首页 > 最新文献

Notre Dame Law Review最新文献

英文 中文
Gift of Language 语言天赋
IF 0.9 3区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2014-02-24 DOI: 10.5040/9781472546579
Joseph Vining
Why is home language important? The language you speak with your children is the first language they will learn. It is their first connection to you, to the rest of their family, and to their culture and community. It is the language they first use to learn about the world around them. It is the language that helps them get “set for life”—and you are a central part of that process! This is one of the many ways parents are their children’s first teachers.
为什么母语很重要?你和孩子说的语言是他们学习的第一语言。这是他们与你、与家人、与文化和社区的第一次联系。这是他们首先用来了解周围世界的语言。这是帮助他们“为生活做好准备”的语言,而你是这个过程的中心部分!这是父母成为孩子启蒙老师的众多方式之一。
{"title":"Gift of Language","authors":"Joseph Vining","doi":"10.5040/9781472546579","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5040/9781472546579","url":null,"abstract":"Why is home language important? The language you speak with your children is the first language they will learn. It is their first connection to you, to the rest of their family, and to their culture and community. It is the language they first use to learn about the world around them. It is the language that helps them get “set for life”—and you are a central part of that process! This is one of the many ways parents are their children’s first teachers.","PeriodicalId":47176,"journal":{"name":"Notre Dame Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2014-02-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"80129797","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
Judge Posner, Judge Wilkinson, and Judicial Critique of Constitutional Theory 波斯纳法官、威尔金森法官与宪法理论的司法批判
IF 0.9 3区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2014-02-21 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2399487
Marc O Degirolami, Kevin C. Walsh
Judge Richard Posner’s well-known view is that constitutional theory is useless. And Judge J. Harvie Wilkinson III has lambasted constitutional theory for the way in which its “cosmic” aspirations threaten democratic self-governance. Many other judges hold similar views. And yet both Posner and Wilkinson — in the popular press, in law review articles, and in books — have advocated what appear to be their own theories of how to judge in constitutional cases. Judicial pragmatism for Posner and judicial restraint for Wilkinson seem to be substitutes for originalism, living constitutionalism, political process theory, and so on. But both Posner and Wilkinson also deny that they are offering a theory at all. This is puzzling. How do these judges simultaneously reject constitutional theory yet seemingly replace it with theories of their own? This Article answers that question — a question that must be answered in order to understand the present-day relationship between constitutional theory and constitutional adjudication. The perspectives of Judge Posner and Judge Wilkinson are particularly valuable because they have not only decided hundreds of constitutional cases but have also written extensively about constitutional theory. Drawing on a close reading of revealing slices of both their extrajudicial writing and their judicial opinions in constitutional cases, this Article makes three contributions. First, it brings to light agreements between Posner and Wilkinson that run far deeper than the heralded differences between them and that stem from their situated understanding of their judicial role. Second, it exposes the limited influence of judicial pragmatism and judicial restraint on these judges’ own constitutional jurisprudence even in those cases where one might expect constitutional theory to exert maximal influence. Third, it explains how judicial pragmatism and judicial restraint are best understood not as constitutional theories but as descriptions of judicial dispositions — character traits that pertain to judicial excellence — that can and should be criticized on their own terms.
理查德·波斯纳法官的著名观点是,宪法理论是无用的。法官j·哈维·威尔金森三世(J. Harvie Wilkinson III)猛烈抨击宪法理论,因为它的“宇宙”抱负威胁到了民主自治。许多其他法官也持类似观点。然而波斯纳和威尔金森——在大众媒体、法律评论文章和书籍中——都倡导了他们自己的关于如何在宪法案件中做出判断的理论。波斯纳的司法实用主义和威尔金森的司法约束似乎是原旨主义、活立宪主义、政治过程论等的替代品。但是波斯纳和威尔金森也都否认他们提供了一个理论。这令人费解。这些法官是如何在拒绝宪法理论的同时,似乎又用自己的理论来取代它的?本文回答了这个问题——为了理解当今宪法理论与宪法裁决之间的关系,必须回答这个问题。波斯纳法官和威尔金森法官的观点特别有价值,因为他们不仅裁决了数百起宪法案件,而且还撰写了大量关于宪法理论的文章。通过仔细阅读他们的法外写作和他们在宪法案件中的司法意见,本文做出了三点贡献。首先,它揭示了波斯纳和威尔金森之间的共识,这些共识远比他们之间预示的分歧要深刻得多,这些分歧源于他们对自己司法角色的定位理解。其次,它暴露了司法实用主义和司法约束对这些法官自身宪法学的有限影响,即使在那些人们可能期望宪法理论发挥最大影响的案件中也是如此。第三,它解释了为什么司法实用主义和司法克制最好不是被理解为宪法理论,而是作为对司法倾向的描述——与司法卓越有关的性格特征——可以而且应该根据自己的条件进行批评。
{"title":"Judge Posner, Judge Wilkinson, and Judicial Critique of Constitutional Theory","authors":"Marc O Degirolami, Kevin C. Walsh","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2399487","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2399487","url":null,"abstract":"Judge Richard Posner’s well-known view is that constitutional theory is useless. And Judge J. Harvie Wilkinson III has lambasted constitutional theory for the way in which its “cosmic” aspirations threaten democratic self-governance. Many other judges hold similar views. And yet both Posner and Wilkinson — in the popular press, in law review articles, and in books — have advocated what appear to be their own theories of how to judge in constitutional cases. Judicial pragmatism for Posner and judicial restraint for Wilkinson seem to be substitutes for originalism, living constitutionalism, political process theory, and so on. But both Posner and Wilkinson also deny that they are offering a theory at all. This is puzzling. How do these judges simultaneously reject constitutional theory yet seemingly replace it with theories of their own? This Article answers that question — a question that must be answered in order to understand the present-day relationship between constitutional theory and constitutional adjudication. The perspectives of Judge Posner and Judge Wilkinson are particularly valuable because they have not only decided hundreds of constitutional cases but have also written extensively about constitutional theory. Drawing on a close reading of revealing slices of both their extrajudicial writing and their judicial opinions in constitutional cases, this Article makes three contributions. First, it brings to light agreements between Posner and Wilkinson that run far deeper than the heralded differences between them and that stem from their situated understanding of their judicial role. Second, it exposes the limited influence of judicial pragmatism and judicial restraint on these judges’ own constitutional jurisprudence even in those cases where one might expect constitutional theory to exert maximal influence. Third, it explains how judicial pragmatism and judicial restraint are best understood not as constitutional theories but as descriptions of judicial dispositions — character traits that pertain to judicial excellence — that can and should be criticized on their own terms.","PeriodicalId":47176,"journal":{"name":"Notre Dame Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2014-02-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"80939474","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Immigration Separation of Powers and the President's Power to Preempt 移民三权分立和总统先发制人的权力
IF 0.9 3区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2014-02-17 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2397402
Catherine Y. Kim
This article explores the unique separation-of-powers issues raised in the immigration context, focusing on the respective powers of Congress and the President to preempt State law. Pursuant to traditional understanding, Congress and only Congress is constitutionally vested with the authority to displace conflicting State laws. Outside of the immigration context, the Supreme Court nonetheless has invoked competing theories of executive power to justify extending preemptive effect to executive decisions, while at the same time imposing significant doctrinal restrictions on its exercise. In its recent decision in Arizona v. United States, however, the Court departed from these existing doctrinal restrictions to hold that a conflict with the potential exercise of executive prosecutorial discretion suffices to displace State law. In doing so, it signaled an unprecedented expansion of the executive’s power to preempt, one without apparent limit. This article argues that considerations unique to immigration law undermine the utility of existing doctrinal frameworks for limiting executive preemption. Nonetheless, some restriction remains warranted. Given the limitations of the existing doctrines, it proposes a new approach to cabining executive authority in this context.
本文探讨了在移民背景下提出的独特的三权分立问题,重点是国会和总统各自的权力,以优先于州法律。根据传统的理解,国会且只有国会在宪法上被赋予取代相互冲突的州法律的权力。尽管如此,在移民问题之外,最高法院还是援引了与之竞争的行政权力理论,为将先发制人的效力扩大到行政决定辩护,同时对其行使施加了重大的理论限制。然而,在最近的亚利桑那州诉美国案的裁决中,法院脱离了这些现有的理论限制,认为与可能行使行政检察自由裁量权的冲突足以取代州法。在这样做的过程中,它标志着行政部门先发制人的权力史无前例地扩大,而且没有明显的限制。本文认为,移民法特有的考虑削弱了限制行政优先权的现有理论框架的效用。尽管如此,一些限制仍然是必要的。鉴于现有理论的局限性,本文提出了在这方面联合行政权力的新方法。
{"title":"Immigration Separation of Powers and the President's Power to Preempt","authors":"Catherine Y. Kim","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2397402","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2397402","url":null,"abstract":"This article explores the unique separation-of-powers issues raised in the immigration context, focusing on the respective powers of Congress and the President to preempt State law. Pursuant to traditional understanding, Congress and only Congress is constitutionally vested with the authority to displace conflicting State laws. Outside of the immigration context, the Supreme Court nonetheless has invoked competing theories of executive power to justify extending preemptive effect to executive decisions, while at the same time imposing significant doctrinal restrictions on its exercise. In its recent decision in Arizona v. United States, however, the Court departed from these existing doctrinal restrictions to hold that a conflict with the potential exercise of executive prosecutorial discretion suffices to displace State law. In doing so, it signaled an unprecedented expansion of the executive’s power to preempt, one without apparent limit. This article argues that considerations unique to immigration law undermine the utility of existing doctrinal frameworks for limiting executive preemption. Nonetheless, some restriction remains warranted. Given the limitations of the existing doctrines, it proposes a new approach to cabining executive authority in this context.","PeriodicalId":47176,"journal":{"name":"Notre Dame Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2014-02-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"89204992","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Putting Paradise in the Parking Lot: Using Zoning to Promote Urban Agriculture 把天堂放在停车场:利用分区促进都市农业
IF 0.9 3区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2013-11-11 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2352915
S. Maloney
This Note explores municipal zoning regulations related to urban agriculture and evaluates specific zoning mechanisms that can be implemented to efficiently promote the accommodation of urban agriculture and access to locally grown food. Consideration of the benefits and costs of urban agriculture, alongside the zoning practices of leading cities, will assist in developing zoning laws that meet the needs of American cities and citizens. Part I of this Note introduces the concept and history of urban agriculture, providing an overview of its benefits and challenges. Part II examines municipal zoning and the principle zoning restrictions that impact farming and gardening in a city. Part III reviews the varied efforts of municipalities to support urban agriculture by incorporating it into local zoning codes. Part IV concludes by offering recommendations for the municipal integration of agriculture into the urban fabric, with particular attentiveness to participatory policy-making in the form of food policy councils.
本报告探讨了与都市农业相关的市政区划法规,并评估了可实施的具体区划机制,以有效促进都市农业的适应和获得当地种植的食物。考虑城市农业的收益和成本,以及主要城市的分区实践,将有助于制定符合美国城市和公民需求的分区法律。本说明的第一部分介绍了都市农业的概念和历史,概述了都市农业的好处和挑战。第二部分考察了城市分区和影响城市农业和园艺的主要分区限制。第三部分回顾了市政当局通过将城市农业纳入当地分区法规来支持城市农业的各种努力。第四部分最后提出了将农业纳入城市结构的建议,特别注意以粮食政策委员会的形式参与决策。
{"title":"Putting Paradise in the Parking Lot: Using Zoning to Promote Urban Agriculture","authors":"S. Maloney","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2352915","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2352915","url":null,"abstract":"This Note explores municipal zoning regulations related to urban agriculture and evaluates specific zoning mechanisms that can be implemented to efficiently promote the accommodation of urban agriculture and access to locally grown food. Consideration of the benefits and costs of urban agriculture, alongside the zoning practices of leading cities, will assist in developing zoning laws that meet the needs of American cities and citizens. Part I of this Note introduces the concept and history of urban agriculture, providing an overview of its benefits and challenges. Part II examines municipal zoning and the principle zoning restrictions that impact farming and gardening in a city. Part III reviews the varied efforts of municipalities to support urban agriculture by incorporating it into local zoning codes. Part IV concludes by offering recommendations for the municipal integration of agriculture into the urban fabric, with particular attentiveness to participatory policy-making in the form of food policy councils.","PeriodicalId":47176,"journal":{"name":"Notre Dame Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2013-11-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"88503209","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 13
The Appointment and Removal of William J. Marbury and When an Office Vests 威廉·j·马布里的任免和办公室的归属
IF 0.9 3区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2013-11-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2857299
S. Prakash
Scholars have ignored the most important question in one of the most famousconstitutional law cases, obscuring the machinations that spawned the dispute. ThisArticle sheds light on the events that precipitated Marbury v. Madison and alsoexplains when an appointment vests. Thomas Jefferson famously refused to deliver acommission to William J. Marbury, causing the latter to seek a writ of mandamus fromthe Supreme Court. The received wisdom supposes that Jefferson’s refusal rested on thegrounds that Marbury had not been appointed a justice of the peace precisely because henever had received a commission. In fact, Jefferson’s delivery argument was a post-hocrationalization, having nothing to do with his actions in March of 1801. JohnAdams’s midnight appointments incensed Jefferson, leading the new President to treatall of the justice of the peace appointments as nullities. To Jefferson, the failure todeliver commissions to some of those appointees mattered not a whit. What seems tohave been far more significant is his sense that the justices of the peace served at hispleasure. Acting on this belief, he simultaneously removed them all and recess appointedmost of them, save for more than a dozen, including William J. Marbury.This Article also addresses whether William J. Marbury and the other midnight appointeeswho never received their commissions were nonetheless appointed, considering fivetheories of when an appointment vests: when the Senate consents; after consent butbefore commissioning; when commissioning occurs; with the delivery of a commission;and with acceptance of the office. In the course of considering these theories, the Articlediscloses the surprising fact that Thomas Jefferson, as Secretary of State, endorsed thesecond theory, namely that appointments vest before the act of commissioning. Moreover,well before Marbury v. Madison, the Adams Administration likewise concludedthat appointments could vest prior to any commission being issued or delivered. Despitethis convergence, the Article contends that none of the five theories is correct becauseeach reads the Constitution as enshrining a single answer regarding when an appointmentvests. There is no single answer. Rather an appointment vests whenever thePresident determines that it shall. The Constitution grants power to the President toappoint, never precisely specifying when or how an appointment vests. By not specifyingwhen or how appointment is made, the Constitution leaves it to the President todecide the manner in which he appoints. This conclusion derives from a general principleof constitutional law: When the Constitution grants power to an entity but doesnot specify the precise means by which it will be exercised, the grantee may decide themeans of exercising it.
学者们忽略了最著名的宪法案件之一中最重要的问题,掩盖了引发争议的阴谋。本文阐明了促成马布里诉麦迪逊案的事件,并解释了任命何时生效。众所周知,托马斯·杰斐逊拒绝向威廉·j·马布里(William J. Marbury)授予委任状,导致后者向最高法院申请行政令。人们普遍认为,杰斐逊拒绝马布里的理由是,马布里没有被任命为治安法官,恰恰是因为他从来没有接受过任命。事实上,杰斐逊的演讲论点是一种后爱国主义,与他在1801年3月的行动毫无关系。约翰·亚当斯的午夜任命激怒了杰斐逊,导致这位新总统将和平法官的任命视为无效。对杰斐逊来说,未能向其中一些被任命者交付委任状一点也不重要。似乎更重要的是,他觉得治安法官听命于他。本着这一信念,他同时将他们全部撤职,并休会任命了大多数人,除了包括威廉·j·马布里在内的十几个人。本文还讨论了威廉·j·马布里和其他从未接受过任命的午夜被任命者是否仍然被任命,考虑了任命何时生效的五种理论:参议院同意;同意后但在投入使用前;调试时;他接受了这个职位,接受了这个委托。在考虑这些理论的过程中,文章揭示了一个令人惊讶的事实,即托马斯·杰斐逊,作为国务卿,支持第二种理论,即任命在委托行为之前生效。此外,早在马布里诉麦迪逊案之前,亚当斯政府同样得出结论,任命可以在任何委员会发布或交付之前授予。尽管有这种趋同,《宪法》认为,这五种理论都不正确,因为每种理论都把宪法解读为对任命何时生效只有一个答案。没有单一的答案。相反,只要总统决定,任命就会生效。宪法赋予总统任命的权力,但从未明确规定任命的时间和方式。由于宪法没有具体规定任命的时间和方式,所以由总统来决定他任命的方式。这一结论源于宪法的一般原则:当宪法授予一个实体权力,但没有具体规定行使权力的具体方式时,受让人可以决定行使权力的方式。
{"title":"The Appointment and Removal of William J. Marbury and When an Office Vests","authors":"S. Prakash","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2857299","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2857299","url":null,"abstract":"Scholars have ignored the most important question in one of the most famousconstitutional law cases, obscuring the machinations that spawned the dispute. ThisArticle sheds light on the events that precipitated Marbury v. Madison and alsoexplains when an appointment vests. Thomas Jefferson famously refused to deliver acommission to William J. Marbury, causing the latter to seek a writ of mandamus fromthe Supreme Court. The received wisdom supposes that Jefferson’s refusal rested on thegrounds that Marbury had not been appointed a justice of the peace precisely because henever had received a commission. In fact, Jefferson’s delivery argument was a post-hocrationalization, having nothing to do with his actions in March of 1801. JohnAdams’s midnight appointments incensed Jefferson, leading the new President to treatall of the justice of the peace appointments as nullities. To Jefferson, the failure todeliver commissions to some of those appointees mattered not a whit. What seems tohave been far more significant is his sense that the justices of the peace served at hispleasure. Acting on this belief, he simultaneously removed them all and recess appointedmost of them, save for more than a dozen, including William J. Marbury.This Article also addresses whether William J. Marbury and the other midnight appointeeswho never received their commissions were nonetheless appointed, considering fivetheories of when an appointment vests: when the Senate consents; after consent butbefore commissioning; when commissioning occurs; with the delivery of a commission;and with acceptance of the office. In the course of considering these theories, the Articlediscloses the surprising fact that Thomas Jefferson, as Secretary of State, endorsed thesecond theory, namely that appointments vest before the act of commissioning. Moreover,well before Marbury v. Madison, the Adams Administration likewise concludedthat appointments could vest prior to any commission being issued or delivered. Despitethis convergence, the Article contends that none of the five theories is correct becauseeach reads the Constitution as enshrining a single answer regarding when an appointmentvests. There is no single answer. Rather an appointment vests whenever thePresident determines that it shall. The Constitution grants power to the President toappoint, never precisely specifying when or how an appointment vests. By not specifyingwhen or how appointment is made, the Constitution leaves it to the President todecide the manner in which he appoints. This conclusion derives from a general principleof constitutional law: When the Constitution grants power to an entity but doesnot specify the precise means by which it will be exercised, the grantee may decide themeans of exercising it.","PeriodicalId":47176,"journal":{"name":"Notre Dame Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2013-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"82283557","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
New Governance and Industry Culture 新治理与产业文化
IF 0.9 3区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2013-07-17 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2064242
K. Schulz
New governance scholarship argues that private regulation is playing a larger role in influencing industry behavior relative to state-centric methods of regulation. Despite its burgeoning growth, new governance scholarship is critiqued as lacking practical examples. This article fills the void by conducting an institutional law and economics analysis of forestry sustainability certifications, a classic example of private regulation. This article analyzes the features of the forestry industry that contribute to the success of sustainability certifications within it. It finds that the industrial characteristics that contribute to successful private regulatory regimes include strong norms within the industry, a resource-type that favors user-developed rules, and robust competition among private actors to regulate the industry. These findings suggest new governance can and does succeed in industries with similar characteristics, providing a novel real-world example of theoretical new governance ideals in practice.
新的治理学者认为,相对于以国家为中心的监管方法,私人监管在影响行业行为方面发挥着更大的作用。尽管发展迅速,但新的治理学术被批评为缺乏实际例子。本文通过对林业可持续发展认证这一民间规制的经典案例进行制度法学和经济学分析,填补了这一空白。本文分析了林业行业的特点,有助于其可持续发展认证的成功。研究发现,促成成功的私人监管制度的行业特征包括行业内强有力的规范,有利于用户制定规则的资源类型,以及私人行为者之间为监管行业而进行的激烈竞争。这些发现表明,新的治理能够并且确实在具有类似特征的行业中取得成功,为实践中的理论新治理理想提供了一个新的现实世界示例。
{"title":"New Governance and Industry Culture","authors":"K. Schulz","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2064242","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2064242","url":null,"abstract":"New governance scholarship argues that private regulation is playing a larger role in influencing industry behavior relative to state-centric methods of regulation. Despite its burgeoning growth, new governance scholarship is critiqued as lacking practical examples. This article fills the void by conducting an institutional law and economics analysis of forestry sustainability certifications, a classic example of private regulation. This article analyzes the features of the forestry industry that contribute to the success of sustainability certifications within it. It finds that the industrial characteristics that contribute to successful private regulatory regimes include strong norms within the industry, a resource-type that favors user-developed rules, and robust competition among private actors to regulate the industry. These findings suggest new governance can and does succeed in industries with similar characteristics, providing a novel real-world example of theoretical new governance ideals in practice.","PeriodicalId":47176,"journal":{"name":"Notre Dame Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2013-07-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"75420338","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Understanding Behavioral Antitrust 理解行为反垄断
IF 0.9 3区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2013-07-13 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.2293508
Avishalom Tor
Behavioral antitrust – the application to antitrust analysis of empirical evidence of robust behavioral deviations from strict rationality – is increasingly popular and hotly debated by legal scholars and the enforcement agencies alike. This Article shows, however, that both proponents and opponents of behavioral antitrust frequently and fundamentally misconstrue its methodology, treating concrete empirical phenomena as if they were broad hypothetical assumptions. Because of this fundamental methodological error, scholars often make three classes of mistakes in behavioral antitrust analyses: First, they fail to appreciate the variability and heterogeneity of behavioral phenomena; second, they disregard the concrete ways in which markets, firms, and other institutions both facilitate and inhibit rational behavior by antitrust actors; and, third, they erroneously equate all deviations from standard rationality with harm to competition. After establishing the central role of rationality assumptions in present-day antitrust and reviewing illustrative behavioral analyses across the field – from horizontal and vertical restraints, through monopolization, to merger enforcement practices – the Article examines the three classes of mistakes, their manifestation, and their consequences in antitrust scholarship. It concludes by offering two sets of essential lessons that the behavioral approach already can offer to make antitrust law and policy more realistic and effective in protecting competition: One concerning the value of case-specific evidence in antitrust adjudication and enforcement, the other showing how antitrust law can and should account for systematic and predictable boundedly rational behavior that is neither constant nor uniform.
行为反垄断——将行为偏离严格理性的实证证据应用于反垄断分析——正日益受到法律学者和执法机构的热烈讨论。然而,本文表明,行为反垄断的支持者和反对者都经常从根本上误解其方法论,将具体的经验现象视为广泛的假设假设。由于这种基本的方法错误,学者们在行为反垄断分析中经常犯三类错误:第一,他们没有认识到行为现象的可变性和异质性;其次,他们忽视了市场、企业和其他机构促进和抑制反垄断行为主体理性行为的具体方式;第三,他们错误地将一切偏离标准理性的行为等同于对竞争的损害。在确立了理性假设在当今反垄断中的核心作用,并回顾了整个领域的示范性行为分析——从横向和纵向限制,到垄断,再到合并执法实践——之后,本文考察了反垄断学术中的三类错误、它们的表现及其后果。最后,它提供了行为学方法已经可以提供的两套基本经验,以使反垄断法和政策在保护竞争方面更加现实和有效:一套是关于反垄断裁决和执行中具体案例证据的价值,另一套是关于反垄断法如何能够而且应该解释既不恒定也不统一的系统和可预测的有限理性行为。
{"title":"Understanding Behavioral Antitrust","authors":"Avishalom Tor","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.2293508","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2293508","url":null,"abstract":"Behavioral antitrust – the application to antitrust analysis of empirical evidence of robust behavioral deviations from strict rationality – is increasingly popular and hotly debated by legal scholars and the enforcement agencies alike. This Article shows, however, that both proponents and opponents of behavioral antitrust frequently and fundamentally misconstrue its methodology, treating concrete empirical phenomena as if they were broad hypothetical assumptions. Because of this fundamental methodological error, scholars often make three classes of mistakes in behavioral antitrust analyses: First, they fail to appreciate the variability and heterogeneity of behavioral phenomena; second, they disregard the concrete ways in which markets, firms, and other institutions both facilitate and inhibit rational behavior by antitrust actors; and, third, they erroneously equate all deviations from standard rationality with harm to competition. After establishing the central role of rationality assumptions in present-day antitrust and reviewing illustrative behavioral analyses across the field – from horizontal and vertical restraints, through monopolization, to merger enforcement practices – the Article examines the three classes of mistakes, their manifestation, and their consequences in antitrust scholarship. It concludes by offering two sets of essential lessons that the behavioral approach already can offer to make antitrust law and policy more realistic and effective in protecting competition: One concerning the value of case-specific evidence in antitrust adjudication and enforcement, the other showing how antitrust law can and should account for systematic and predictable boundedly rational behavior that is neither constant nor uniform.","PeriodicalId":47176,"journal":{"name":"Notre Dame Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2013-07-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"91366472","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 18
Originalism and the Colorblind Constitution 原旨主义和无视肤色的宪法
IF 0.9 3区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2013-04-03 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2244610
Michael B. Rappaport
The legal literature on the subject of originalism and affirmative action asserts two propositions: that originalism strongly supports the constitutionality of affirmative action and that the two originalist justices – Justices Scalia and Thomas – appear to be hypocrites for holding that the Constitution forbids government affirmative action. These claims are made by various leading scholars, including Cass Sunstein and Jed Rubenfeld. This Article challenges these claims. First, I argue that the Constitution’s original meaning does not plainly establish that state affirmative action is constitutional. Instead, there is, at the least, a reasonable argument to be made that such affirmative action is unconstitutional. In fact, based on the available evidence, I believe that the case for concluding that the 14th Amendment’s original meaning prohibits affirmative action as to laws within its scope is stronger than the case for concluding that it allows affirmative action. Second, because there is at least a reasonable argument for their position, I argue that the originalist justices are not being inconsistent or hypocritical by supporting a colorblind Constitution. I do argue, however, that the originalist justices should have explained how an originalist methodology could yield the colorblind constitution. The claim that the original meaning supports affirmative action is based on a set of federal statutes passed at the time of the 14th Amendment that are thought to provide race based benefits to blacks. I argue, however, that these statutes do not provide strong evidence that the 14th Amendment allows such race based benefits. These were federal statutes that were not governed by the 14th Amendment and therefore were not directly informative of its meaning. Moreover, most of these statutes, and perhaps virtually all of them, are not necessarily best interpreted as providing race based benefits. In addition to arguing that the evidence for the constitutionality of affirmative action under the 14th Amendment’s original meaning is weak, the Article also contends that there is relatively substantial originalist evidence in favor of the colorblind Constitution. The Article explores two leading and representative theories of the original meaning of the equality component of the 14th Amendment – John Harrison’s interpretation of the Privileges or Immunities Clause and Michelle Saunders’s interpretation of the Equal Protection Clause – to show that they are reasonably interpreted to support the colorblind Constitution.
关于原旨主义和平权行动主题的法律文献提出了两个命题:原旨主义强烈支持平权行动的合宪性,而两位原旨主义大法官——大法官斯卡利亚和托马斯——似乎是伪君子,因为他们认为宪法禁止政府的平权行动。这些主张是由许多著名学者提出的,包括卡斯·桑斯坦和杰德·鲁本菲尔德。本文对这些说法提出了质疑。首先,我认为宪法的原意并没有明确规定州平权行动符合宪法。相反,至少有一个合理的论点可以证明,这种平权行动是违宪的。事实上,根据现有的证据,我认为认为第14修正案的原意禁止在其范围内的平权行动的结论强于认为它允许平权行动的结论。其次,因为他们的立场至少有一个合理的论据,我认为原旨主义的大法官们支持不分肤色的宪法并不是自相矛盾或虚伪的。然而,我确实认为,原旨主义的大法官们应该解释原旨主义的方法论是如何产生无视肤色的宪法的。认为原意支持平权行动的说法是基于第14修正案时期通过的一系列联邦法规,这些法规被认为为黑人提供了基于种族的福利。然而,我认为,这些法规并没有提供强有力的证据,证明第14修正案允许这种基于种族的福利。这些是不受第14修正案管辖的联邦法规,因此不能直接说明其含义。此外,这些法规中的大多数,也许实际上是全部,并不一定最好地被解释为提供基于种族的福利。除了认为根据第14修正案的原意支持平权行动合宪性的证据不足外,该条还认为,有相对大量的原旨证据支持不分肤色的宪法。本文探讨了关于第14修正案中平等部分原意的两种主要和具有代表性的理论——约翰·哈里森对特权或豁免条款的解释和米歇尔·桑德斯对平等保护条款的解释——以表明它们被合理地解释为支持不分肤色的宪法。
{"title":"Originalism and the Colorblind Constitution","authors":"Michael B. Rappaport","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2244610","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2244610","url":null,"abstract":"The legal literature on the subject of originalism and affirmative action asserts two propositions: that originalism strongly supports the constitutionality of affirmative action and that the two originalist justices – Justices Scalia and Thomas – appear to be hypocrites for holding that the Constitution forbids government affirmative action. These claims are made by various leading scholars, including Cass Sunstein and Jed Rubenfeld. This Article challenges these claims. First, I argue that the Constitution’s original meaning does not plainly establish that state affirmative action is constitutional. Instead, there is, at the least, a reasonable argument to be made that such affirmative action is unconstitutional. In fact, based on the available evidence, I believe that the case for concluding that the 14th Amendment’s original meaning prohibits affirmative action as to laws within its scope is stronger than the case for concluding that it allows affirmative action. Second, because there is at least a reasonable argument for their position, I argue that the originalist justices are not being inconsistent or hypocritical by supporting a colorblind Constitution. I do argue, however, that the originalist justices should have explained how an originalist methodology could yield the colorblind constitution. The claim that the original meaning supports affirmative action is based on a set of federal statutes passed at the time of the 14th Amendment that are thought to provide race based benefits to blacks. I argue, however, that these statutes do not provide strong evidence that the 14th Amendment allows such race based benefits. These were federal statutes that were not governed by the 14th Amendment and therefore were not directly informative of its meaning. Moreover, most of these statutes, and perhaps virtually all of them, are not necessarily best interpreted as providing race based benefits. In addition to arguing that the evidence for the constitutionality of affirmative action under the 14th Amendment’s original meaning is weak, the Article also contends that there is relatively substantial originalist evidence in favor of the colorblind Constitution. The Article explores two leading and representative theories of the original meaning of the equality component of the 14th Amendment – John Harrison’s interpretation of the Privileges or Immunities Clause and Michelle Saunders’s interpretation of the Equal Protection Clause – to show that they are reasonably interpreted to support the colorblind Constitution.","PeriodicalId":47176,"journal":{"name":"Notre Dame Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2013-04-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"81017038","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Against Coherence in Statutory Interpretation 反对法律解释的连贯性
IF 0.9 3区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2013-03-11 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2309071
J. D. Ohlendorf
A long tradition in legal theory views the judicial role as centrally including the duty to make the entire body of law “speak with one voice.” This coherence ideal permeates much of the law of statutory interpretation, but one body of doctrine that it has particularly influenced is the set of standards that federal courts use to determine when a newly-enacted statute overrides preexisting legal rules. Determining whether Congress implicitly intends to preempt state law, repeal previous legislation, or displace federal common law is an increasingly important part of the “ordinary diet of the law.” And although, this Article maintains, modern preemption doctrine is largely consistent with the presumptive judicial role in statutory interpretation — that of Congress’s faithful agent — the desire for coherence has motivated the Court to develop standards governing repeal and displacement that deviate from the preemption framework. This Article argues that courts should abandon the quest for coherence in statutory interpretation. In a reasonably pluralistic society like ours, widespread agreement on a coherent ranking of basic values is unlikely. Against this backdrop of deep disagreement, collective social action is purchased only by hammering out specific compromises, and the overall pattern of compromises is unlikely to be coherent. Imposing coherence on the body of law accordingly unravels the very compromises that allowed the legislature to act and, in doing so, both disrespects the process of mutual compromise that made collective action possible and impedes future legislative action. Recognizing the importance of compromise to modern legislation should lead to the rejection of normative coherence as an ideal in statutory interpretation. And, absent some other justification for their current divergence, the doctrinal standards for repeal and displacement should be unified with the current preemption framework.
法律理论中有一个悠久的传统,认为司法角色主要包括使整个法律体系“用一个声音说话”的责任。这种一致性的理想渗透在成文法解释的许多法律中,但它特别影响的一个理论体系是联邦法院用来确定新颁布的法规何时优于先前存在的法律规则的一套标准。确定国会是否有意暗中取代州法律、废除以前的立法或取代联邦普通法,是“法律的日常饮食”中日益重要的一部分。虽然,本文认为,现代优先原则在很大程度上与法定解释中假定的司法角色——国会忠实的代理人——是一致的,但对一致性的渴望促使法院制定了偏离优先框架的废除和取代标准。本文认为,法院应放弃对法律解释连贯性的追求。在我们这样一个相当多元化的社会里,不太可能就基本价值观的连贯排序达成广泛共识。在这种分歧严重的背景下,集体社会行动只能通过敲定具体的妥协来换取,而妥协的总体模式不太可能是连贯的。因此,在法律主体上强加一致性,破坏了允许立法机关采取行动的妥协,这样做既不尊重使集体行动成为可能的相互妥协进程,也阻碍了未来的立法行动。认识到向现代立法妥协的重要性应导致拒绝将规范性一致性作为法律解释的理想。而且,如果没有其他理由来解释目前的分歧,废除和取代的理论标准应该与目前的优先框架统一起来。
{"title":"Against Coherence in Statutory Interpretation","authors":"J. D. Ohlendorf","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2309071","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2309071","url":null,"abstract":"A long tradition in legal theory views the judicial role as centrally including the duty to make the entire body of law “speak with one voice.” This coherence ideal permeates much of the law of statutory interpretation, but one body of doctrine that it has particularly influenced is the set of standards that federal courts use to determine when a newly-enacted statute overrides preexisting legal rules. Determining whether Congress implicitly intends to preempt state law, repeal previous legislation, or displace federal common law is an increasingly important part of the “ordinary diet of the law.” And although, this Article maintains, modern preemption doctrine is largely consistent with the presumptive judicial role in statutory interpretation — that of Congress’s faithful agent — the desire for coherence has motivated the Court to develop standards governing repeal and displacement that deviate from the preemption framework. This Article argues that courts should abandon the quest for coherence in statutory interpretation. In a reasonably pluralistic society like ours, widespread agreement on a coherent ranking of basic values is unlikely. Against this backdrop of deep disagreement, collective social action is purchased only by hammering out specific compromises, and the overall pattern of compromises is unlikely to be coherent. Imposing coherence on the body of law accordingly unravels the very compromises that allowed the legislature to act and, in doing so, both disrespects the process of mutual compromise that made collective action possible and impedes future legislative action. Recognizing the importance of compromise to modern legislation should lead to the rejection of normative coherence as an ideal in statutory interpretation. And, absent some other justification for their current divergence, the doctrinal standards for repeal and displacement should be unified with the current preemption framework.","PeriodicalId":47176,"journal":{"name":"Notre Dame Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2013-03-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"75088293","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Is Expert Evidence Really Different 专家证据真的不同吗
IF 0.9 3区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2013-02-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2210397
F. Schauer, Barbara A. Spellman
Daubert v. Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals, which along with its successor cases has imposed demanding standards of reliability on the admission of scientific and other expert evidence, has transformed much of American evidence law. The Daubert revolution has been subject to strong endorsement and equally strong criticism, but few critics, and none since Daubert, have asked why expert evidence is treated differently in the first place. The common assumption, going back over a century, is that expert evidence is treated differently because of the risk that juries (and judges), not themselves possessed of the relevant expertise, will systematically overvalue such evidence. The overvaluation may be based on ignorance, or on novices being overly impressed by expert credentials and trappings, but the belief in overvaluation as the primary foundation for the distinct treatment of expert evidence persists, generating not only Daubert but also a long history of treating expert evidence specially. It turns out, however, that the longstanding assumption of overvaluation is unsupported by the research. Several decades of research, mostly by psychologists, shows the common assumptions of jury overvaluation of expert evidence to be large unfounded. Indeed, modern research shows that it is eyewitness and other so-called direct evidence that is overvalued. By relying on the erroneous assumption of jury overvaluation of expert testimony and the equally erroneous assumption of non-overvaluation of direct testimony, the law of evidence has drawn a distinction that rests on a false empirical basis. Moreover, insofar as the distinction between expert and other evidence also rests on a distinction between the facts that lay witnesses offer and the inferences (opinions) that come from experts, this distinction is undercut not only by the modern treatment of lay opinion, but by a great deal of philosophical work on the expert-dependence of the judgments that ordinary people make in all aspects of their lives.
道伯特诉梅雷尔陶氏制药公司案及其后续案件对科学证据和其他专家证据的采纳提出了严格的可靠性标准,在很大程度上改变了美国的证据法。道伯特革命一直受到强烈的支持和同样强烈的批评,但很少有批评者,自道伯特以来就没有人问过,为什么首先要区别对待专家证据。一个多世纪以来的普遍假设是,专家证据受到区别对待,因为陪审团(和法官)本身不具备相关的专业知识,因此有可能系统性地高估这些证据。这种高估可能是由于无知,或者是由于新手被专家的资历和外表所蒙蔽,但是,将高估作为区别对待专家证据的主要基础的信念仍然存在,不仅产生了道伯特,而且产生了专门对待专家证据的悠久历史。然而,事实证明,长期以来估值过高的假设并没有得到这项研究的支持。几十年的研究(主要是心理学家的研究)表明,陪审团高估专家证据的普遍假设在很大程度上是没有根据的。事实上,现代研究表明,目击者和其他所谓的直接证据被高估了。依靠陪审团高估专家证词的错误假设和同样错误的对直接证词不高估的假设,证据法得出了一种基于错误经验基础的区分。此外,就专家证据和其他证据之间的区别而言,也取决于外行证人提供的事实和来自专家的推论(意见)之间的区别,这种区别不仅被外行意见的现代处理所削弱,而且被大量关于普通人在生活的各个方面所做的判断依赖于专家的哲学工作所削弱。
{"title":"Is Expert Evidence Really Different","authors":"F. Schauer, Barbara A. Spellman","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2210397","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2210397","url":null,"abstract":"Daubert v. Merrell Dow Pharmaceuticals, which along with its successor cases has imposed demanding standards of reliability on the admission of scientific and other expert evidence, has transformed much of American evidence law. The Daubert revolution has been subject to strong endorsement and equally strong criticism, but few critics, and none since Daubert, have asked why expert evidence is treated differently in the first place. The common assumption, going back over a century, is that expert evidence is treated differently because of the risk that juries (and judges), not themselves possessed of the relevant expertise, will systematically overvalue such evidence. The overvaluation may be based on ignorance, or on novices being overly impressed by expert credentials and trappings, but the belief in overvaluation as the primary foundation for the distinct treatment of expert evidence persists, generating not only Daubert but also a long history of treating expert evidence specially. It turns out, however, that the longstanding assumption of overvaluation is unsupported by the research. Several decades of research, mostly by psychologists, shows the common assumptions of jury overvaluation of expert evidence to be large unfounded. Indeed, modern research shows that it is eyewitness and other so-called direct evidence that is overvalued. By relying on the erroneous assumption of jury overvaluation of expert testimony and the equally erroneous assumption of non-overvaluation of direct testimony, the law of evidence has drawn a distinction that rests on a false empirical basis. Moreover, insofar as the distinction between expert and other evidence also rests on a distinction between the facts that lay witnesses offer and the inferences (opinions) that come from experts, this distinction is undercut not only by the modern treatment of lay opinion, but by a great deal of philosophical work on the expert-dependence of the judgments that ordinary people make in all aspects of their lives.","PeriodicalId":47176,"journal":{"name":"Notre Dame Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2013-02-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"74482255","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 6
期刊
Notre Dame Law Review
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1