首页 > 最新文献

George Washington Law Review最新文献

英文 中文
The Jurisprudence of Justice Samuel Alito 塞缪尔·阿利托法官的法学
IF 1.5 3区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2019-05-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.3235320
S. Calabresi, Todd W. Shaw
Justice Samuel Alito has sat on the judicial bench for nearly 30 years and has authored more than 250 Supreme Court opinions, nearly 40% of those for a majority of the Court. But his jurisprudence has yet to be systematically described. Although superficial accounts have been offered, they diverge widely. To some commentators, for example, Justice Alito is a methodological pluralist or “newer textualist,” though to others he is an originalist of the same or similar stripe as Justice Antonin Scalia. Yet Justice Alito’s jurisprudence cannot so neatly be identified with these or other competing descriptions. This Article is the first systematic account in any legal publication of Justice Alito’s jurisprudence. It analyzes nearly three dozen of Justice Alito’s opinions to demonstrate that three themes characterize his jurisprudence: (1) a fact-oriented approach in which fact is distinct from doctrine; (2) an implementation of “inclusive originalism,” under which a judge may evaluate precedent, policy, or practice, but only if the original meaning of the constitutional text incorporates such modalities; and (3) a strong presumption in favor of precedent and historical practice. Justice Alito’s jurisprudence is largely consistent with Burkean Conservatism. The three themes of Justice Alito’s jurisprudence follow the two features of Edmund Burke’s philosophical method of approaching political questions. First, Justice Alito’s distinction between fact and doctrine acknowledges both the Burkean rejection of abstract theory and the necessity of placing factual circumstances before principle and theory. Second, Justice Alito’s deference to precedent and historical practice squares with the Burkean tradition of relying on tradition and prescriptive wisdom.
塞缪尔·阿利托大法官担任法官近30年,撰写了250多份最高法院意见书,其中近40%的意见书代表了最高法院的多数意见。但他的法理学尚未被系统地描述。尽管提供了一些肤浅的解释,但它们分歧很大。例如,对一些评论家来说,阿利托大法官是方法论上的多元主义者或“新文本主义者”,尽管对其他人来说,他是与安东宁·斯卡利亚大法官相同或相似的原旨主义者。然而,阿利托大法官的法理学不能如此利落地与这些或其他相互矛盾的描述等同起来。这篇文章是任何法律出版物中对阿利托大法官的法理学的第一个系统描述。它分析了阿利托大法官的近36个意见,以证明他的法理学的三个主题:(1)以事实为导向的方法,其中事实与学说不同;(2)实施“包容性原旨主义”,即法官可以评估先例、政策或实践,但前提是宪法文本的原始含义包含了这些模式;(3)有利于先例和历史实践的强烈推定。阿利托大法官的法理学在很大程度上与伯克保守主义相一致。阿利托大法官的法理学的三个主题遵循了埃德蒙·伯克处理政治问题的哲学方法的两个特点。首先,阿利托大法官对事实和学说的区分既承认了伯克对抽象理论的拒绝,也承认了将事实情况置于原则和理论之前的必要性。其次,阿利托大法官对先例和历史实践的尊重符合伯克依靠传统和规范智慧的传统。
{"title":"The Jurisprudence of Justice Samuel Alito","authors":"S. Calabresi, Todd W. Shaw","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.3235320","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.3235320","url":null,"abstract":"Justice Samuel Alito has sat on the judicial bench for nearly 30 years and has authored more than 250 Supreme Court opinions, nearly 40% of those for a majority of the Court. But his jurisprudence has yet to be systematically described. Although superficial accounts have been offered, they diverge widely. To some commentators, for example, Justice Alito is a methodological pluralist or “newer textualist,” though to others he is an originalist of the same or similar stripe as Justice Antonin Scalia. Yet Justice Alito’s jurisprudence cannot so neatly be identified with these or other competing descriptions. \u0000 \u0000This Article is the first systematic account in any legal publication of Justice Alito’s jurisprudence. It analyzes nearly three dozen of Justice Alito’s opinions to demonstrate that three themes characterize his jurisprudence: (1) a fact-oriented approach in which fact is distinct from doctrine; (2) an implementation of “inclusive originalism,” under which a judge may evaluate precedent, policy, or practice, but only if the original meaning of the constitutional text incorporates such modalities; and (3) a strong presumption in favor of precedent and historical practice. \u0000 \u0000Justice Alito’s jurisprudence is largely consistent with Burkean Conservatism. The three themes of Justice Alito’s jurisprudence follow the two features of Edmund Burke’s philosophical method of approaching political questions. First, Justice Alito’s distinction between fact and doctrine acknowledges both the Burkean rejection of abstract theory and the necessity of placing factual circumstances before principle and theory. Second, Justice Alito’s deference to precedent and historical practice squares with the Burkean tradition of relying on tradition and prescriptive wisdom.","PeriodicalId":47068,"journal":{"name":"George Washington Law Review","volume":"87 1","pages":"507-578"},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2019-05-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46438376","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Measuring Computer Use Norms 测量电脑使用规范
IF 1.5 3区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2016-11-16 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2675895
Matthew B. Kugler
The Computer Fraud and Abuse Act prohibits unauthorized use of computer systems. One proposed method of defining unauthorized use is to use the norms of actual computer users, restricting punishment to that which many or all agree to be unauthorized. This study measures lay authorization beliefs and punishment preferences for a variety of computer misuse activities. Though perceived authorization is strongly predictive of punishment attitudes, results show that many people view common misuse activities as unauthorized but not deserving of any meaningful punishment. Respondents also viewed as unauthorized many activities – such as ignoring a website’s terms of service, surfing the news while at work, or connecting to a neighbor’s unsecured wireless network – that scholars have argued are implicitly licensed. This divergence between perceived authorization and desired punishment presents a challenge for the CFAA framework. To avoid results that would strike both the lay public and field experts as overcriminalization, “unauthorized use” must therefore be interpreted far more narrowly than common usage would suggest.
《计算机欺诈和滥用法》禁止未经授权使用计算机系统。定义未经授权使用的一种建议方法是使用实际计算机用户的规范,将惩罚限制在许多或所有同意未经授权的情况下。本研究测量了人们对各种计算机滥用行为的授权信念和惩罚偏好。尽管感知到的授权对惩罚态度有很强的预测性,但结果表明,许多人认为常见的滥用行为是未经授权的,不应该受到任何有意义的惩罚。受访者还认为许多行为——比如无视网站的服务条款,在工作时浏览新闻,或者连接邻居不安全的无线网络——都是未经授权的,学者们认为这些行为是隐含许可的。感知授权和期望惩罚之间的分歧对CFAA框架提出了挑战。因此,为了避免造成一般公众和实地专家都认为过度定罪的结果,“未经授权使用”的解释必须比一般用法所暗示的要狭隘得多。
{"title":"Measuring Computer Use Norms","authors":"Matthew B. Kugler","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2675895","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2675895","url":null,"abstract":"The Computer Fraud and Abuse Act prohibits unauthorized use of computer systems. One proposed method of defining unauthorized use is to use the norms of actual computer users, restricting punishment to that which many or all agree to be unauthorized. This study measures lay authorization beliefs and punishment preferences for a variety of computer misuse activities. Though perceived authorization is strongly predictive of punishment attitudes, results show that many people view common misuse activities as unauthorized but not deserving of any meaningful punishment. Respondents also viewed as unauthorized many activities – such as ignoring a website’s terms of service, surfing the news while at work, or connecting to a neighbor’s unsecured wireless network – that scholars have argued are implicitly licensed. This divergence between perceived authorization and desired punishment presents a challenge for the CFAA framework. To avoid results that would strike both the lay public and field experts as overcriminalization, “unauthorized use” must therefore be interpreted far more narrowly than common usage would suggest.","PeriodicalId":47068,"journal":{"name":"George Washington Law Review","volume":"84 1","pages":"1568-1590"},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2016-11-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.2675895","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68250079","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
The Evolutionary Interpretation of Treaties and the Right to Marry: Why Article 23(2) of the ICCPR Should Be Re-Interpreted to Encompass Same-Sex Marriage 条约与婚姻权利的演化解释:为什么《公民权利和政治权利国际公约》第23条第2款应该被重新解释以涵盖同性婚姻
IF 1.5 3区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2016-09-13 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2887121
Oscar I. Roos, A. Mackay
The United Nations Human Rights Committee (HRC) has not considered the application of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR) to same-sex marriage since providing their views in 2002 in response to an individual communication brought by two lesbian couples about New Zealand’s Marriage Act. Since 2002, the pace of reform globally has been increasing, with numerous countries now allowing same-sex couples to marry — in many cases in response to court decisions. This has led a number of commentators to opine that at some time in the future, the HRC will depart from the views it expressed in 2002 and adopt an interpretation of the ICCPR which embraces a right to marry a person of the same sex. This Article takes a doctrinal approach to that issue and goes to its crux. It applies the general rule of treaty interpretation set out in Article 31 of the Vienna Convention on the Interpretation of Treaties and argues that (i) the right to marry in Article 23(2) of the ICCPR should be given an evolutionary, rather than static interpretation; and (ii) a contemporary evolutionary interpretation of the right to marry should encompass a right to marry a person of the same sex.
联合国人权事务委员会(HRC)自2002年回应两名女同性恋夫妇就新西兰《婚姻法》提出的个人来文以来,一直没有考虑将《公民权利和政治权利国际公约》(ICCPR)适用于同性婚姻。自2002年以来,全球改革的步伐一直在加快,许多国家现在允许同性伴侣结婚——在许多情况下是对法院判决的回应。这导致一些评论员认为,在未来的某个时候,人权委员会将偏离其在2002年表达的观点,并通过对《公民权利和政治权利国际公约》的解释,其中包括与同性结婚的权利。这篇文章采取了一个理论的方法来解决这个问题,并找到了它的关键。它适用于《维也纳条约解释公约》第31条规定的条约解释的一般规则,并认为(i)《公民权利和政治权利国际公约》第23条第(2)款中规定的结婚权利应给予渐进的解释,而不是静态的解释;(ii)当代进化论对婚姻权利的解释应该包括与同性结婚的权利。
{"title":"The Evolutionary Interpretation of Treaties and the Right to Marry: Why Article 23(2) of the ICCPR Should Be Re-Interpreted to Encompass Same-Sex Marriage","authors":"Oscar I. Roos, A. Mackay","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2887121","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2887121","url":null,"abstract":"The United Nations Human Rights Committee (HRC) has not considered the application of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR) to same-sex marriage since providing their views in 2002 in response to an individual communication brought by two lesbian couples about New Zealand’s Marriage Act. Since 2002, the pace of reform globally has been increasing, with numerous countries now allowing same-sex couples to marry — in many cases in response to court decisions. This has led a number of commentators to opine that at some time in the future, the HRC will depart from the views it expressed in 2002 and adopt an interpretation of the ICCPR which embraces a right to marry a person of the same sex. This Article takes a doctrinal approach to that issue and goes to its crux. It applies the general rule of treaty interpretation set out in Article 31 of the Vienna Convention on the Interpretation of Treaties and argues that (i) the right to marry in Article 23(2) of the ICCPR should be given an evolutionary, rather than static interpretation; and (ii) a contemporary evolutionary interpretation of the right to marry should encompass a right to marry a person of the same sex.","PeriodicalId":47068,"journal":{"name":"George Washington Law Review","volume":"54 1","pages":"879-945"},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2016-09-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"83574954","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Religion, Conscience, and Belief in the European Court of Human Rights 欧洲人权法院的宗教、良心和信仰
IF 1.5 3区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2015-08-09 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2641644
Aaron R. Petty
In this paper, I suggest that a more critical view toward the notion of “religion” under Article 9 by the European Court of Human Rights would take an important step toward a more inclusive and egalitarian human rights jurisprudence. In other work, I have shown that “religion” as a legal term of art is generally understood by judges to refer primarily to belief, and that this understanding privileges Christianity at the expense of others.I begin by reviewing the position of religion in Europe and the special role of religion in the origin of the Westphalian system, the emergence of liberalism and, ultimately, modern human rights. I then turn to the specific right at issue, that of religion or belief under the ECHR. I discuss the origin of the Convention, review the structure of the Court and Commission it created, and take account of the analytical approach applied in addressing claims arising under Article 9. I suggest that Christian bias may be observed both in the terms of the Convention itself, and in its application by the Court. The final language used in the text of the Convention introduces inequality between religions based on the relative centrality of belief by tacitly equating religion with “belief” and with a similarly vague and belief-based notion of “conscience.”I then discuss how the Court has exacerbated the problems inherent in the convention through Court-made doctrines including the forum internum and forum externum, a historical theological dialectic the Commission repurposed as a legal doctrine, the margin of appreciation, consensus, and subsidiarity. I conclude that maintaining religion as a legal term of art is inherently problematic because it requires a focus on belief that does not comfortably fit outside of a Western context. Court adjudicating claims for religious protection involving religious minorities should take due care not to assume that belief plays a central role in those traditions.
在本文中,我建议欧洲人权法院对第9条下的“宗教”概念采取更加批判的观点,将朝着更加包容和平等的人权法理学迈出重要的一步。在其他工作中,我已经表明,“宗教”作为一个法律艺术术语,通常被法官理解为主要指信仰,这种理解以牺牲其他人的利益为代价,赋予基督教特权。我首先回顾了宗教在欧洲的地位,以及宗教在威斯特伐利亚体系的起源、自由主义的出现以及最终的现代人权中的特殊作用。然后,我转到有争议的具体权利,即欧洲人权公约规定的宗教或信仰权利。我将讨论《公约》的起源,审查《公约》所设立的法院和委员会的结构,并考虑到在处理根据第9条产生的索赔时所采用的分析方法。我认为,无论是在《公约》本身的条款中,还是在法院的适用中,都可以看到基督教的偏见。《公约》文本中最后使用的语言,通过将宗教与“信仰”以及同样模糊的、以信仰为基础的“良心”概念默认地等同起来,引入了基于信仰相对中心地位的宗教之间的不平等。然后,我将讨论法院是如何通过法院制定的理论(包括“内部论坛”和“外部论坛”)加剧公约中固有的问题的,这是一种历史神学辩证法,委员会将其重新定位为一种法律理论、增值边际、共识和辅助原则。我的结论是,将宗教作为一种艺术的法律术语本身就是有问题的,因为它需要关注信仰,而这种信仰在西方语境之外是不适合的。法院在裁决涉及宗教少数群体的宗教保护要求时,应适当注意,不要假定信仰在这些传统中起着中心作用。
{"title":"Religion, Conscience, and Belief in the European Court of Human Rights","authors":"Aaron R. Petty","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2641644","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2641644","url":null,"abstract":"In this paper, I suggest that a more critical view toward the notion of “religion” under Article 9 by the European Court of Human Rights would take an important step toward a more inclusive and egalitarian human rights jurisprudence. In other work, I have shown that “religion” as a legal term of art is generally understood by judges to refer primarily to belief, and that this understanding privileges Christianity at the expense of others.I begin by reviewing the position of religion in Europe and the special role of religion in the origin of the Westphalian system, the emergence of liberalism and, ultimately, modern human rights. I then turn to the specific right at issue, that of religion or belief under the ECHR. I discuss the origin of the Convention, review the structure of the Court and Commission it created, and take account of the analytical approach applied in addressing claims arising under Article 9. I suggest that Christian bias may be observed both in the terms of the Convention itself, and in its application by the Court. The final language used in the text of the Convention introduces inequality between religions based on the relative centrality of belief by tacitly equating religion with “belief” and with a similarly vague and belief-based notion of “conscience.”I then discuss how the Court has exacerbated the problems inherent in the convention through Court-made doctrines including the forum internum and forum externum, a historical theological dialectic the Commission repurposed as a legal doctrine, the margin of appreciation, consensus, and subsidiarity. I conclude that maintaining religion as a legal term of art is inherently problematic because it requires a focus on belief that does not comfortably fit outside of a Western context. Court adjudicating claims for religious protection involving religious minorities should take due care not to assume that belief plays a central role in those traditions.","PeriodicalId":47068,"journal":{"name":"George Washington Law Review","volume":"65 1","pages":"807"},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2015-08-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"91056667","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Four Challenges Confronting a Moral Conception of Universal Human Rights 普遍人权道德观面临的四大挑战
IF 1.5 3区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2015-05-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2394917
Eric D. Blumenson
This Essay describes some fundamental debates concerning the nature and possibility of universal human rights, conceived as a species of justice rather than law. It identifies four claims entailed by such rights and some significant problems each claim confronts. The designation “universal human rights” explicitly asserts three of them: paradigmatic human rights purport to be (1) universal, in that their protections and obligations bind every society, regardless of its laws and mores; (2) human, in that the rights belong equally to every person by virtue of one’s humanity, regardless of character, social standing, disabilities, or other individual attributes; and (3) matters of right which afford certain fundamental individual interests priority over the community’s wishes or welfare. Human rights differ widely in what they afford a right to — life, religious liberty, adequate nutrition, etc. — but they all share a fourth claim on which each distinct right is premised: that (4) the right specified serves to safeguard one such fundamental priority interest. Each of these claims generates uncertainty and disagreement, even among those who do not doubt the reality of universal human rights. Some theorists favor putting these some of these claims to rest by pursuing a different understanding of human rights that makes sense without them. The more modest aim of this Essay is to help inform that proposal by presenting these claims and challenges as concisely and transparently as possible.
本文描述了一些关于普遍人权的本质和可能性的基本争论,普遍人权被认为是一种正义而不是法律。它确定了这些权利所包含的四项要求以及每项要求所面临的一些重大问题。“普遍人权”一词明确地强调了其中的三个方面:范式人权的目的是(1)普遍的,因为它们的保护和义务对每个社会都有约束力,无论其法律和习俗如何;(2)人的,即由于每个人的人性,无论其性格、社会地位、残疾或其他个人属性如何,这些权利平等地属于每个人;(3)某些个人的根本利益优先于社会的愿望或福利的权利事项。人权所赋予的权利——生命、宗教自由、充足的营养等等——差别很大,但它们都有一个共同的要求,每一项不同的权利都以这个要求为前提:(4)所规定的权利是为了维护一种基本的优先利益。这些主张中的每一项都产生了不确定性和分歧,即使在那些不怀疑普遍人权现实的人中间也是如此。一些理论家倾向于通过追求一种不同的对人权的理解来搁置这些主张,这种理解在没有它们的情况下是有意义的。这篇文章更谦虚的目的是通过尽可能简洁和透明地提出这些主张和挑战来帮助告知这一建议。
{"title":"Four Challenges Confronting a Moral Conception of Universal Human Rights","authors":"Eric D. Blumenson","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2394917","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2394917","url":null,"abstract":"This Essay describes some fundamental debates concerning the nature and possibility of universal human rights, conceived as a species of justice rather than law. It identifies four claims entailed by such rights and some significant problems each claim confronts. The designation “universal human rights” explicitly asserts three of them: paradigmatic human rights purport to be (1) universal, in that their protections and obligations bind every society, regardless of its laws and mores; (2) human, in that the rights belong equally to every person by virtue of one’s humanity, regardless of character, social standing, disabilities, or other individual attributes; and (3) matters of right which afford certain fundamental individual interests priority over the community’s wishes or welfare. Human rights differ widely in what they afford a right to — life, religious liberty, adequate nutrition, etc. — but they all share a fourth claim on which each distinct right is premised: that (4) the right specified serves to safeguard one such fundamental priority interest. Each of these claims generates uncertainty and disagreement, even among those who do not doubt the reality of universal human rights. Some theorists favor putting these some of these claims to rest by pursuing a different understanding of human rights that makes sense without them. The more modest aim of this Essay is to help inform that proposal by presenting these claims and challenges as concisely and transparently as possible.","PeriodicalId":47068,"journal":{"name":"George Washington Law Review","volume":"33 1","pages":"327"},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2015-05-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"87991821","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Duty of Clarity 澄清的责任
IF 1.5 3区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2015-03-13 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2578318
John O. McGinnis
This article shows that the Constitution contemplates that judges are to exercise a duty of clarity before declining to follow legislation because it violates the Constitution. That is, they were to exercise the power of judicial review only if the legislation at issue proved to be in manifest contradiction of a constitutional provision. But judges were also expected to use the ample legal methods of clarification available to pin down the Constitution’s precise meaning.The best categorization of this duty of clarity and clarification is that it was an aspect of the judicial power granted under Article III of the Constitution. Thus, the article rejects James Bradley Thayer’s form of judicial deference - that legislation should be uphold on the basis of any interpretation that could be embraced by “a rational person” - as extreme and unwarranted. Thayer followed a jurisprudential tradition that developed subsequent to the Framing in which judicial review was fundamentally a political rather than a legal exercise and in which judges necessarily made law in the interstices of a written text’s unclear commands without any clear framework of discipline provided by legal rules. As a result, Thayer’s concept of constitutional deference has a larger scope and effect than it did at the jurisprudence of the Founding where judges were not seen as lawmakers in that sense and where the judicial duty of clarity has jurisprudential roots in natural law rather than positivism. But the article also rejects the notion that judicial review permits judges to overturn legislation based on their own view of the Constitution, even if their interpretation is not clearly the best one. The duty of clarity casts doubt on the legality of constitutional construction as opposed to constitutional interpretation in the course of judicial review, because constitutional construction can occur only when the meaning of the Constitution is unclear.
这表明,宪法考虑到法官在因立法违反宪法而拒绝遵循立法之前,应行使明确的义务。也就是说,只有在有关立法被证明明显违反宪法规定的情况下,他们才有权行使司法审查的权力。但法官们也被期望使用充分的法律方法来澄清宪法的确切含义。对这一澄清和澄清义务的最佳分类是,它是根据《宪法》第三条授予的司法权的一个方面。因此,该条拒绝了詹姆斯·布拉德利·塞耶的司法服从形式——立法应该在任何可能被“理性的人”接受的解释的基础上得到支持——认为这是极端和毫无根据的。塞耶遵循了一种法学传统,这种传统是在《框架》之后发展起来的,在这种传统中,司法审查基本上是一种政治行为,而不是一种法律行为,法官必须在书面文本中不明确的命令的间隙制定法律,而没有法律规则提供的任何明确的纪律框架。因此,塞耶的宪法服从概念比在建国时期的法理学中具有更大的范围和影响,在建国时期,法官不被视为这种意义上的立法者,而且司法澄清的义务具有自然法而不是实证主义的法理学根源。但该条款也驳斥了司法审查允许法官根据自己对宪法的看法推翻立法的观点,即使他们的解释显然不是最好的。在司法审查过程中,明确义务对宪法构建的合法性提出了质疑,而不是对宪法解释的合法性提出质疑,因为宪法构建只有在宪法含义不明确的情况下才能发生。
{"title":"The Duty of Clarity","authors":"John O. McGinnis","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2578318","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2578318","url":null,"abstract":"This article shows that the Constitution contemplates that judges are to exercise a duty of clarity before declining to follow legislation because it violates the Constitution. That is, they were to exercise the power of judicial review only if the legislation at issue proved to be in manifest contradiction of a constitutional provision. But judges were also expected to use the ample legal methods of clarification available to pin down the Constitution’s precise meaning.The best categorization of this duty of clarity and clarification is that it was an aspect of the judicial power granted under Article III of the Constitution. Thus, the article rejects James Bradley Thayer’s form of judicial deference - that legislation should be uphold on the basis of any interpretation that could be embraced by “a rational person” - as extreme and unwarranted. Thayer followed a jurisprudential tradition that developed subsequent to the Framing in which judicial review was fundamentally a political rather than a legal exercise and in which judges necessarily made law in the interstices of a written text’s unclear commands without any clear framework of discipline provided by legal rules. As a result, Thayer’s concept of constitutional deference has a larger scope and effect than it did at the jurisprudence of the Founding where judges were not seen as lawmakers in that sense and where the judicial duty of clarity has jurisprudential roots in natural law rather than positivism. But the article also rejects the notion that judicial review permits judges to overturn legislation based on their own view of the Constitution, even if their interpretation is not clearly the best one. The duty of clarity casts doubt on the legality of constitutional construction as opposed to constitutional interpretation in the course of judicial review, because constitutional construction can occur only when the meaning of the Constitution is unclear.","PeriodicalId":47068,"journal":{"name":"George Washington Law Review","volume":"84 1","pages":"843-919"},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2015-03-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68211117","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 6
The Sherlock Holmes Canon 夏洛克·福尔摩斯正典
IF 1.5 3区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2015-03-05 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2545919
Anita S. Krishnakumar
Many of the Supreme Court’s statutory interpretation cases infer meaning from Congress’s failure to comment in the legislative record. Colorfully referred to as the “dog that did not bark” canon, after a Sherlock Holmes story involving a watchdog that failed to bark while a racehorse was being stolen, the interpretive presumption holds as follows: if a statutory interpretation would significantly change the existing legal landscape, Congress can be expected to comment on that change in the legislative record; thus, a lack of congressional comment regarding a significant change can be taken as evidence that Congress did not intend that interpretation. Failure to comment arguments typically arise when the Supreme Court considers the meaning of a statutory provision that has been amended and an interpretation is advanced that arguably would change the status quo. Surprisingly, this canine canon of construction has received little theoretical attention — and what little attention it has received has tended to be positive, assuming that the canon leads courts to follow congressional intent. But there are several practical and theoretical problems with the assumptions underlying the canon. This essay examines how courts employ the Sherlock Holmes canon in practice and explores the canon’s normative and theoretical implications in detail. Ultimately, it argues that the Sherlock Holmes canon should be invoked only in rare cases, when there is special reason for courts to expect or require Congress to comment on a change in the law.
最高法院的许多法律解释案例都是从国会未能在立法记录中发表评论中推断出意义的。在夏洛克·福尔摩斯(Sherlock Holmes)的故事中,一只看门狗在一匹赛马被偷时没有吠叫,这被生动地称为“不叫的狗”经典。在此之后,解释性推定如下:如果一项法定解释将显著改变现有的法律格局,国会可以预期将对立法记录中的这一变化发表评论;因此,国会对重大变化缺乏评论可以被视为国会不打算作出这种解释的证据。当最高法院考虑已修订的法定条款的含义,并提出可能改变现状的解释时,通常会出现无法评论论点的情况。令人惊讶的是,这条关于建筑的经典几乎没有得到理论上的关注——而且它所得到的一点点关注往往是积极的,假设经典会导致法院遵循国会的意图。但是,这些经典背后的假设存在一些实际和理论上的问题。本文考察了法院在实践中如何运用福尔摩斯经典,并详细探讨了经典的规范和理论含义。最后,它认为,只有在极少数情况下,当法院有特殊理由期望或要求国会对法律的变化发表评论时,才应该援引夏洛克·福尔摩斯的经典。
{"title":"The Sherlock Holmes Canon","authors":"Anita S. Krishnakumar","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2545919","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2545919","url":null,"abstract":"Many of the Supreme Court’s statutory interpretation cases infer meaning from Congress’s failure to comment in the legislative record. Colorfully referred to as the “dog that did not bark” canon, after a Sherlock Holmes story involving a watchdog that failed to bark while a racehorse was being stolen, the interpretive presumption holds as follows: if a statutory interpretation would significantly change the existing legal landscape, Congress can be expected to comment on that change in the legislative record; thus, a lack of congressional comment regarding a significant change can be taken as evidence that Congress did not intend that interpretation. Failure to comment arguments typically arise when the Supreme Court considers the meaning of a statutory provision that has been amended and an interpretation is advanced that arguably would change the status quo. Surprisingly, this canine canon of construction has received little theoretical attention — and what little attention it has received has tended to be positive, assuming that the canon leads courts to follow congressional intent. But there are several practical and theoretical problems with the assumptions underlying the canon. This essay examines how courts employ the Sherlock Holmes canon in practice and explores the canon’s normative and theoretical implications in detail. Ultimately, it argues that the Sherlock Holmes canon should be invoked only in rare cases, when there is special reason for courts to expect or require Congress to comment on a change in the law.","PeriodicalId":47068,"journal":{"name":"George Washington Law Review","volume":"26 1","pages":"1"},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2015-03-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68199249","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Complexity of International Criminal Trials Is Necessary 国际刑事审判的复杂性是必要的
IF 1.5 3区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2015-03-04 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2573952
S. Ford
There is a widespread belief among both academics and policymakers that international criminal trials are too complex, and tribunals have come under enormous pressure to reduce the complexity of their trials. So far, however, changes to the procedure have not meaningfully affected trial complexity. This Article explains why these changes have failed and argues that the complexity of international criminal trials is necessary for them to fulfill their purposes. Using a multiple regression model of the factors driving trial complexity at the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (ICTY), this Article shows that the largest drivers of complexity are two factors that courts cannot control: the accused’s seniority within the political or military hierarchy and whether the accused is a direct perpetrator. The complexity of international criminal trials appears to be driven by the need to attribute responsibility for serious violations of international criminal law to accused who are often both organizationally and geographically distant from the crimes they are alleged to be responsible for. Attribution of responsibility is a necessary feature of most international criminal trials, and complexity associated with this process cannot be easily eliminated. The Article considers some ways that complexity could be significantly reduced – for example by making international criminal law violations strict liability offenses – but they all come with serious drawbacks that would probably undermine the purposes of international criminal justice. Ultimately, it appears that international criminal trials must be complex if they are to achieve the goals that we have set for them.
学术界和政策制定者普遍认为,国际刑事审判过于复杂,法庭面临着巨大的压力,要求其减少审判的复杂性。然而,到目前为止,程序的变化并没有对审判的复杂性产生有意义的影响。本文解释了这些变化失败的原因,并认为国际刑事审判的复杂性对于它们实现其目的是必要的。本文利用前南问题国际刑事法庭(前南问题国际法庭)审判复杂性因素的多元回归模型表明,复杂性的最大驱动因素是法院无法控制的两个因素:被告在政治或军事等级中的资历以及被告是否是直接犯罪者。国际刑事审判的复杂性似乎是由于需要将严重违反国际刑法的责任归咎于被告人,而这些被告人往往在组织上和地理上都远离被指控对其负责的罪行。责任归属是大多数国际刑事审判的一个必要特征,与这一过程有关的复杂性不能轻易消除。该条考虑了一些可以大大降低复杂性的方法- -例如将违反国际刑法的行为定为严格责任罪- -但它们都有严重的缺点,可能会破坏国际刑事司法的目的。最终看来,国际刑事审判如果要实现我们为其设定的目标,就必须是复杂的。
{"title":"The Complexity of International Criminal Trials Is Necessary","authors":"S. Ford","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2573952","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2573952","url":null,"abstract":"There is a widespread belief among both academics and policymakers that international criminal trials are too complex, and tribunals have come under enormous pressure to reduce the complexity of their trials. So far, however, changes to the procedure have not meaningfully affected trial complexity. This Article explains why these changes have failed and argues that the complexity of international criminal trials is necessary for them to fulfill their purposes. Using a multiple regression model of the factors driving trial complexity at the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (ICTY), this Article shows that the largest drivers of complexity are two factors that courts cannot control: the accused’s seniority within the political or military hierarchy and whether the accused is a direct perpetrator. The complexity of international criminal trials appears to be driven by the need to attribute responsibility for serious violations of international criminal law to accused who are often both organizationally and geographically distant from the crimes they are alleged to be responsible for. Attribution of responsibility is a necessary feature of most international criminal trials, and complexity associated with this process cannot be easily eliminated. The Article considers some ways that complexity could be significantly reduced – for example by making international criminal law violations strict liability offenses – but they all come with serious drawbacks that would probably undermine the purposes of international criminal justice. Ultimately, it appears that international criminal trials must be complex if they are to achieve the goals that we have set for them.","PeriodicalId":47068,"journal":{"name":"George Washington Law Review","volume":"22 1","pages":"151"},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2015-03-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"81455306","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 6
International Criminal Courts in Action: The ICTR's Effect on Death Penalty and Reconciliation in Rwanda 国际刑事法院在行动:卢旺达问题国际法庭对卢旺达死刑与和解的影响
IF 1.5 3区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2015-03-02 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2640306
Sigall Horovitz
This article focuses on a major reform encouraged by the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda (ICTR) – the abolition of the death penalty in Rwanda. For a decade prior to this reform, Rwandan courts have been imposing the death penalty in genocide cases. Using a qualitative empirical research method, still uncommon in international legal studies, the article shows how the ICTR’s requirements influenced the abolition, and then considers the impact of the abolition on national reconciliation in Rwanda. The findings suggest that the abolition has contributed to reconciliation, including through re-humanizing perpetrators and their relatives, improving survivors’ perception of society, and inspiring both survivors and perpetrators to envision a shared future. This is quite remarkable considering that, during the debates on the ICTR’s establishment, Rwanda insisted that sentencing to death genocide perpetrators was necessary for post-conflict justice and reconciliation. The article thus sheds a new light on the relationship between international tribunals and national reconciliation. In particular, it suggests that international tribunals can advance national reconciliation (and thus attain one of their explicit goals) through encouraging domestic legal developments such as death penalty reforms. Moreover, by raising awareness to the abolition’s positive effects on interethnic relations in Rwanda, the article could inform debates about the future of capital punishment in other death penalty countries.
本文重点讨论卢旺达问题国际刑事法庭(卢旺达问题国际法庭)鼓励的一项重大改革——在卢旺达废除死刑。在这项改革之前的十年里,卢旺达法院一直在种族灭绝案件中判处死刑。本文采用在国际法律研究中仍不常见的定性实证研究方法,展示了卢旺达问题国际法庭的要求如何影响废除死刑,然后考虑废除死刑对卢旺达民族和解的影响。研究结果表明,废除死刑有助于和解,包括通过使犯罪者及其亲属重新人性化,改善幸存者对社会的看法,并激励幸存者和犯罪者展望共同的未来。考虑到在关于设立卢旺达问题国际法庭的辩论中,卢旺达坚持认为,对灭绝种族者判处死刑对于冲突后的司法与和解是必要的,这一点相当引人注目。因此,这篇文章对国际法庭与民族和解之间的关系有了新的认识。特别是,它建议国际法庭可以通过鼓励国内法律发展,如死刑改革,来促进民族和解(从而实现其明确目标之一)。此外,通过提高对废除死刑对卢旺达种族间关系的积极影响的认识,该条可为其他死刑国家关于死刑未来的辩论提供信息。
{"title":"International Criminal Courts in Action: The ICTR's Effect on Death Penalty and Reconciliation in Rwanda","authors":"Sigall Horovitz","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2640306","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2640306","url":null,"abstract":"This article focuses on a major reform encouraged by the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda (ICTR) – the abolition of the death penalty in Rwanda. For a decade prior to this reform, Rwandan courts have been imposing the death penalty in genocide cases. Using a qualitative empirical research method, still uncommon in international legal studies, the article shows how the ICTR’s requirements influenced the abolition, and then considers the impact of the abolition on national reconciliation in Rwanda. The findings suggest that the abolition has contributed to reconciliation, including through re-humanizing perpetrators and their relatives, improving survivors’ perception of society, and inspiring both survivors and perpetrators to envision a shared future. This is quite remarkable considering that, during the debates on the ICTR’s establishment, Rwanda insisted that sentencing to death genocide perpetrators was necessary for post-conflict justice and reconciliation. The article thus sheds a new light on the relationship between international tribunals and national reconciliation. In particular, it suggests that international tribunals can advance national reconciliation (and thus attain one of their explicit goals) through encouraging domestic legal developments such as death penalty reforms. Moreover, by raising awareness to the abolition’s positive effects on interethnic relations in Rwanda, the article could inform debates about the future of capital punishment in other death penalty countries.","PeriodicalId":47068,"journal":{"name":"George Washington Law Review","volume":"6 1","pages":"505"},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2015-03-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"87534450","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Lenient in Theory, Dumb in Fact: Prison, Speech, and Scrutiny 理论上宽容,实际上愚蠢:监狱,言论和审查
IF 1.5 3区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2015-02-20 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2568132
D. M. Shapiro
The Supreme Court declared 30 years ago in Turner v. Safley that prisoners are not without constitutional rights: Any restriction on those rights must be justified by a reasonable relationship between the restriction at issue and a legitimate penological objective. In practice, however, the decision has given prisoners virtually no protection. Exercising their discretion under Turner, correctional officials have saddled prisoners’ expressive rights with a host of arbitrary restrictions — including prohibiting President Obama’s book as a national security threat; using hobby knives to excise Bible passages from letters; forbidding all non-religious publications; banning Ulysses, John Updike, Maimonides, case law, and cat pictures. At the same time, the courts have had no difficulty administering the Religious Land Use and Institutionalized Persons Act (RLUIPA), which gives prisons far less deference by extending strict scrutiny to free exercise claims by prisoners. Experience with the Turner standard demonstrates that it licenses capricious invasions of constitutional rights, and RLUIPA demonstrates that a heightened standard of review can protect prisoners’ expressive freedoms without compromising prison security. It is time for the Court to revisit Turner.
30年前,最高法院在特纳诉萨夫利案(Turner v. Safley)中宣布,囚犯并非没有宪法权利:对这些权利的任何限制,都必须以相关限制与合法的刑罚目标之间的合理关系为依据。然而,在实践中,这一决定实际上没有给囚犯提供任何保护。在特纳的领导下,狱警们行使他们的自由裁量权,对囚犯的表达权施加了一系列武断的限制——包括禁止奥巴马总统的书作为国家安全威胁;用小刀从书信中删去圣经段落;禁止一切非宗教出版物;禁止尤利西斯、约翰·厄普代克、迈蒙尼德、判例法和猫画。与此同时,法院在执行《宗教土地使用和机构人员法》(RLUIPA)方面没有任何困难,该法案通过严格审查囚犯的自由行使要求,大大减少了监狱的顺从。特纳标准的经验表明,它允许反复无常地侵犯宪法权利,而RLUIPA表明,提高审查标准可以在不损害监狱安全的情况下保护囚犯的表达自由。现在是法院重新审视特纳的时候了。
{"title":"Lenient in Theory, Dumb in Fact: Prison, Speech, and Scrutiny","authors":"D. M. Shapiro","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2568132","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2568132","url":null,"abstract":"The Supreme Court declared 30 years ago in Turner v. Safley that prisoners are not without constitutional rights: Any restriction on those rights must be justified by a reasonable relationship between the restriction at issue and a legitimate penological objective. In practice, however, the decision has given prisoners virtually no protection. Exercising their discretion under Turner, correctional officials have saddled prisoners’ expressive rights with a host of arbitrary restrictions — including prohibiting President Obama’s book as a national security threat; using hobby knives to excise Bible passages from letters; forbidding all non-religious publications; banning Ulysses, John Updike, Maimonides, case law, and cat pictures. At the same time, the courts have had no difficulty administering the Religious Land Use and Institutionalized Persons Act (RLUIPA), which gives prisons far less deference by extending strict scrutiny to free exercise claims by prisoners. Experience with the Turner standard demonstrates that it licenses capricious invasions of constitutional rights, and RLUIPA demonstrates that a heightened standard of review can protect prisoners’ expressive freedoms without compromising prison security. It is time for the Court to revisit Turner.","PeriodicalId":47068,"journal":{"name":"George Washington Law Review","volume":"84 1","pages":"972-1028"},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2015-02-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68207283","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
期刊
George Washington Law Review
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1