首页 > 最新文献

George Washington Law Review最新文献

英文 中文
Preferring One's Own Civilians: May Soldiers Endanger Enemy Civilians More than They Would Endanger Their State's Civilians? 偏爱本国平民:士兵对敌方平民的危害是否大于对本国平民的危害?
IF 1.5 3区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2009-08-07 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.1445509
Iddo Porat, Ziv Bohrer
When soldiers engage in war they should be careful not to harm enemy civilians. However, the question remains how careful should they be and, in particular, to what degree should they be willing to risk their lives in order not to harm enemy civilians? In a recent article for the New York Review of Books Professor Michael Walzer and Professor Avisahi Margalit argue that soldiers should take upon themselves the same degree of risk in order not to harm enemy civilians as they would have taken if those civilians were their own civilians. According to their example, if Hezbollah were to take over a Kibbutz in northern Israel and hold civilian hostages as human shields (for example by intermingling with them so that it would be impossible to hurt Hezbollah people without hurting the civilians) Israeli soldiers should risk themselves in order not to harm those civilians equally if: 1. The civilians used as human shields were Israeli Kibbutz members. 2. The civilians used as human shields were Swedish volunteers in the Kibbutz 3. The civilians used as human shields were residents of northern Lebanon which Hezbollah brought with them to Israel for use as human shields. I shall refer to this as the “equality” principle. Walzer and Margalit further argue that the degree of risk that Israeli soldiers should take upon themselves in all of these instances is higher than the degree of risk that they would impose on the civilians. To this I shall refer as the “altruism” principle. In this article I would like to question both the equality and the altruism principles, based on an argument from individual self defense. The gist of the argument is the following: in situations in which an aggressor holds an innocent person as a human shield, the defender may kill the human shield in order to save his life, because the human shield is morally equivalent to an innocent aggressor. That is, his well being poses a risk to the defender’s life, although he is in no way responsible or culpable for that risk. In such situations, the defender has an agent-relative permission to prefer his own life over the life of the human shield (hence the rejection of the altruism principle). However, if the human shield is someone close to the defender, such as his son, or his lover (or possibly his countryman) he may justifiably choose to risk his life more than the minimal moral requirement that would apply to any other human shield; that is he may choose to risk his life more than what he would be required to if the human shield were a stranger (hence the rejection of the equality principle).
士兵参加战争时应注意不要伤害敌方平民。然而,问题仍然是,他们应该多么小心,特别是,他们应该在多大程度上愿意冒着生命危险,以不伤害敌方平民?在《纽约书评》最近的一篇文章中,Michael Walzer教授和Avisahi Margalit教授认为,士兵应该承担同样程度的风险,以避免伤害敌方平民,就像如果这些平民是他们自己的平民一样。根据他们的例子,如果真主党占领了以色列北部的一个基布兹,并将平民人质作为人体盾牌(例如,通过与他们混在一起,这样就不可能在不伤害平民的情况下伤害真主党人民),以色列士兵应该冒着自己的风险,以免同样伤害这些平民:被用作人体盾牌的平民是以色列基布兹的成员。2. 被用作人体盾牌的平民是基布兹的瑞典志愿者。被用作人体盾牌的平民是黎巴嫩北部的居民,真主党把他们带到以色列用作人体盾牌。我将把这称为“平等”原则。Walzer和Margalit进一步认为,以色列士兵在所有这些情况下承担的风险程度要高于他们对平民施加的风险程度。对此,我将称之为“利他主义”原则。在这篇文章中,我想质疑平等原则和利他主义原则,基于个人自卫的论点。论点的要点如下:在侵略者将无辜者作为人肉盾牌的情况下,防御者可以杀死人肉盾牌以挽救他的生命,因为人肉盾牌在道德上等同于无辜的侵略者。也就是说,他的健康对辩护人的生命构成危险,尽管他对这种危险不负有任何责任或责任。在这种情况下,防卫者拥有相对于代理人的许可,可以选择自己的生命而不是人盾的生命(因此拒绝了利他主义原则)。然而,如果人肉盾牌是与防御者关系密切的人,如他的儿子或他的情人(或可能是他的同胞),他可以合理地选择冒生命危险,而不是适用于任何其他人肉盾牌的最低道德要求;也就是说,如果人肉盾牌是一个陌生人,他可能会选择冒更多的生命危险(因此拒绝了平等原则)。
{"title":"Preferring One's Own Civilians: May Soldiers Endanger Enemy Civilians More than They Would Endanger Their State's Civilians?","authors":"Iddo Porat, Ziv Bohrer","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.1445509","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.1445509","url":null,"abstract":"When soldiers engage in war they should be careful not to harm enemy civilians. However, the question remains how careful should they be and, in particular, to what degree should they be willing to risk their lives in order not to harm enemy civilians? In a recent article for the New York Review of Books Professor Michael Walzer and Professor Avisahi Margalit argue that soldiers should take upon themselves the same degree of risk in order not to harm enemy civilians as they would have taken if those civilians were their own civilians. According to their example, if Hezbollah were to take over a Kibbutz in northern Israel and hold civilian hostages as human shields (for example by intermingling with them so that it would be impossible to hurt Hezbollah people without hurting the civilians) Israeli soldiers should risk themselves in order not to harm those civilians equally if: 1. The civilians used as human shields were Israeli Kibbutz members. 2. The civilians used as human shields were Swedish volunteers in the Kibbutz 3. The civilians used as human shields were residents of northern Lebanon which Hezbollah brought with them to Israel for use as human shields. I shall refer to this as the “equality” principle. Walzer and Margalit further argue that the degree of risk that Israeli soldiers should take upon themselves in all of these instances is higher than the degree of risk that they would impose on the civilians. To this I shall refer as the “altruism” principle. In this article I would like to question both the equality and the altruism principles, based on an argument from individual self defense. The gist of the argument is the following: in situations in which an aggressor holds an innocent person as a human shield, the defender may kill the human shield in order to save his life, because the human shield is morally equivalent to an innocent aggressor. That is, his well being poses a risk to the defender’s life, although he is in no way responsible or culpable for that risk. In such situations, the defender has an agent-relative permission to prefer his own life over the life of the human shield (hence the rejection of the altruism principle). However, if the human shield is someone close to the defender, such as his son, or his lover (or possibly his countryman) he may justifiably choose to risk his life more than the minimal moral requirement that would apply to any other human shield; that is he may choose to risk his life more than what he would be required to if the human shield were a stranger (hence the rejection of the equality principle).","PeriodicalId":47068,"journal":{"name":"George Washington Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2009-08-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"78812167","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
Justice John Marshall Harlan Professor of Law 约翰·马歇尔·哈兰法官,法学教授
IF 1.5 3区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2009-05-13 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.1403917
Brian L. Frye, J. Blackman, Michael B. McCloskey
From 1889 to 1910, while serving on the United States Supreme Court, the first Justice John Marshall Harlan taught at the Columbian College of Law, which became the George Washington University School of Law. For two decades, he primarily taught working-class evening students, in classes as diverse as property, torts, conflicts of law, jurisprudence, domestic relations, commercial law, evidence — and most significantly — constitutional law. Harlan’s lectures on constitutional law would have been lost to history, but for the enterprising initiative — and remarkable note-taking — of one of Harlan’s students, George Johannes. During the 1897-98 academic year, George Johannes and a classmate transcribed verbatim the twenty-seven lectures Justice Harlan delivered on constitutional law. In 1955, Johannes sent the transcripts to the second Justice Harlan. The papers were ultimately deposited in the Library of Congress. Though much attention has been given to the life and jurisprudence of Justice Harlan, his lectures have been largely ignored. Harlan’s lectures are a treasure trove of insights into his jurisprudence, as well as the state of constitutional law at the turn of the 20th century. They provide the unique opportunity to listen in as one of our greatest Justices lectures on the precipice of a constitutional revolution that he helped create. In this article, we use the lectures to paint a picture of who Justice Harlan was, what he believed, how he sought to impart that knowledge to the future lawyers of America, and how he predicted many of the changes in constitutional law that occurred during the 20th century.This article, along with the annotated transcript of all twenty-seven lectures (http://ssrn.com/abstract=2003116), written on the centennial of Justice Harlan’s death, is a tribute to one of the giants of the law, and his contribution to legal education.
从1889年到1910年,在美国最高法院任职期间,第一任大法官约翰·马歇尔·哈兰在哥伦比亚大学法学院任教,该学院后来成为乔治·华盛顿大学法学院。二十年来,他主要教授工人阶级的夜校学生,课程种类繁多,包括财产法、侵权法、法律冲突、法理学、家庭关系、商法、证据法——最重要的是——宪法。如果不是哈兰的学生乔治·约翰内斯(George Johannes)的积极主动和出色的笔记记录,哈兰关于宪法的讲座早就湮没在历史长河中了。在1897-98学年,乔治·约翰内斯和一位同学逐字逐句地抄写了哈兰大法官关于宪法的27次演讲。1955年,约翰内斯将笔录寄给了第二任大法官哈兰。这些文件最终被存放在国会图书馆。虽然人们对哈兰法官的生平和法学给予了很多关注,但他的演讲在很大程度上却被忽视了。哈伦的讲座是他的法学见解的宝库,也是20世纪之交宪法状态的宝库。他们提供了一个独特的机会来聆听我们最伟大的大法官之一关于他帮助创建的宪法革命的悬崖的演讲。在这篇文章中,我们将利用这些讲座来描绘哈伦大法官是谁,他的信仰是什么,他如何试图将这些知识传授给美国未来的律师,以及他如何预测20世纪发生的许多宪法变化。这篇文章,连同所有27次讲座的注释文本(http://ssrn.com/abstract=2003116),都是为纪念哈伦法官逝世一百周年而写的,是对这位法律界巨人的致敬,以及他对法律教育的贡献。
{"title":"Justice John Marshall Harlan Professor of Law","authors":"Brian L. Frye, J. Blackman, Michael B. McCloskey","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.1403917","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.1403917","url":null,"abstract":"From 1889 to 1910, while serving on the United States Supreme Court, the first Justice John Marshall Harlan taught at the Columbian College of Law, which became the George Washington University School of Law. For two decades, he primarily taught working-class evening students, in classes as diverse as property, torts, conflicts of law, jurisprudence, domestic relations, commercial law, evidence — and most significantly — constitutional law. Harlan’s lectures on constitutional law would have been lost to history, but for the enterprising initiative — and remarkable note-taking — of one of Harlan’s students, George Johannes. During the 1897-98 academic year, George Johannes and a classmate transcribed verbatim the twenty-seven lectures Justice Harlan delivered on constitutional law. In 1955, Johannes sent the transcripts to the second Justice Harlan. The papers were ultimately deposited in the Library of Congress. Though much attention has been given to the life and jurisprudence of Justice Harlan, his lectures have been largely ignored. Harlan’s lectures are a treasure trove of insights into his jurisprudence, as well as the state of constitutional law at the turn of the 20th century. They provide the unique opportunity to listen in as one of our greatest Justices lectures on the precipice of a constitutional revolution that he helped create. In this article, we use the lectures to paint a picture of who Justice Harlan was, what he believed, how he sought to impart that knowledge to the future lawyers of America, and how he predicted many of the changes in constitutional law that occurred during the 20th century.This article, along with the annotated transcript of all twenty-seven lectures (http://ssrn.com/abstract=2003116), written on the centennial of Justice Harlan’s death, is a tribute to one of the giants of the law, and his contribution to legal education.","PeriodicalId":47068,"journal":{"name":"George Washington Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2009-05-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68175611","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Duplicative Foreign Litigation 重复涉外诉讼
IF 1.5 3区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2009-03-09 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.1356177
Austen L. Parrish
What should a court do when a lawsuit involving the same parties and the same issues is already pending in the court of another country? With the growth of transnational litigation, the issue of reactive, duplicative proceedings - and the waste inherent in such duplication - becomes a more common problem. The future does not promise change. In a modern, globalized world, litigants are increasingly tempted to forum shop among countries to find courts and law more favorably inclined to them than their opponents. The federal courts, however, do not yet have a coherent response to the problem. They apply at least three different approaches when deciding whether to stay or dismiss U.S. litigation in the face of a first-filed foreign proceeding. All three approaches, however, are undertheorized, fail to account for the costs of duplicative actions, and uncritically assume that domestic theory applies with equal force in the international context. Relying on domestic abstention principles, courts routinely refuse to stay duplicative actions believing that doing so would constitute an abdication of their "unflagging obligation" to exercise jurisdiction. The academic community in turn has yet to give the issue sustained attention, and a dearth of scholarship addresses the problem. This article offers a different way of thinking about the problem of duplicative foreign litigation. After describing the shortcomings of current approaches, it argues that when courts consider stay requests they must account for the breadth of their increasingly extraterritorial jurisdictional assertions. The article concludes that courts should adopt a modified lis pendens principle, and reverse the current presumption. Absent exceptional circumstances, courts should usually stay duplicative litigation so long as the party seeking the stay can establish that the first-filed foreign action has jurisdiction over the case under U.S. jurisdictional principles. This approach - pragmatic in its orientation, yet also more theoretically coherent than current law - would help avoid the wastes inherent in duplicative litigation, and better serve long-term U.S. interests.
当涉及相同当事人和相同问题的诉讼已经在另一个国家的法院悬而未决时,法院应该怎么做?随着跨国诉讼的增加,被动的、重复的诉讼问题- -以及这种重复所固有的浪费- -成为一个更普遍的问题。未来不会带来改变。在一个现代化的、全球化的世界里,诉讼当事人越来越倾向于在不同的国家之间进行仲裁,以找到比他们的对手更有利于他们的法院和法律。然而,联邦法院还没有对这个问题做出一致的回应。面对首次提起的外国诉讼,它们在决定是否保留或驳回美国诉讼时,至少采用三种不同的方法。然而,这三种方法都缺乏理论基础,没有考虑到重复行动的成本,而且不加批判地假设国内理论在国际背景下同样有效。依靠国内弃权原则,法院通常拒绝保留重复行动,认为这样做将构成放弃其行使管辖权的“不懈义务”。反过来,学术界也没有给予这个问题持续的关注,学术研究的缺乏解决了这个问题。本文对重复涉外诉讼问题提供了一种不同的思考方式。在描述了当前方法的缺点之后,它认为,当法院考虑暂缓请求时,它们必须考虑到其日益增加的治外法权主张的广度。本文的结论是,法院应采用修改后的未决案件原则,并扭转现行推定。在没有特殊情况的情况下,法院通常应暂停重复诉讼,只要寻求暂停的一方能够证明,根据美国司法原则,首次提起的外国诉讼对该案件具有管辖权。这种方法——其方向是务实的,但在理论上也比现行法律更连贯——将有助于避免重复诉讼所固有的浪费,并更好地为美国的长期利益服务。
{"title":"Duplicative Foreign Litigation","authors":"Austen L. Parrish","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.1356177","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.1356177","url":null,"abstract":"What should a court do when a lawsuit involving the same parties and the same issues is already pending in the court of another country? With the growth of transnational litigation, the issue of reactive, duplicative proceedings - and the waste inherent in such duplication - becomes a more common problem. The future does not promise change. In a modern, globalized world, litigants are increasingly tempted to forum shop among countries to find courts and law more favorably inclined to them than their opponents. The federal courts, however, do not yet have a coherent response to the problem. They apply at least three different approaches when deciding whether to stay or dismiss U.S. litigation in the face of a first-filed foreign proceeding. All three approaches, however, are undertheorized, fail to account for the costs of duplicative actions, and uncritically assume that domestic theory applies with equal force in the international context. Relying on domestic abstention principles, courts routinely refuse to stay duplicative actions believing that doing so would constitute an abdication of their \"unflagging obligation\" to exercise jurisdiction. The academic community in turn has yet to give the issue sustained attention, and a dearth of scholarship addresses the problem. This article offers a different way of thinking about the problem of duplicative foreign litigation. After describing the shortcomings of current approaches, it argues that when courts consider stay requests they must account for the breadth of their increasingly extraterritorial jurisdictional assertions. The article concludes that courts should adopt a modified lis pendens principle, and reverse the current presumption. Absent exceptional circumstances, courts should usually stay duplicative litigation so long as the party seeking the stay can establish that the first-filed foreign action has jurisdiction over the case under U.S. jurisdictional principles. This approach - pragmatic in its orientation, yet also more theoretically coherent than current law - would help avoid the wastes inherent in duplicative litigation, and better serve long-term U.S. interests.","PeriodicalId":47068,"journal":{"name":"George Washington Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2009-03-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68168601","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
American Civil Religion: An Idea Whose Time Is Past 美国公民宗教:一种过时的思想
IF 1.5 3区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2009-03-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.1440351
F. M. Gedicks
From the founding of the United States, Americans have understood loyalty to their country as a religious and not just a civic commitment. The idea of a 'civil religion' that defines the collective identity of a nation originates with Rousseau, and was adapted to the United States Robert Bellah, who suggested that a peculiarly American civil religion has underwritten government and civil society in the United States. Leaving aside the question whether civil religion has ever truly unified all or virtually all Americans, I argue that it excludes too many Americans to function as such a unifying force in the present. I discuss the general content of American civil religion, and then briefly examine how it has been deployed to sacralize four historical 'moments' in American history, the Founding, the Civil War, the Cold War, and the contemporary Culture Wars. I argue that religious pluralism and sectarian activism in the United States make a unifying civil religion improbable from a practical standpoint, and that the tendency of civil religion to devolve into idolatry, i.e., the sanctification of the government and its goals, makes it normatively unattractive, particularly for religious minorities. I close by suggesting that American civil religion can genuinely include and unify all Americans only if it drops its religious component, and that American society has sufficient cultural resources to inform a 'secular' civil religion.This paper was delivered at a symposium entitled 'Civil Religion in the United States and Europe: Four Comparative Perspectives,' held at Brigham Young University Law School on March 12-14, 2009.
自美国建国以来,美国人就把对国家的忠诚理解为一种宗教信仰,而不仅仅是一种公民义务。“公民宗教”定义了一个国家的集体身份,这一概念起源于卢梭,并被美国的罗伯特·贝拉(Robert Bellah)所采用,他认为美国特有的公民宗教为美国的政府和公民社会提供了保障。暂且不谈公民宗教是否真正团结了全体美国人,或者实际上团结了全体美国人,我认为它排除了太多的美国人,使其无法在当今发挥这样一种团结力量的作用。我讨论了美国公民宗教的一般内容,然后简要地考察了它是如何被用来神圣化美国历史上的四个历史“时刻”的:建国、内战、冷战和当代文化战争。我认为,从实践的角度来看,美国的宗教多元化和宗派激进主义使得统一的公民宗教不太可能,而且公民宗教倾向于沦为偶像崇拜,即将政府及其目标神圣化,使其在规范上没有吸引力,特别是对宗教少数群体而言。我最后建议,美国的公民宗教只有在放弃其宗教成分的情况下才能真正包括和团结所有美国人,而且美国社会有足够的文化资源来支持“世俗”的公民宗教。这篇论文发表于2009年3月12日至14日在杨百翰大学法学院举行的题为“美国和欧洲的公民宗教:四个比较视角”的研讨会上。
{"title":"American Civil Religion: An Idea Whose Time Is Past","authors":"F. M. Gedicks","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.1440351","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.1440351","url":null,"abstract":"From the founding of the United States, Americans have understood loyalty to their country as a religious and not just a civic commitment. The idea of a 'civil religion' that defines the collective identity of a nation originates with Rousseau, and was adapted to the United States Robert Bellah, who suggested that a peculiarly American civil religion has underwritten government and civil society in the United States. Leaving aside the question whether civil religion has ever truly unified all or virtually all Americans, I argue that it excludes too many Americans to function as such a unifying force in the present. I discuss the general content of American civil religion, and then briefly examine how it has been deployed to sacralize four historical 'moments' in American history, the Founding, the Civil War, the Cold War, and the contemporary Culture Wars. I argue that religious pluralism and sectarian activism in the United States make a unifying civil religion improbable from a practical standpoint, and that the tendency of civil religion to devolve into idolatry, i.e., the sanctification of the government and its goals, makes it normatively unattractive, particularly for religious minorities. I close by suggesting that American civil religion can genuinely include and unify all Americans only if it drops its religious component, and that American society has sufficient cultural resources to inform a 'secular' civil religion.This paper was delivered at a symposium entitled 'Civil Religion in the United States and Europe: Four Comparative Perspectives,' held at Brigham Young University Law School on March 12-14, 2009.","PeriodicalId":47068,"journal":{"name":"George Washington Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2009-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"83744012","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Two Visions of Corporate Law 公司法的两个愿景
IF 1.5 3区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2009-01-15 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.1328343
Todd Henderson
In a recent paper, Professor Robert Ahdieh argues that the debate about whether corporate law federalism leads to a race to the top or the bottom is pointless because state corporate law has little to do with the quality of corporate governance. Ahdieh thinks that markets, like those for corporate control and labor, are what make corporate governance what it is, not state competition for corporate charters. This essay, which will appear in the George Washington Law Review as part of a colloquy on Ahdieh's thought-provoking paper, argues that the race debate matters because while the market for corporate control disciplines managers, it is competition among states that disciplines states from distorting the market for corporate control. After showing that the race debate matters, the essay then tries to explain the persistence and ideological valence of the debate. Why is it that the debate continues despite innumerable empirical and theoretical studies on both sides, and why is it that defenders of the federalism model are mostly conservatives and critics are mostly liberals? The answer to both questions is that the race debate is really a conflict between two visions of corporate law held by these groups. Using the framework developed by Thomas Sowell, the essay shows how the split in the academic community about the optimality of the corporate law model can be explained by one's faith in experts (what Sowell calls the "unconstrained" vision) or by one's faith in processes, like markets (what Sowell calls the "constrained" vision). The essay then offers some preliminary thoughts on the implications of this description for corporate law scholarship and some ideas on how to move the debate forward.
在最近的一篇论文中,罗伯特•阿迪耶(Robert Ahdieh)教授认为,关于公司法联邦制是否会导致竞争的争论毫无意义,因为州公司法与公司治理的质量几乎没有关系。Ahdieh认为,市场,就像公司控制和劳动力市场一样,是公司治理的基础,而不是国家对公司章程的竞争。这篇文章将出现在《乔治华盛顿法律评论》(George Washington Law Review)上,作为对Ahdieh那篇发人深省的论文的讨论的一部分。文章认为,种族辩论很重要,因为虽然公司控制权的市场约束了管理者,但约束各州扭曲公司控制权市场的是各州之间的竞争。在展示了种族辩论的重要性之后,文章试图解释辩论的持久性和意识形态价值。为什么尽管双方都进行了无数的实证和理论研究,辩论仍在继续?为什么联邦主义模式的捍卫者大多是保守派,而批评者大多是自由派?这两个问题的答案是,种族辩论实际上是这些团体对公司法的两种看法之间的冲突。利用托马斯·索威尔(Thomas Sowell)提出的框架,这篇文章展示了学术界关于公司法模型最优性的分歧是如何通过对专家的信任(索威尔称之为“不受约束”的观点)或对市场等过程的信任(索威尔称之为“受约束”的观点)来解释的。然后,本文就这种描述对公司法学术的影响提供了一些初步的想法,并就如何推动辩论提出了一些想法。
{"title":"Two Visions of Corporate Law","authors":"Todd Henderson","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.1328343","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.1328343","url":null,"abstract":"In a recent paper, Professor Robert Ahdieh argues that the debate about whether corporate law federalism leads to a race to the top or the bottom is pointless because state corporate law has little to do with the quality of corporate governance. Ahdieh thinks that markets, like those for corporate control and labor, are what make corporate governance what it is, not state competition for corporate charters. This essay, which will appear in the George Washington Law Review as part of a colloquy on Ahdieh's thought-provoking paper, argues that the race debate matters because while the market for corporate control disciplines managers, it is competition among states that disciplines states from distorting the market for corporate control. After showing that the race debate matters, the essay then tries to explain the persistence and ideological valence of the debate. Why is it that the debate continues despite innumerable empirical and theoretical studies on both sides, and why is it that defenders of the federalism model are mostly conservatives and critics are mostly liberals? The answer to both questions is that the race debate is really a conflict between two visions of corporate law held by these groups. Using the framework developed by Thomas Sowell, the essay shows how the split in the academic community about the optimality of the corporate law model can be explained by one's faith in experts (what Sowell calls the \"unconstrained\" vision) or by one's faith in processes, like markets (what Sowell calls the \"constrained\" vision). The essay then offers some preliminary thoughts on the implications of this description for corporate law scholarship and some ideas on how to move the debate forward.","PeriodicalId":47068,"journal":{"name":"George Washington Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2009-01-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68163824","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 34
Oy Vey! The Bernstein Exception: Rethinking the Doctrine in the Wake of Constitutional Abuses, Corporate Malfeasance and the 'War on Terror' Oy一!伯恩斯坦例外:在宪法滥用、公司渎职和“反恐战争”之后重新思考这一原则
IF 1.5 3区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2008-02-15 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.1093563
B. Frankel
The Bernstein doctrine is a classic example of the exception swallowing the rule. The Bernstein exception allows the Executive to intercede in Act of State cases when it determines that adjudication would not harm U.S. foreign relations. The Exception was initially intended solely to permit victims of Nazi war crimes to recover in United States courts. In the more than 50 years since its inception, however, the Bernstein doctrine has expanded far beyond its original intended purpose. As a result, the Bernstein exception has created a host of constitutional and political dilemmas. For example, the Bernstein exception violates the separation of powers doctrine by giving the Executive, through the State Department, unchecked power to determine the outcome of Act of State cases brought in United States courts. This power has most recently been used by the Bush Administration to intercede on behalf of powerful, multi-national corporations in suits brought by individual plaintiffs, who are often the victims of international human rights abuses at the hands of these politically-connected corporations. Moreover, the current Administration has used the Bernstein exception as another means to unconstitutionally expand its power in the purported war on terror. The Bush Administration has been successful in having cases dismissed simply by making the unsubstantiated observation that adjudication in a U.S. court might have a negative effect on a particular foreign government's continued cooperation in fighting terrorism. In short, this article argues that the Bernstein exception should be abolished by the U.S. Supreme Court. While the Executive's views regarding the impact of a particular case on U.S. foreign relations may well be informative, its opinion cannot be dispositive. The judiciary is quite capable of determining the applicability of the Act of State doctrine without intervention by the Executive.
伯恩斯坦主义是例外吞下规则的典型例子。伯恩斯坦例外允许行政机关在确定裁决不会损害美国外交关系的情况下,在国家法案件中进行调解。“例外”最初只是为了允许纳粹战争罪行的受害者在美国法院获得赔偿。然而,伯恩斯坦主义自诞生以来的50多年里,已经远远超出了其最初的目的。结果,伯恩斯坦例外造成了一系列宪法和政治困境。例如,伯恩斯坦例外违反了三权分立原则,它通过国务院赋予行政部门不受制约的权力,以决定提交美国法院的国家法案件的结果。这一权力最近被布什政府用来代表强大的跨国公司在个人原告提起的诉讼中进行调解,这些原告往往是这些有政治关系的公司侵犯国际人权的受害者。此外,现任政府利用伯恩斯坦例外作为另一种手段,在所谓的反恐战争中违宪地扩大其权力。布什政府成功地驳回了一些案件,仅仅是因为他们毫无根据地认为,美国法院的裁决可能会对某个外国政府继续合作打击恐怖主义产生负面影响。简而言之,本文认为伯恩斯坦例外应该被美国最高法院废除。虽然行政当局对某一特定案件对美国外交关系的影响的看法很可能是有益的,但它的意见不能是决定性的。司法部门完全有能力在不受行政部门干预的情况下确定国家行为原则的适用性。
{"title":"Oy Vey! The Bernstein Exception: Rethinking the Doctrine in the Wake of Constitutional Abuses, Corporate Malfeasance and the 'War on Terror'","authors":"B. Frankel","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.1093563","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.1093563","url":null,"abstract":"The Bernstein doctrine is a classic example of the exception swallowing the rule. The Bernstein exception allows the Executive to intercede in Act of State cases when it determines that adjudication would not harm U.S. foreign relations. The Exception was initially intended solely to permit victims of Nazi war crimes to recover in United States courts. In the more than 50 years since its inception, however, the Bernstein doctrine has expanded far beyond its original intended purpose. As a result, the Bernstein exception has created a host of constitutional and political dilemmas. For example, the Bernstein exception violates the separation of powers doctrine by giving the Executive, through the State Department, unchecked power to determine the outcome of Act of State cases brought in United States courts. This power has most recently been used by the Bush Administration to intercede on behalf of powerful, multi-national corporations in suits brought by individual plaintiffs, who are often the victims of international human rights abuses at the hands of these politically-connected corporations. Moreover, the current Administration has used the Bernstein exception as another means to unconstitutionally expand its power in the purported war on terror. The Bush Administration has been successful in having cases dismissed simply by making the unsubstantiated observation that adjudication in a U.S. court might have a negative effect on a particular foreign government's continued cooperation in fighting terrorism. In short, this article argues that the Bernstein exception should be abolished by the U.S. Supreme Court. While the Executive's views regarding the impact of a particular case on U.S. foreign relations may well be informative, its opinion cannot be dispositive. The judiciary is quite capable of determining the applicability of the Act of State doctrine without intervention by the Executive.","PeriodicalId":47068,"journal":{"name":"George Washington Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2008-02-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"81688887","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Jus Ad Bellum in the Age of WMD Proliferation 大规模杀伤性武器扩散时代的战争权
IF 1.5 3区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2008-01-01 DOI: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199204908.003.0009
D. Joyner
This Article will discuss the normative question of what should be the character of the rules and institutions of international law covering international uses of force, in the age of proliferation of weapons of mass destruction (WMD) technologies. It will posit that international use of force law is currently in a state of crisis, precipitated by the proliferation of WMD technologies and the revised set of national security calculations, which determine when and why states choose to use force internationally, that have been thrust upon states as a result. It will review a number of options which have been proposed for changing the substance of international laws and institutions which currently regulate this area, in order to make them responsive to this change in international security realities, and more effective and useful to states. However it will conclude that none of these proposals truly grasps the nettle of the problems facing states in the post-proliferated age, and the challenge of designing and maintaining effective and supportable rules and institutions in this area. It will argue that more fundamental changes to the character of these rules and institutions are necessary if they are to fulfill a needed role in providing standards for international behavior in this most vital area of international relations. Using both international legal theory and international relations theory, it will argue specifically that international law regulating uses of force should be deformalized, and maintained not as legally binding rules, but as politically persuasive norms. This change in the character of rules in this area, it will be argued, would help to preserve the integrity of the rest of the formal corpus of international law, while accomplishing virtually the same results in influencing state behavior and in normativizing international relations in this area, as do the current formal rules of the jus ad bellum.
本文将讨论一个规范性问题,即在大规模毁灭性武器技术扩散的时代,涉及国际使用武力的国际法规则和机构的性质应该是什么。它将假定国际使用武力法目前处于危机状态,这是由大规模杀伤性武器技术的扩散和国家安全计算的修订所促成的,这些计算决定了国家何时以及为什么选择在国际上使用武力,而这些计算已被强加给各国。它将审查为改变目前管理这一领域的国际法和机构的实质而提出的若干备选办法,以便使它们适应国际安全现实的这种变化,对各国更有效和有用。然而,报告得出的结论是,这些建议都没有真正抓住后扩散时代各国面临的问题,以及在这一领域设计和维持有效和可支持的规则和制度的挑战。它将争辩说,如果要使这些规则和机构在为国际关系这一最重要领域的国际行为提供标准方面发挥必要的作用,就必须对它们的性质进行更根本的改变。本文将运用国际法理论和国际关系理论,具体论证规范武力使用的国际法应该被去形式化,并不是作为具有法律约束力的规则,而是作为具有政治说服力的规范来维持。有人会说,这一领域规则性质的这种变化将有助于维护国际法其余正式主体的完整性,同时在影响国家行为和使这一领域的国际关系正常化方面取得的结果几乎与现行的“战时法”正式规则相同。
{"title":"Jus Ad Bellum in the Age of WMD Proliferation","authors":"D. Joyner","doi":"10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199204908.003.0009","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199204908.003.0009","url":null,"abstract":"This Article will discuss the normative question of what should be the character of the rules and institutions of international law covering international uses of force, in the age of proliferation of weapons of mass destruction (WMD) technologies. It will posit that international use of force law is currently in a state of crisis, precipitated by the proliferation of WMD technologies and the revised set of national security calculations, which determine when and why states choose to use force internationally, that have been thrust upon states as a result. It will review a number of options which have been proposed for changing the substance of international laws and institutions which currently regulate this area, in order to make them responsive to this change in international security realities, and more effective and useful to states. However it will conclude that none of these proposals truly grasps the nettle of the problems facing states in the post-proliferated age, and the challenge of designing and maintaining effective and supportable rules and institutions in this area. It will argue that more fundamental changes to the character of these rules and institutions are necessary if they are to fulfill a needed role in providing standards for international behavior in this most vital area of international relations. Using both international legal theory and international relations theory, it will argue specifically that international law regulating uses of force should be deformalized, and maintained not as legally binding rules, but as politically persuasive norms. This change in the character of rules in this area, it will be argued, would help to preserve the integrity of the rest of the formal corpus of international law, while accomplishing virtually the same results in influencing state behavior and in normativizing international relations in this area, as do the current formal rules of the jus ad bellum.","PeriodicalId":47068,"journal":{"name":"George Washington Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2008-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"72689491","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Reprocessing Vermont Yankee 再加工佛蒙特洋基
IF 1.5 3区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2006-08-24 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.926349
Gary Lawson, J. Beermann
In Vermont Yankee Nuclear Power Corp. v. NRDC, 435 U.S. 519 (1978), the Supreme Court unanimously and stridently chastised the D.C. Circuit for forcing the Nuclear Regulatory Commission to employ procedures such as discovery and cross-examination in a notice-and-comment rulemaking when no organic statute, regulation, or constitutional provision required it. Vermont Yankee is almost universally regarded as one of the most important administrative law decisions issued by the Supreme Court. For the past three decades, various scholars, most notably Paul Verkuil and Richard Pierce, have been anticipating, and urging, a "Vermont Yankee II," in which the Court would similarly invalidate other administrative law doctrines. These prior calls for a Vermont Yankee II were not actually attempts to extend the reasoning and holding of Vermont Yankee. Rather Vermont Yankee was employed as a broad symbol - a metaphor of sorts - for Supreme Court intervention to reign in undue lower-court interference with agency discretion and autonomy. There are a significant number of important administrative law doctrines that seem to us to fly squarely in the face of all but the most unreasonably narrow understandings of the Vermont Yankee decision. These doctrines, ranging from the prohibitions on agency ex parte contacts and prejudgment in rulemakings to the expanded modern conception of the notice of proposed rulemaking, are all ripe for reconsideration. In this paper, after setting out the Vermont Yankee decision, we examine previous calls for a "Vermont Yankee II" and explain, in light of what we characterize as the "natural reading" of Vermont Yankee why the regulation of ex parte contacts and agency prejudgment in rulemakings, and mainstream applications of the APA's notice requirements violate the holding of Vermont Yankee as properly understood, as well as the principles and policies underlying the decision. Rejecting these doctrines is thus the appropriate target for a Vermont Yankee II.
在佛蒙特州扬基核电公司诉NRDC案(435 U.S. 519(1978))中,最高法院一致严厉谴责华盛顿特区巡回法院强迫核管理委员会在没有组织性法规、法规或宪法条款要求的情况下,在通知和评论规则制定中采用发现和交叉询问等程序。佛蒙特州扬基案几乎被普遍认为是最高法院发布的最重要的行政法裁决之一。在过去的三十年里,许多学者,最著名的是保罗·维尔库伊和理查德·皮尔斯,一直在预测并敦促“佛蒙特Yankee II”,即法院同样会使其他行政法理论无效。这些先前对“佛蒙特Yankee II”的要求实际上并不是试图扩展“佛蒙特Yankee”的推理和主张。相反,佛蒙特扬基被用作一个广泛的象征——某种意义上的隐喻——最高法院干预下级法院对机构自由裁量权和自主权的不当干预。在我们看来,有很多重要的行政法理论都与佛蒙特州扬基案判决的最不合理的狭隘理解截然相反。这些理论,从禁止单方面代理接触和规则制定中的预先判断,到扩大了的规则制定建议通知的现代概念,都是重新考虑的时机。在本文中,在阐述了佛蒙特Yankee案的判决之后,我们考察了之前对“佛蒙特Yankee案II”的呼吁,并根据我们所描述的佛蒙特Yankee案的“自然解读”,解释了为什么在规则制定中对单方面联系和机构预判的规定,以及APA通知要求的主流应用,违反了正确理解的佛蒙特Yankee案的判决,以及该判决背后的原则和政策。因此,对佛蒙特州的“洋基二号”来说,拒绝这些学说是合适的目标。
{"title":"Reprocessing Vermont Yankee","authors":"Gary Lawson, J. Beermann","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.926349","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.926349","url":null,"abstract":"In Vermont Yankee Nuclear Power Corp. v. NRDC, 435 U.S. 519 (1978), the Supreme Court unanimously and stridently chastised the D.C. Circuit for forcing the Nuclear Regulatory Commission to employ procedures such as discovery and cross-examination in a notice-and-comment rulemaking when no organic statute, regulation, or constitutional provision required it. Vermont Yankee is almost universally regarded as one of the most important administrative law decisions issued by the Supreme Court. For the past three decades, various scholars, most notably Paul Verkuil and Richard Pierce, have been anticipating, and urging, a \"Vermont Yankee II,\" in which the Court would similarly invalidate other administrative law doctrines. These prior calls for a Vermont Yankee II were not actually attempts to extend the reasoning and holding of Vermont Yankee. Rather Vermont Yankee was employed as a broad symbol - a metaphor of sorts - for Supreme Court intervention to reign in undue lower-court interference with agency discretion and autonomy. There are a significant number of important administrative law doctrines that seem to us to fly squarely in the face of all but the most unreasonably narrow understandings of the Vermont Yankee decision. These doctrines, ranging from the prohibitions on agency ex parte contacts and prejudgment in rulemakings to the expanded modern conception of the notice of proposed rulemaking, are all ripe for reconsideration. In this paper, after setting out the Vermont Yankee decision, we examine previous calls for a \"Vermont Yankee II\" and explain, in light of what we characterize as the \"natural reading\" of Vermont Yankee why the regulation of ex parte contacts and agency prejudgment in rulemakings, and mainstream applications of the APA's notice requirements violate the holding of Vermont Yankee as properly understood, as well as the principles and policies underlying the decision. Rejecting these doctrines is thus the appropriate target for a Vermont Yankee II.","PeriodicalId":47068,"journal":{"name":"George Washington Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2006-08-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67887896","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 7
Space, Place and Speech: The Expressive Topography 空间、地点与言语:表达地形
IF 1.5 3区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2005-08-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.854264
Timothy J. Zick
Place is currently under-theorized in First Amendment jurisprudence. When it has been independently considered at all, place has been conceptualized as nothing more than an inert backdrop for expressive scenes. For more than sixty years, place has been treated as property, a public resource, like air or water, that the government controls. There are many and sustained critiques of the constitutional doctrine of place. But there has been no effort to fundamentally and systematically reconsider place itself. Building upon a forthcoming TEXAS LAW REVIEW article, entitled Speech and Spatial Tactics, this Article fashions a new perspective on place. Drawing upon the work of scholars of place in human geography, anthropology, sociology, and philosophy, the Article sets forth a conception of place that it calls Expressive Place. In contrast to current treatments of place as secondary, inert, given, and binary, Expressive Place is primary to expression, dynamic, constructed, and variable. The Article utilizes the concept of Expressive Place to re-plot the expressive topography, the sum of public space potentially available for expressive activity. The revised topography consists of at least six spatial types that substantially affect First Amendment rights - Embodied, Contested, Inscribed, Tactical, Cyber, and Non-places. The Article offers several prescriptive suggestions in light of this ambitious re-conceptualization of place. A new method by which courts can read place is proposed, as are several specific alterations of the manner in which courts review spatial regulations under the time, place, and manner doctrine.
目前在第一修正案的法理学中,地方理论还不够理论化。当它被独立地考虑时,地方被概念化为表达场景的惰性背景。六十多年来,土地一直被视为财产,一种公共资源,就像空气或水一样,由政府控制。对宪法的地方原则有许多持续不断的批评。但是,没有人努力从根本上和系统地重新考虑地方本身。建立在即将到来的德克萨斯法律评论文章,题为演讲和空间战术,这篇文章时尚的地方的新观点。本文借鉴了人文地理学、人类学、社会学和哲学等领域研究地点的学者的研究成果,提出了一个地点概念,称之为“表达性地点”。与目前对场所的次要、惰性、给定和二元性的处理不同,表达性场所是主要的、动态的、建构的和可变的。文章利用表现性场所的概念重新绘制表现性地形,即可能用于表现性活动的公共空间总和。修订后的地形包括至少六种对第一修正案权利有实质性影响的空间类型——具体化、争议性、刻录性、战术性、网络性和非场所。文章提供了几个指令性的建议,根据这个雄心勃勃的重新概念化的地方。提出了一种法院可以解读地点的新方法,以及法院在时间、地点和方式原则下审查空间规则的几种具体改变。
{"title":"Space, Place and Speech: The Expressive Topography","authors":"Timothy J. Zick","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.854264","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.854264","url":null,"abstract":"Place is currently under-theorized in First Amendment jurisprudence. When it has been independently considered at all, place has been conceptualized as nothing more than an inert backdrop for expressive scenes. For more than sixty years, place has been treated as property, a public resource, like air or water, that the government controls. There are many and sustained critiques of the constitutional doctrine of place. But there has been no effort to fundamentally and systematically reconsider place itself. Building upon a forthcoming TEXAS LAW REVIEW article, entitled Speech and Spatial Tactics, this Article fashions a new perspective on place. Drawing upon the work of scholars of place in human geography, anthropology, sociology, and philosophy, the Article sets forth a conception of place that it calls Expressive Place. In contrast to current treatments of place as secondary, inert, given, and binary, Expressive Place is primary to expression, dynamic, constructed, and variable. The Article utilizes the concept of Expressive Place to re-plot the expressive topography, the sum of public space potentially available for expressive activity. The revised topography consists of at least six spatial types that substantially affect First Amendment rights - Embodied, Contested, Inscribed, Tactical, Cyber, and Non-places. The Article offers several prescriptive suggestions in light of this ambitious re-conceptualization of place. A new method by which courts can read place is proposed, as are several specific alterations of the manner in which courts review spatial regulations under the time, place, and manner doctrine.","PeriodicalId":47068,"journal":{"name":"George Washington Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2005-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.854264","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67844009","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 9
Eugenics and compulsory sterilization laws: providing redress for victims of a shameful era in United States history. 优生学和强制绝育法:为美国历史上一个可耻时代的受害者提供赔偿。
IF 1.5 3区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2004-04-01
Michael G Silver
{"title":"Eugenics and compulsory sterilization laws: providing redress for victims of a shameful era in United States history.","authors":"Michael G Silver","doi":"","DOIUrl":"","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":47068,"journal":{"name":"George Washington Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2004-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"25627225","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
George Washington Law Review
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1