首页 > 最新文献

EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY最新文献

英文 中文
“Belief” and Belief "信念 "与信仰
IF 0.9 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-01-28 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12934
Eric Marcus
Our interest in understanding belief stems partly from our being creatures who think. However, the term ‘belief’ is used to refer to many states: from the fully conscious rational state that partly constitutes knowledge to the fanciful states of alarm clocks. Which of the many ‘belief’ states must a theory of belief be answerable to? This is the scope question. I begin my answer with a reply to a recent argument that belief is invariably weak, i.e., that the evidential standards that are required for belief are low. Although one state we refer to using the term ‘belief’ fits this profile, other ‘belief’ states do not. Crucially, when ‘belief’ is heard in a weak sense, it attributes a state that only a rational creature can be in. I will use this observation as a starting point for an argument that the study of (our) belief should not be constrained by the requirement that the illuminated state be held in common with any non-rational being. This lends support to the Transformative Theory of Rationality, according to which rationality does not merely add powers or complexity to the animal mind, but transforms it into a different kind of mind altogether.
我们之所以对理解信念感兴趣,部分原因在于我们是会思考的生物。然而,"信念 "一词被用来指代多种状态:从部分构成知识的完全有意识的理性状态,到闹钟的幻想状态。在众多的 "信念 "状态中,信念理论必须回答哪些状态?这是一个范围问题。在回答这个问题时,我首先要回答最近提出的一个论点,即信念总是脆弱的,也就是说,信念所要求的证据标准很低。虽然我们用 "信念 "一词所指的一种状态符合这一特征,但其他 "信念 "状态却不符合这一特征。最重要的是,当 "信念 "被弱化时,它是一种只有理性生物才会有的状态。我将以这一观点为出发点,论证对(我们的)信念的研究不应受制于任何非理性生物所共同拥有的被照亮状态这一要求。根据这一理论,理性并不只是增加动物心智的力量或复杂性,而是将其转变为一种完全不同的心智。
{"title":"“Belief” and Belief","authors":"Eric Marcus","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12934","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12934","url":null,"abstract":"Our interest in understanding belief stems partly from our being creatures who think. However, the term ‘belief’ is used to refer to many states: from the fully conscious rational state that partly constitutes knowledge to the fanciful states of alarm clocks. Which of the many ‘belief’ states must a theory of belief be answerable to? This is the <i>scope question</i>. I begin my answer with a reply to a recent argument that belief is invariably <i>weak</i>, i.e., that the evidential standards that are required for belief are low. Although one state we refer to using the term ‘belief’ fits this profile, other ‘belief’ states do not. Crucially, when ‘belief’ is heard in a weak sense, it attributes a state that only a rational creature can be in. I will use this observation as a starting point for an argument that the study of (our) belief should not be constrained by the requirement that the illuminated state be held in common with any non-rational being. This lends support to the Transformative Theory of Rationality, according to which rationality does not merely add powers or complexity to the animal mind, but transforms it into a different kind of mind altogether.","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"135 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2024-01-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139583114","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Is Margaret Cavendish a naïve realist? 玛格丽特-卡文迪什是一个天真的现实主义者吗?
IF 0.9 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-01-25 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12914
Daniel Whiting

Perception plays a central and wide-ranging role in the philosophy of Margaret Cavendish. In this paper, I argue that Cavendish holds a naïve realist theory of perception. The case draws on what Cavendish has to say about perceptual presentation, the role of sympathy in experience, the natures of hallucination and of illusion, and the individuation of kinds. While Cavendish takes perception to have representational content, I explain how this is consistent with naïve realism. In closing, I address challenges to the interpretation, one of which turns on whether Cavendish allows for action at a distance. I argue that she does.

在玛格丽特-卡文迪什的哲学中,知觉起着核心和广泛的作用。在本文中,我将论证卡文迪什持有一种天真的现实主义知觉理论。这一论证借鉴了卡文迪什关于知觉呈现、同情在经验中的作用、幻觉和错觉的性质以及种类的个性化的论述。虽然卡文迪什认为知觉具有表象内容,但我解释了这如何与天真的现实主义相一致。最后,我讨论了对这一解释的质疑,其中之一是卡文迪什是否允许远距离行动。我认为她是允许的。
{"title":"Is Margaret Cavendish a naïve realist?","authors":"Daniel Whiting","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12914","DOIUrl":"10.1111/ejop.12914","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Perception plays a central and wide-ranging role in the philosophy of Margaret Cavendish. In this paper, I argue that Cavendish holds a naïve realist theory of perception. The case draws on what Cavendish has to say about perceptual presentation, the role of sympathy in experience, the natures of hallucination and of illusion, and the individuation of kinds. While Cavendish takes perception to have representational content, I explain how this is consistent with naïve realism. In closing, I address challenges to the interpretation, one of which turns on whether Cavendish allows for action at a distance. I argue that she does.</p>","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"32 2","pages":"321-341"},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2024-01-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/ejop.12914","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139583109","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Representation in action 行动中的代表性
IF 0.7 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-01-16 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12932
Alec Hinshelwood

When one is intentionally doing something, one represents that thing as a goal to be accomplished. One represents it practically. How should we characterize this practical representation further? In this paper, I argue that when one is intentionally doing something, one's representation of it as a goal to be accomplished must also be knowledge that one is intentionally doing that thing. And I argue that this knowledge must itself be one's intentionally doing that thing. I aim to show, then, that insofar as representing practically just is knowing practically, it is equally acting intentionally.

当一个人有意去做某件事时,他就会把这件事当作一个要完成的目标。这就是实际表述。我们应该如何进一步描述这种实际表征呢?在本文中,我认为,当一个人有意做某件事情时,他将其表征为一个要完成的目标,这也必须是他有意做这件事的知识。而且我认为,这种知识本身必须是一个人有意在做的事情。因此,我的目的是要证明,只要实践表征就是实践认知,它就同样是有意为之的行为。
{"title":"Representation in action","authors":"Alec Hinshelwood","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12932","DOIUrl":"10.1111/ejop.12932","url":null,"abstract":"<p>When one is intentionally doing something, one represents that thing as a goal to be accomplished. One represents it practically. How should we characterize this practical representation further? In this paper, I argue that when one is intentionally doing something, one's representation of it as a goal to be accomplished must also be knowledge that one is intentionally doing that thing. And I argue that this knowledge must itself be one's intentionally doing that thing. I aim to show, then, that insofar as representing practically just is knowing practically, it is equally acting intentionally.</p>","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"32 3","pages":"690-707"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-01-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/ejop.12932","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139496133","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Emulative envy and loving admiration 羡慕和爱慕
IF 0.9 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-01-16 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12927
Luke Brunning
Would you rather your friends, family, and partners envy you, or admire you, when you flourish? Many people would prefer to be admired, and so we often strive to tame our envy. Recently, however, Sara Protasi offered an intriguing defence of “emulative envy” which apparently improves us and our relationships, and is compatible with love. I find her account unconvincing, and defend loving admiration in this article. In Section 2, I summarize Protasi's nuanced account of envy. In Section 2, I argue that irrespective of how we analyze emotions in general we can argue that it is preferable to prioritize the cultivation of some emotions over others. In Section 4, I challenge Protasi's assumptions about the affinity between love and envy. My core argument is in Section 5 where I examine envy's impact on the envier, the envied, and relationships. Envy impedes an authentic relationship to the goods and goals in the envier's life, alienates the envied, and stifles joint-action. From all perspectives admiration typically fares better. After briefly considering the objection that admiration may impede love in Section 6, I conclude, in section seven, that admiration should be preferred to emulative envy in our intimate relationships.
当你蓬勃发展时,你是希望你的朋友、家人和合作伙伴羡慕你,还是钦佩你?很多人都希望自己被人钦佩,因此我们常常努力抑制自己的嫉妒心。然而,最近萨拉-普罗塔西(Sara Protasi)为 "模仿性嫉妒 "做了一个耐人寻味的辩护。我认为她的说法难以令人信服,并在本文中为爱的钦佩辩护。在第 2 节中,我总结了普罗塔西关于嫉妒的细微论述。在第 2 节中,我论证了无论我们如何分析一般情感,我们都可以认为优先培养某些情感比培养其他情感更可取。在第 4 节中,我对普罗塔西关于爱与嫉妒之间亲和力的假设提出质疑。我的核心论点在第 5 节,我将探讨嫉妒对嫉妒者、被嫉妒者和人际关系的影响。妒忌阻碍了与羡慕者生活中的物品和目标之间的真实关系,疏远了被羡慕者,并扼杀了共同行动。从所有角度来看,钦佩通常都更胜一筹。在第 6 节中,我简要地考虑了 "钦佩可能会妨碍爱情 "这一反对意见,然后在第 7 节中得出结论,在我们的亲密关系中,钦佩应该比模仿性嫉妒更受欢迎。
{"title":"Emulative envy and loving admiration","authors":"Luke Brunning","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12927","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12927","url":null,"abstract":"Would you rather your friends, family, and partners envy you, or admire you, when you flourish? Many people would prefer to be admired, and so we often strive to tame our envy. Recently, however, Sara Protasi offered an intriguing defence of “emulative envy” which apparently improves us and our relationships, and is compatible with love. I find her account unconvincing, and defend loving admiration in this article. In Section 2, I summarize Protasi's nuanced account of envy. In Section 2, I argue that irrespective of how we analyze emotions in general we can argue that it is preferable to prioritize the cultivation of some emotions over others. In Section 4, I challenge Protasi's assumptions about the affinity between love and envy. My core argument is in Section 5 where I examine envy's impact on the envier, the envied, and relationships. Envy impedes an authentic relationship to the goods and goals in the envier's life, alienates the envied, and stifles joint-action. From all perspectives admiration typically fares better. After briefly considering the objection that admiration may impede love in Section 6, I conclude, in section seven, that admiration should be preferred to emulative envy in our intimate relationships.","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"6 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2024-01-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139496226","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Correction to ‘On the eve of the “Philosophy of Symbolic Forms”: Cassirer and Hegel’ 对《"符号形式哲学 "的前夜》的更正:卡西勒与黑格尔
IF 0.9 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-01-16 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12930

Ferrari, M. On the eve of the “Philosophy of Symbolic Forms”: Cassirer and Hegel. European Journal of Philosophy, 31, 1125–1134.

The article by Ferrari (2023) has been corrected online to incorporate the following edits that were missed during production. The updated article can be accessed at https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/ejop.12915.
  • The author's affiliation has been updated (department name).
  • Amended a mention of “Hegelian” to “Hegelianism” in the 2nd paragraph of the main text.
  • Updated text for clarity (For example: “entangled” to “intertwined”; “Twenties” to “1920s”; “long dominated” to “long time”; “appointed” instead of “called”; “publication” instead of “edition”).
  • Typographical errors have been corrected.
  • Mention of “Hegelian” to “Hegelianism” in the 2nd paragraph of the main text.
  • These in-text citations have been updated include more details or to correct the citation year:

    • Kroner (1921)
    • Cassier (1996)
    • Lasson (1922)

  • The following changes have been made in the reference list:

    • Cassirer (1910)—Added
    • Cassirer (1979)—Updated
    • Cassirer (2009)—Removed
    • Cassirer (1920)—Updated
    • Cassirer (1958)—Updated
    • Cassirer (1996)—Updated
    • Cassirer (1999)—Updated
    • Cassirer (2001)—Updated
    • Cassirer (2004)—Updated
    • Cassirer (2006)—Updated
    • Cassirer (2021a)—Updated
    • Cassirer (2021b)—Updated
    • Cassirer (2021c)—Updated
    • Dilthey (1963)—Updated
    • Kroner (1921)—Updated
    • Gadamer (1958)—Updated
    • Natorp (1958)—Updated
    • Natorp (2015)—Updated

We apologize for these errors.

Ferrari, M. On the eve of the "Philosophy of Symbolic Forms":Cassirer and Hegel.European Journal of Philosophy, 31, 1125-1134.Ferrari (2023)的文章已在网上更正,加入了以下在制作过程中遗漏的编辑内容。更新后的文章可在 https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/ejop.12915 上查阅。更新了作者单位(系名)。将正文第 2 段中的 "黑格尔 "改为 "黑格尔主义":"将正文第 2 段中的 "黑格尔 "一词改为 "黑格尔主义":Kroner (1921)、Cassier (1996)、Lasson (1922):Cassirer (1910)-已添加Cassirer (1979)-已更新Cassirer (2009)-已删除Cassirer (1920)-已更新Cassirer (1958)-已更新Cassirer (1996)-已更新Cassirer (1999)-已更新Cassirer (2001)-已更新Cassirer (2004)-已更新Cassirer (2006)-已更新Cassirer (2007)-已删除Cassirer (2007)-已删除Cassirer (2007)-已删除Cassirer (2007)-已删除(2006)-UpdatedCassirer (2021a)-UpdatedCassirer (2021b)-UpdatedCassirer (2021c)-UpdatedDilthey (1963)-UpdatedKroner (1921)-UpdatedGadamer (1958)-UpdatedNatorp (1958)-UpdatedNatorp (2015)-Updated我们对这些错误表示歉意。
{"title":"Correction to ‘On the eve of the “Philosophy of Symbolic Forms”: Cassirer and Hegel’","authors":"","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12930","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12930","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Ferrari, M. On the eve of the “Philosophy of Symbolic Forms”: Cassirer and Hegel. <i>European Journal of Philosophy, 31</i>, 1125–1134.</p>\u0000<div>The article by Ferrari (2023) has been corrected online to incorporate the following edits that were missed during production. The updated article can be accessed at https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/ejop.12915. <ul>\u0000<li>The author's affiliation has been updated (department name).</li>\u0000<li>Amended a mention of “Hegelian” to “Hegelianism” in the 2nd paragraph of the main text.</li>\u0000<li>Updated text for clarity (For example: “entangled” to “intertwined”; “Twenties” to “1920s”; “long dominated” to “long time”; “appointed” instead of “called”; “publication” instead of “edition”).</li>\u0000<li>Typographical errors have been corrected.</li>\u0000<li>Mention of “Hegelian” to “Hegelianism” in the 2nd paragraph of the main text.</li>\u0000<li>\u0000<p>These in-text citations have been updated include more details or to correct the citation year: </p><ul>\u0000<li>Kroner (1921)</li>\u0000<li>Cassier (1996)</li>\u0000<li>Lasson (1922)</li>\u0000</ul>\u0000<p></p>\u0000</li>\u0000<li>\u0000<p>The following changes have been made in the reference list: </p><ul>\u0000<li>Cassirer (1910)—Added</li>\u0000<li>Cassirer (1979)—Updated</li>\u0000<li>Cassirer (2009)—Removed</li>\u0000<li>Cassirer (1920)—Updated</li>\u0000<li>Cassirer (1958)—Updated</li>\u0000<li>Cassirer (1996)—Updated</li>\u0000<li>Cassirer (1999)—Updated</li>\u0000<li>Cassirer (2001)—Updated</li>\u0000<li>Cassirer (2004)—Updated</li>\u0000<li>Cassirer (2006)—Updated</li>\u0000<li>Cassirer (2021a)—Updated</li>\u0000<li>Cassirer (2021b)—Updated</li>\u0000<li>Cassirer (2021c)—Updated</li>\u0000<li>Dilthey (1963)—Updated</li>\u0000<li>Kroner (1921)—Updated</li>\u0000<li>Gadamer (1958)—Updated</li>\u0000<li>Natorp (1958)—Updated</li>\u0000<li>Natorp (2015)—Updated</li>\u0000</ul>\u0000<p></p>\u0000</li>\u0000</ul>\u0000</div>\u0000<p>We apologize for these errors.</p>","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"64 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2024-01-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139496204","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Schelling's late philosophy in confrontation with Hegel. By Peter Dews, Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2022. pp. 344. $110 (hardback) 谢林晚期哲学与黑格尔的对峙。牛津大学出版社牛津大学出版社。2022. pp.344.110美元(精装本)
IF 0.9 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-01-16 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12924
Eliza Starbuck Little
{"title":"Schelling's late philosophy in confrontation with Hegel. By Peter Dews, Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2022. pp. 344. $110 (hardback)","authors":"Eliza Starbuck Little","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12924","DOIUrl":"10.1111/ejop.12924","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"32 1","pages":"296-298"},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2024-01-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139619950","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Transcendental arguments and metaphysical neutrality: A Wittgensteinian proposal 超验论证与形而上学中立:维特根斯坦的建议
IF 0.9 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-01-14 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12922
Sidra Shahid

Despite periods of resurgence over the last decades, it is safe to say that transcendental arguments no longer enjoy a prominent presence in the philosophical landscape. One reason for their declining prominence is the sustained suspicion that despite their self-proclaimed metaphysical neutrality, transcendental arguments are, in fact, metaphysically committed. This paper aims to revive the discussion of transcendental considerations by offering a metaphysically neutral account of transcendental arguments. I argue that a metaphysically neutral conception of transcendental arguments requires a revision of two concepts constitutive of transcendental claims, namely, transcendental necessity and the a priori. I propose a transcendental reading of Wittgenstein's On Certainty, which, I maintain, provides us with an alternative, metaphysically neutral understanding of these concepts. Thus revised, transcendental claims are suitable for what Mark Sacks once described as the “post-metaphysical” orientation of contemporary philosophy.

尽管超越论证在过去数十年间曾有过复兴,但可以肯定地说,超越论证在哲学界的地位已不复存在。其地位下降的原因之一是,人们一直怀疑,尽管超验论证自称是形而上学中立的,但事实上,它们是形而上学的承诺。本文旨在通过对超验论证进行形而上学中立的阐述,重振对超验考量的讨论。我认为,形而上学中立的超验论证概念需要修正两个构成超验主张的概念,即超验必然性和先验性。我建议对维特根斯坦的《论确定性》进行超越论解读,我认为这为我们提供了对这些概念的另一种形而上学中立的理解。经过这样的修订,超越论的主张适合马克-萨克斯(Mark Sacks)曾经描述过的当代哲学的 "后形而上学 "取向。
{"title":"Transcendental arguments and metaphysical neutrality: A Wittgensteinian proposal","authors":"Sidra Shahid","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12922","DOIUrl":"10.1111/ejop.12922","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Despite periods of resurgence over the last decades, it is safe to say that transcendental arguments no longer enjoy a prominent presence in the philosophical landscape. One reason for their declining prominence is the sustained suspicion that despite their self-proclaimed metaphysical neutrality, transcendental arguments are, in fact, metaphysically committed. This paper aims to revive the discussion of transcendental considerations by offering a metaphysically neutral account of transcendental arguments. I argue that a metaphysically neutral conception of transcendental arguments requires a revision of two concepts constitutive of transcendental claims, namely, transcendental necessity and the a priori. I propose a transcendental reading of Wittgenstein's <i>On Certainty</i>, which, I maintain, provides us with an alternative, metaphysically neutral understanding of these concepts. Thus revised, transcendental claims are suitable for what Mark Sacks once described as the “post-metaphysical” orientation of contemporary philosophy.</p>","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"32 2","pages":"476-488"},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2024-01-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/ejop.12922","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139496205","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Kant on race and the radical evil in the human species 康德论种族与人类的极端邪恶
IF 0.9 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-01-12 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12921
Laura Papish

Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason remains one of the most opaque of Kant's published writings. Though this opacity belongs, partly, to the text itself, a key claim of this article is that this opacity stems also from the narrow lenses through which his readers view this text. Often read as part of Kant's moral philosophy or his universal history, the literature has thus far neglected a different vantage point on the Religion, one that does not refute the utility of these lenses but complements them. This paper places the Religion alongside parts of Kant's corpus that it is less typically paired with, namely his natural history writings—in particular, his writings on the concept of race and the development of the human races. I argue that by doing so, we can shed much light on Kant's infamous claim that there is a radical evil in the human species. More precisely, we will come to appreciate that this evil is not, as it is usually understood, a static property or fixed characteristic of human beings. Instead, radical evil concerns a dynamic, changing defect in human nature that increasingly threatens our aspirations to collective moral perfection.

在康德已出版的著作中,《纯粹理性界限内的宗教》仍然是最不透明的著作之一。尽管这种不透明性部分是由文本本身造成的,但本文的一个关键主张是,这种不透明性还源于康德的读者通过狭隘的视角来看待这一文本。文献通常将《宗教论》作为康德道德哲学或其普遍历史的一部分来解读,但迄今为止,人们却忽视了对《宗教论》的另一种视角,这种视角不仅没有反驳这些视角的效用,反而是对它们的补充。本文将《宗教学》与康德文集中不那么常见的部分内容,即他的自然史著作,尤其是他关于种族概念和人种发展的著作放在一起进行研究。我认为,通过这样做,我们可以对康德臭名昭著的 "人种中存在着根本的恶 "这一说法有更多的了解。更确切地说,我们将认识到,这种恶并不像人们通常理解的那样,是人类的一种静态属性或固定特征。相反,激进的恶涉及人性中一种动态的、不断变化的缺陷,它日益威胁着我们对集体道德完美的渴望。
{"title":"Kant on race and the radical evil in the human species","authors":"Laura Papish","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12921","DOIUrl":"10.1111/ejop.12921","url":null,"abstract":"<p><i>Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason</i> remains one of the most opaque of Kant's published writings. Though this opacity belongs, partly, to the text itself, a key claim of this article is that this opacity stems also from the narrow lenses through which his readers view this text. Often read as part of Kant's moral philosophy or his universal history, the literature has thus far neglected a different vantage point on the <i>Religion</i>, one that does not refute the utility of these lenses but complements them. This paper places the <i>Religion</i> alongside parts of Kant's corpus that it is less typically paired with, namely his natural history writings—in particular, his writings on the concept of race and the development of the human races. I argue that by doing so, we can shed much light on Kant's infamous claim that there is a radical evil in the human species. More precisely, we will come to appreciate that this evil is not, as it is usually understood, a static property or fixed characteristic of human beings. Instead, radical evil concerns a dynamic, changing defect in human nature that increasingly threatens our aspirations to collective moral perfection.</p>","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"32 1","pages":"49-66"},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2024-01-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139462399","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Extravagance and misery: Hegel on the multiplication and refinement of needs 奢侈与痛苦黑格尔论需求的倍增与细化
IF 0.7 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-01-12 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12916
Nicolás García Mills

The topic of this paper is Hegel's claim in the Philosophy of Right that, within the modern social world, human needs tend to be endlessly expanded. Unlike the role that the system of needs plays in the formation of its participants' psychological makeup and the problem of poverty and the rabble, the topic of the expansion of needs remains underdiscussed in the recent Hegel literature on the virtues and vices of civil society. My discussion of the topic aims to answer the following two sets of questions: How does it come to pass that individuals' needs are endlessly expanded in this way? And is that expansion a phenomenon to be applauded or condemned? In particular, does the endless expansion of needs aid or obstruct the realization of social members' freedom? In answer to the first question, I argue that for Hegel the endless expansion of needs results from the level of specialization and division of labor distinctive of the modern market economy, the human capacity for a certain kind of abstraction, and the desire to be recognized by other participants in the market system. In answer to the second set of questions, and despite Hegel's own apparent ambivalence, I argue on his behalf that the endless expansion of needs represents an obstacle to the realization of freedom, and is on that ground a phenomenon to be condemned, for the following two reasons: First, the endless expansion of needs increases the influence or “pressure” of desire on the members of civil society that are subject to that expansion. Second, that expansion leads to widespread frustration, understood as the inability on the part of the members of civil society to ever fully realize their ends or satisfy their desires. I end by briefly considering two Hegelian solutions to the pernicious effects of the endless expansion of needs.

本文的主题是黑格尔在《权利哲学》中的主张,即在现代社会世界中,人的需求趋于无止境地膨胀。与需求体系在其参与者的心理构成以及贫困和乌合之众问题的形成中所扮演的角色不同,在黑格尔关于公民社会的美德与恶习的最新文献中,关于需求扩张的话题仍未得到充分讨论。我对这一话题的讨论旨在回答以下两组问题:个人的需求是如何以这种方式无休止地扩大的?这种扩张是值得称赞还是应该谴责?特别是,需求的无止境扩张是有助于还是阻碍了社会成员自由的实现?在回答第一个问题时,我认为在黑格尔看来,需求的无止境扩张源于现代市场经济特有的专业化和分工水平、人类的某种抽象能力以及被市场体系中其他参与者认可的愿望。在回答第二组问题时,尽管黑格尔本人表面上模棱两可,但我还是替他论证说,需求的无止境膨胀是实现自由的障碍,因此是一种应予谴责的现象,理由有二:首先,需求的无休止膨胀增加了欲望对公民社会成员的影响或 "压力",而公民社会成员是这种膨胀的对象。其次,这种扩张会导致普遍的挫折感,这种挫折感被理解为公民社会成员无法完全实现他们的目的或满足他们的欲望。最后,我简要地探讨了黑格尔对需求无止境膨胀的有害影响的两种解决方案。
{"title":"Extravagance and misery: Hegel on the multiplication and refinement of needs","authors":"Nicolás García Mills","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12916","DOIUrl":"10.1111/ejop.12916","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The topic of this paper is Hegel's claim in the <i>Philosophy of Right</i> that, within the modern social world, human needs tend to be endlessly expanded. Unlike the role that the system of needs plays in the formation of its participants' psychological makeup and the problem of poverty and the rabble, the topic of the expansion of needs remains underdiscussed in the recent Hegel literature on the virtues and vices of civil society. My discussion of the topic aims to answer the following two sets of questions: How does it come to pass that individuals' needs are endlessly expanded in this way? And is that expansion a phenomenon to be applauded or condemned? In particular, does the endless expansion of needs aid or obstruct the realization of social members' freedom? In answer to the first question, I argue that for Hegel the endless expansion of needs results from the level of specialization and division of labor distinctive of the modern market economy, the human capacity for a certain kind of abstraction, and the desire to be recognized by other participants in the market system. In answer to the second set of questions, and despite Hegel's own apparent ambivalence, I argue on his behalf that the endless expansion of needs represents an obstacle to the realization of freedom, and is on that ground a phenomenon to be condemned, for the following two reasons: First, the endless expansion of needs increases the influence or “pressure” of desire on the members of civil society that are subject to that expansion. Second, that expansion leads to widespread frustration, understood as the inability on the part of the members of civil society to ever fully realize their ends or satisfy their desires. I end by briefly considering two Hegelian solutions to the pernicious effects of the endless expansion of needs.</p>","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"32 3","pages":"758-777"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-01-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/ejop.12916","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139462359","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Listening to algorithms: The case of self-knowledge 聆听算法:自知之明
IF 0.9 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-01-10 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12923
Casey Doyle
This paper begins with the thought that there is something out of place about offloading inquiry into one's own mind to AI. The paper's primary goal is to articulate the unease felt when considering cases of doing so. It draws a parallel between the use of algorithms in the criminal law: in both cases one feels entitled to be treated as an exception to a verdict made on the basis of a certain kind of evidence. Then it identifies an account of first-person authority that can make good on this: agentialism. Thus, the paper constitutes an argument in favor of an agentialist treatment of self-knowledge and first-person authority.
本文一开始就认为,让人工智能来探究自己的思想有些不合时宜。本文的主要目的是阐明在考虑这样做的情况时所感受到的不安。它将算法的使用与刑法相提并论:在这两种情况下,人们都认为自己有权被视为根据某种证据做出的判决的例外情况。然后,本文指出了一种能够实现这一点的第一人称权威论:行动主义。因此,本文构成了一个论点,支持以一种行动主义的方式来处理自我认识和第一人称权威。
{"title":"Listening to algorithms: The case of self-knowledge","authors":"Casey Doyle","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12923","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12923","url":null,"abstract":"This paper begins with the thought that there is something out of place about offloading inquiry into one's own mind to AI. The paper's primary goal is to articulate the unease felt when considering cases of doing so. It draws a parallel between the use of algorithms in the criminal law: in both cases one feels entitled to be treated as an exception to a verdict made on the basis of a certain kind of evidence. Then it identifies an account of first-person authority that can make good on this: agentialism. Thus, the paper constitutes an argument in favor of an agentialist treatment of self-knowledge and first-person authority.","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"125 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2024-01-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139462384","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1