":"This paper argues that Nietzsche is deliberately imprecise in his characterization of what he calls the slave revolt in morality. In particular, none of the people or groups he nominates as instigators of the slave revolt, namely, Jewish priests, the Jewish people, the prophets, Jesus, and Paul, were literally slaves. Analysis of Nietzsche's texts, including his usage of the term “slaves,” and his sources concerning those he nominates as the instigators of the slave revolt, make clear that Nietzsche knew none of these were literally slaves. He calls it a slave revolt because he means that the propagators of that revolt preached what he takes to be the slavish values, including, humility, compassion, obedience, and lack of egoism. He uses the high loaded term “slave” both to disparage those values and, most importantly, to bring home to his readers the message that they, as inheritors of Judeo‐Christian values, actual adhere to and practice the debased slavish values preached, but not necessarily practiced, by the original instigators of the slave revolt. For Nietzsche, his readers are strangers to themselves, thus he notes “slavery is everywhere visible, although it does not call itself as such.”","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2024-07-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141574981","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Modalization and demodalization: On the phenomenology of negation 模态化和去模态化:论否定的现象学
IF 0.9 2区 哲学 N/A PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-07-04 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12983
Kyle Banick
Negation is widely thought to be uniquely captured by the usual extensional Boolean connective in the setting of classical logic. However, there has been recent interest in a modal approach to negation. This essay examines the problem of modal negation with an Husserlian phenomenological lens. I argue that the Husserlian approach to negation contains an ambiguity which points to a pluralism about negation. On this view, negation begins its life as a modal notion with nonclassical properties, and the question of classical negation is a question of its demodalization. I reconstruct a phenomenological legitimation of the demodalization, but I remain skeptical about its wider prospects. Nevertheless, the phenomenological‐modal approach to negation answers the skepticism about the very possibility of debates about negation and gives valuable insight into the fundamental nature of the problem. The argument should be of interest both to those who are specifically interested in Husserl's logic and the relationship of phenomenology to intuitionistic (and other nonclassical) logics, as well as to philosophers of logic more generally interested in obtaining different angles on the problem of negation from a systematic perspective.
人们普遍认为,在经典逻辑中,通常的扩展布尔连接词可以唯一地捕捉否定。然而,最近人们对否定的模态方法产生了兴趣。本文从胡塞尔现象学的视角来探讨模态否定问题。我认为胡塞尔的 "否定 "方法包含一种模棱两可的东西,它指向否定的多元论。根据这种观点,否定一开始就是一个具有非经典属性的模态概念,而经典否定的问题就是它的去模态化问题。我重建了去模态化的现象学合法性,但对其更广阔的前景仍持怀疑态度。不过,对否定的现象学模式方法回答了对否定辩论可能性本身的怀疑,并对问题的根本性质提出了有价值的见解。无论是对胡塞尔的逻辑学和现象学与直觉主义(及其他非经典)逻辑学的关系特别感兴趣的人,还是对希望从系统的角度获得关于否定问题的不同视角的逻辑哲学家,都应该对这一论证感兴趣。
{"title":"Modalization and demodalization: On the phenomenology of negation","authors":"Kyle Banick","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12983","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12983","url":null,"abstract":"Negation is widely thought to be uniquely captured by the usual extensional Boolean connective in the setting of classical logic. However, there has been recent interest in a <jats:italic>modal</jats:italic> approach to negation. This essay examines the problem of modal negation with an Husserlian phenomenological lens. I argue that the Husserlian approach to negation contains an ambiguity which points to a pluralism about negation. On this view, negation begins its life as a modal notion with nonclassical properties, and the question of classical negation is a question of its demodalization. I reconstruct a phenomenological legitimation of the demodalization, but I remain skeptical about its wider prospects. Nevertheless, the phenomenological‐modal approach to negation answers the skepticism about the very possibility of debates about negation and gives valuable insight into the fundamental nature of the problem. The argument should be of interest both to those who are specifically interested in Husserl's logic and the relationship of phenomenology to intuitionistic (and other nonclassical) logics, as well as to philosophers of logic more generally interested in obtaining different angles on the problem of negation from a systematic perspective.","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2024-07-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141550864","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Acting as causing change 作为引起变化的行为
IF 0.7 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-07-02 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12973
Maria Alvarez

The paper defends a version of the view that agency is a causal power, the “causing view.” After sketching the view, and explaining how it differs from its rivals, various challenges are assessed. A family of objections says that causing change is neither necessary nor sufficient for acting. The second challenge centers on an Aristotelian thesis about the relation between an action (A's opening a window) and the corresponding passion (the window's being opened by A). The final objection concerns the dynamic nature of acting: the claim is that a causal view of agency cannot accommodate actions “in progress” or mere activity. I conclude that none of the objections examined presents unsurmountable problems for the causal view of agency which, at least in the version here defended, remains a highly plausible and attractive view.

本文为 "代理是一种因果力量 "这一观点的一个版本--"导致观点"--进行了辩护。在概述了这一观点并解释了它与其竞争对手的区别之后,对各种挑战进行了评估。一系列反对意见认为,引起变化既不是行动的必要条件,也不是充分条件。第二个质疑集中在亚里士多德关于行动(A 打开窗户)与相应的激情(窗户被 A 打开)之间关系的论断。最后一个反对意见涉及行动的动态性质:其主张是,关于代理的因果观点无法容纳 "进行中 "的行动或单纯的活动。我的结论是,所研究的反对意见都没有给代理的因果观带来不可克服的问题,至少在本文所辩护的版本中,代理的因果观仍然是一个非常合理和有吸引力的观点。
{"title":"Acting as causing change","authors":"Maria Alvarez","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12973","DOIUrl":"10.1111/ejop.12973","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The paper defends a version of the view that agency is a causal power, the “causing view.” After sketching the view, and explaining how it differs from its rivals, various challenges are assessed. A family of objections says that causing change is neither necessary nor sufficient for acting. The second challenge centers on an Aristotelian thesis about the relation between an action (A's opening a window) and the corresponding passion (the window's being opened by A). The final objection concerns the dynamic nature of acting: the claim is that a causal view of agency cannot accommodate actions “in progress” or mere activity. I conclude that none of the objections examined presents unsurmountable problems for the causal view of agency which, at least in the version here defended, remains a highly plausible and attractive view.</p>","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-07-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/ejop.12973","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141550877","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
How to decide what to do: Why you're already a realist about value 如何决定做什么为什么你已经是价值现实主义者?
IF 0.7 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-06-18 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12977
Claire Kirwin

Metaethical realists and anti-realists alike have typically assumed that deliberation about what to do is, at least sometimes, properly settled by the agent's evaluative attitudes—what she wants, likes, or values—rather than by any objective source of value out in the world. I argue that this picture of deliberation is not one that the deliberating agent herself can accept. Seen from within the first-person perspective, the agent's own evaluative attitudes are not encountered as descriptive psychological facts, but are rather “transparent” to the external world, conceived as a place already suffused with normative significance: they are her finding the relevant parts of the world to be desirable, valuable, and so on. And from the agent's own point of view, these attitudes can do the normative work involved in settling deliberation only because and insofar as they are understood as in this way a warranted response to this desirability or value. Attitudes that the agent does not experience as transparent in this way are attitudes from which she is alienated, and as such she cannot understand them as authoritative over her deliberation. What this means, I argue, is that deliberation about what to do involves a commitment to a particularly substantive form of metaethical realism.

元伦理学的现实主义者和反现实主义者通常都假定,关于做什么的商议,至少有时是由行为者的评价态度--她想要什么、喜欢什么或看重什么--而不是由世界上任何客观的价值来源来解决的。我认为,这种慎思的图景并不是慎思者本身所能接受的。从第一人称视角来看,代理人自己的评价态度并不是作为描述性的心理事实出现的,而是对外部世界 "透明 "的,被视为一个已经充满了规范意义的地方:它们是她发现世界的相关部分是可取的、有价值的等等。而从行为者自身的角度来看,这些态度之所以能够完成解决商议所涉及的规范性工作,只是因为它们被理解为以这种方式对这种可取性或价值做出的有正当理由的回应。行为主体没有体验到以这种方式透明的态度是她所疏远的态度,因此,她不能将这些态度理解为对她的商议具有权威性。我认为,这就意味着,关于做什么的深思熟虑涉及到对一种特别实质性的元伦理现实主义的承诺。
{"title":"How to decide what to do: Why you're already a realist about value","authors":"Claire Kirwin","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12977","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12977","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Metaethical realists and anti-realists alike have typically assumed that deliberation about what to do is, at least sometimes, properly settled by the agent's evaluative attitudes—what she wants, likes, or values—rather than by any objective source of value out in the world. I argue that this picture of deliberation is not one that the deliberating agent herself can accept. Seen from within the first-person perspective, the agent's own evaluative attitudes are not encountered as descriptive psychological facts, but are rather “transparent” to the external world, conceived as a place already suffused with normative significance: they are her finding the relevant parts of the world to be desirable, valuable, and so on. And from the agent's own point of view, these attitudes can do the normative work involved in settling deliberation only because and insofar as they are understood as in this way a warranted response to this desirability or value. Attitudes that the agent does not experience as transparent in this way are attitudes from which she is alienated, and as such she cannot understand them as authoritative over her deliberation. What this means, I argue, is that deliberation about what to do involves a commitment to a particularly substantive form of metaethical realism.</p>","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-06-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/ejop.12977","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142404841","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A project of “impure” enquiry—Williams' historical self-consciousness 一个 "不纯粹 "的探究项目--威廉斯的历史自我意识
IF 0.9 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-06-18 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12981
Miranda Fricker

Bernard Williams’ philosophy is shaped by a distinctive and abiding interest in the borderlands between Philosophy and History. He famously considers moral philosophy, and particularly moral theory, to over-step the border that marks the real ‘limits’ of the discipline, and in his later work he explicitly advances the idea of doing ‘impure’ philosophy, by which he meant philosophy that mixed itself with history. By examining the complex impression left on Williams’ historical self-consciousness by his engagements with two very different figures in the history of philosophy, namely Descartes and Wittgenstein, I will explore a number of ways in which philosophy and history are closely intertwined for Williams. This will draw out the positive vision he modelled for us of ‘impure’ philosophy—a philosophical style he took to contribute to nurturing philosophy as a humanistic discipline.

伯纳德-威廉斯的哲学以其对哲学与历史之间边界的独特而持久的兴趣而形成。他认为道德哲学,尤其是道德理论,逾越了标志着该学科真正 "界限 "的边界,并在其晚期著作中明确提出了 "不纯粹 "哲学的观点,他指的是将自身与历史混为一谈的哲学。通过研究威廉斯与哲学史上两位截然不同的人物(即笛卡尔和维特根斯坦)的交往给他的历史自我意识留下的复杂印象,我将探讨哲学与历史在威廉斯看来是如何紧密交织在一起的。这将勾勒出他为我们塑造的 "不纯粹 "哲学的积极愿景--他认为这种哲学风格有助于将哲学培育成一门人文主义学科。
{"title":"A project of “impure” enquiry—Williams' historical self-consciousness","authors":"Miranda Fricker","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12981","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12981","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Bernard Williams’ philosophy is shaped by a distinctive and abiding interest in the borderlands between Philosophy and History. He famously considers moral philosophy, and particularly moral theory, to over-step the border that marks the real ‘limits’ of the discipline, and in his later work he explicitly advances the idea of doing ‘impure’ philosophy, by which he meant philosophy that mixed itself with history. By examining the complex impression left on Williams’ historical self-consciousness by his engagements with two very different figures in the history of philosophy, namely Descartes and Wittgenstein, I will explore a number of ways in which philosophy and history are closely intertwined for Williams. This will draw out the positive vision he modelled for us of ‘impure’ philosophy—a philosophical style he took to contribute to nurturing philosophy as a humanistic discipline.</p>","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2024-06-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141424929","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Vindicating universalism: Pragmatic genealogy and moral progress 平反普遍主义:实用主义谱系与道德进步
IF 0.9 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-06-12 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12975
C. Blunden, Benedict Lane
How do we justify the normative standards to which we appeal in support of our moral progress judgments, given their historical and cultural contingency? To answer this question in a noncircular way, Elizabeth Anderson and Philip Kitcher appeal exclusively to formal features of the methodology by which a moral change was brought about; some moral methodologies are systematically less prone to bias than others and are therefore less vulnerable to error. However, we argue that the methodologies espoused by Anderson and Kitcher implicitly appeal to the substantive principle of “moral universalism.” This sets up the positive project of the paper: an attempt to vindicate moral universalism with a pragmatic genealogy. Using resources from cultural evolutionary theory and the history of ideas we argue that the universalistic norms widely committed to in many societies today have the function of maintaining cooperation in large anonymous groups. Furthermore, while universalistic norms play this instrumental role, their functional benefits are best secured when people following such norms do so for intrinsic rather than instrumental reasons. Finally, having elaborated our pragmatic genealogy, we close by considering how this genealogy should affect our commitment to moral universalism and how it can complement the methods of Anderson and Kitcher.
鉴于历史和文化的偶然性,我们如何证明我们为支持道德进步判断而诉诸的规范性标准是合理的?为了非循环地回答这个问题,伊丽莎白-安德森(Elizabeth Anderson)和菲利普-基彻(Philip Kitcher)完全诉诸于促成道德变革的方法论的形式特征;有些道德方法论在系统上比其他方法论更不容易出现偏差,因此也更不容易出错。然而,我们认为,安德森和基彻所信奉的方法论隐含着对 "道德普遍主义 "这一实质性原则的诉求。这就提出了本文的积极课题:尝试用实用主义谱系来为道德普遍主义辩护。利用文化进化论和思想史的资源,我们论证了当今许多社会广泛承诺的普遍主义规范具有维持大型匿名群体合作的功能。此外,尽管普遍主义准则发挥着这种工具性作用,但当人们出于内在而非工具性的原因而遵守这些准则时,它们的功能性益处才能得到最好的保障。最后,在阐述了我们的实用主义谱系之后,我们最后考虑了这一谱系应该如何影响我们对道德普遍主义的承诺,以及它如何能够补充安德森和基彻的方法。
{"title":"Vindicating universalism: Pragmatic genealogy and moral progress","authors":"C. Blunden, Benedict Lane","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12975","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12975","url":null,"abstract":"How do we justify the normative standards to which we appeal in support of our moral progress judgments, given their historical and cultural contingency? To answer this question in a noncircular way, Elizabeth Anderson and Philip Kitcher appeal exclusively to formal features of the methodology by which a moral change was brought about; some moral methodologies are systematically less prone to bias than others and are therefore less vulnerable to error. However, we argue that the methodologies espoused by Anderson and Kitcher implicitly appeal to the substantive principle of “moral universalism.” This sets up the positive project of the paper: an attempt to vindicate moral universalism with a pragmatic genealogy. Using resources from cultural evolutionary theory and the history of ideas we argue that the universalistic norms widely committed to in many societies today have the function of maintaining cooperation in large anonymous groups. Furthermore, while universalistic norms play this instrumental role, their functional benefits are best secured when people following such norms do so for intrinsic rather than instrumental reasons. Finally, having elaborated our pragmatic genealogy, we close by considering how this genealogy should affect our commitment to moral universalism and how it can complement the methods of Anderson and Kitcher.","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2024-06-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141349861","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Love's realism: Iris Murdoch and the importance of being human 爱的现实主义:艾里斯-默多克与做人的重要性
IF 0.9 2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2024-06-11 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12978
Lesley Jamieson
Defenders of two Rationality Views of love—the Qualities View and the Personhood View—have drawn on Iris Murdoch's philosophical writings to highlight a connection between love and a “realistic” perspective on the beloved. Murdoch does not inform the basic structure of these views—she is rather introduced as a supplement who shows that in love, we pay accurate, nuanced, unguarded, and unflinching attention to the other. In this paper, I contend that these authors have failed to see that Murdoch offers a distinct view of love and is inappropriate to enlist as an ally. This is in large part because they have missed the full sense of what Murdoch means by connecting love and realism. I contend that for Murdoch, to love someone means seeing them in light of a realistic vision of what it means to be human; this includes an appreciation of the limits of freedom, the formative influence of personal history, and the nature and extent of our differences from one another. This helps us to see why Murdoch variously describes loving attention as realistic, compassionate, tolerant, and extremely difficult. It also sheds light on some important and familiar ways that we criticize one another's grounds for love.
两种理性爱情观--"特质观 "和 "人格观"--的捍卫者们利用艾里斯-默多克的哲学著作来强调爱情与对爱人的 "现实 "视角之间的联系。默多克并没有为这些观点的基本结构提供信息--相反,她是作为一个补充者被介绍的,她表明在爱情中,我们对对方给予了准确、细致、毫不掩饰和坚定不移的关注。在本文中,我认为这些作者没有看到默多克提供了一种独特的爱情观,不宜将其作为盟友。这在很大程度上是因为他们没有充分理解默多克将爱与现实主义联系起来的含义。我认为,对默多克来说,爱一个人就意味着从现实的角度看待他,理解他作为人的意义;这包括理解自由的局限性、个人历史的形成性影响,以及我们彼此差异的性质和程度。这有助于我们理解为什么默多克将爱的关注描述为现实的、富有同情心的、宽容的和极其困难的。它还揭示了我们批评彼此爱的理由的一些重要而熟悉的方式。
{"title":"Love's realism: Iris Murdoch and the importance of being human","authors":"Lesley Jamieson","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12978","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12978","url":null,"abstract":"Defenders of two Rationality Views of love—the Qualities View and the Personhood View—have drawn on Iris Murdoch's philosophical writings to highlight a connection between love and a “realistic” perspective on the beloved. Murdoch does not inform the basic structure of these views—she is rather introduced as a supplement who shows that in love, we pay accurate, nuanced, unguarded, and unflinching attention to the other. In this paper, I contend that these authors have failed to see that Murdoch offers a distinct view of love and is inappropriate to enlist as an ally. This is in large part because they have missed the full sense of what Murdoch means by connecting love and realism. I contend that for Murdoch, to love someone means seeing them in light of a realistic vision of what it means to be human; this includes an appreciation of the limits of freedom, the formative influence of personal history, and the nature and extent of our differences from one another. This helps us to see why Murdoch variously describes loving attention as realistic, compassionate, tolerant, and extremely difficult. It also sheds light on some important and familiar ways that we criticize one another's grounds for love.","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2024-06-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141357895","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1