首页 > 最新文献

Boston University Law Review最新文献

英文 中文
The Power of Insults 侮辱的力量
IF 1.7 3区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2020-01-01 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3535975
R. Colker
Insults work on both a structural level and a personal level. This Article argues that the economic and political power elite has effectively hurled insults at civil rights activists, plaintiffs, and their lawyers to undermine civil rights reform. It has long been understood that the civil rights community must engage in cultural, political, and legal work to attain effective reforms. But insufficient attention has been paid to how the power elite uses the cultural tool of insults to undermine these reforms. Limitations on effective civil rights reform range from constraints on the private attorney general model of enforcement to the ban on the Legal Services Corporation’s use of class action lawsuits. Insults have played an important and previously unrecognized role in the creation of these limitations. After discussing the undertheorized phenomenon of the power of public insults, this Article presents a case study of defense pleadings filed in accessibility cases brought under the Americans with Disabilities Act. These pleadings reflect how defendants can use insults as part of their litigation strategy to make it difficult for plaintiffs to attain effective relief under a statute designed to create structural reform. Rather than worrying about whether civil rights activists should go high when the power elite goes low, this Article argues that it is crucial that civil rights statutes be constructed with a stronger foundation. Then, plaintiffs will be better  Distinguished University Professor & Heck-Faust Memorial Chair in Constitutional Law, Moritz College of Law, The Ohio State University. I would like to thank the Center for Law, Policy, and Social Science at The Ohio State University for its generous support of this project. I would like to thank attorney and disability activist Amy Robertson for bringing this problem to my attention and helping me find examples. I would also like to thank my Moritz research assistants: MacKenzie Boyd, Stacey Dettwiller, Emily Durell, Kelsie Hendren, and Lindsey Woods. This Article has also benefited from feedback from Amna Akbar, Amy Cohen, Rosalind Dixon, Doron Dorfman, Jasmine Harris, David Levine, Arlene Mayerson, Courtlyn Roser-Jones, Marc Spindelman, and Dan Tokaji, as well as the participants at the 2019 AALS Disability Law Panel, 2019 Berkeley Center for the Study of Law and Society Workshop, 2019 Moritz Faculty Workshop, and 2019 University of New South Wales Faculty Workshop. Finally, this Article has benefited from the research assistance of Stephanie Ziegler of the Moritz Law Library and the secretarial assistance of Allyson Hennelly. 2 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 100:1 able to withstand the barrage of insults they typically encounter when seeking effective relief. Straw houses are too easy to blow down. 2020] THE POWER OF INSULTS 3
侮辱在结构层面和个人层面都起作用。本文认为,经济和政治权力精英实际上对民权活动家、原告及其律师进行了侮辱,以破坏民权改革。人们早就认识到,民权团体必须参与文化、政治和法律工作,以实现有效的改革。但是,对于权力精英如何利用侮辱这一文化工具来破坏这些改革,人们却没有给予足够的关注。对有效的民权改革的限制包括对私人司法部长执行模式的限制,以及对法律服务公司使用集体诉讼的禁令。侮辱在这些限制的产生中发挥了重要的作用,而这是以前未被认识到的。在讨论了公众侮辱的力量这一未被理论化的现象之后,本文对根据《美国残疾人法案》提起的无障碍案件中的辩护诉状进行了案例研究。这些诉状反映了被告如何利用侮辱作为其诉讼策略的一部分,使原告难以根据旨在进行结构性改革的法规获得有效救济。本文并不担心当权力精英走向低谷时,民权活动家是否应该走高,而是认为民权法规的构建必须有一个更坚实的基础。然后,原告将被任命为俄亥俄州立大学莫里茨法学院杰出大学教授和赫克-福斯特宪法纪念主席。我要感谢俄亥俄州立大学法律、政策和社会科学中心对这个项目的慷慨支持。我要感谢律师和残疾人活动家艾米·罗伯逊让我注意到这个问题,并帮助我找到例子。我还要感谢我在莫里茨的研究助理:麦肯齐·博伊德,斯泰西·德特威勒,艾米丽·杜雷尔,凯尔茜·亨德伦和林赛·伍兹。本文还受益于Amna Akbar、Amy Cohen、Rosalind Dixon、Doron Dorfman、Jasmine Harris、David Levine、Arlene Mayerson、Courtlyn rose - jones、Marc Spindelman和Dan Tokaji以及2019年AALS残疾法小组、2019年伯克利法律与社会研究中心研讨会、2019年莫里茨教师研讨会和2019年新南威尔士大学教师研讨会的参与者的反馈。最后,本文得益于莫里茨法律图书馆的斯蒂芬妮·齐格勒(Stephanie Ziegler)的研究协助和艾莉森·亨内利(Allyson Hennelly)的秘书协助。2《波士顿大学法律评论》[卷100:1]能够承受他们在寻求有效救济时通常遇到的一连串侮辱。稻草屋太容易被吹倒了。2020]侮辱的力量
{"title":"The Power of Insults","authors":"R. Colker","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3535975","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3535975","url":null,"abstract":"Insults work on both a structural level and a personal level. This Article argues that the economic and political power elite has effectively hurled insults at civil rights activists, plaintiffs, and their lawyers to undermine civil rights reform. It has long been understood that the civil rights community must engage in cultural, political, and legal work to attain effective reforms. But insufficient attention has been paid to how the power elite uses the cultural tool of insults to undermine these reforms. Limitations on effective civil rights reform range from constraints on the private attorney general model of enforcement to the ban on the Legal Services Corporation’s use of class action lawsuits. Insults have played an important and previously unrecognized role in the creation of these limitations. After discussing the undertheorized phenomenon of the power of public insults, this Article presents a case study of defense pleadings filed in accessibility cases brought under the Americans with Disabilities Act. These pleadings reflect how defendants can use insults as part of their litigation strategy to make it difficult for plaintiffs to attain effective relief under a statute designed to create structural reform. Rather than worrying about whether civil rights activists should go high when the power elite goes low, this Article argues that it is crucial that civil rights statutes be constructed with a stronger foundation. Then, plaintiffs will be better  Distinguished University Professor & Heck-Faust Memorial Chair in Constitutional Law, Moritz College of Law, The Ohio State University. I would like to thank the Center for Law, Policy, and Social Science at The Ohio State University for its generous support of this project. I would like to thank attorney and disability activist Amy Robertson for bringing this problem to my attention and helping me find examples. I would also like to thank my Moritz research assistants: MacKenzie Boyd, Stacey Dettwiller, Emily Durell, Kelsie Hendren, and Lindsey Woods. This Article has also benefited from feedback from Amna Akbar, Amy Cohen, Rosalind Dixon, Doron Dorfman, Jasmine Harris, David Levine, Arlene Mayerson, Courtlyn Roser-Jones, Marc Spindelman, and Dan Tokaji, as well as the participants at the 2019 AALS Disability Law Panel, 2019 Berkeley Center for the Study of Law and Society Workshop, 2019 Moritz Faculty Workshop, and 2019 University of New South Wales Faculty Workshop. Finally, this Article has benefited from the research assistance of Stephanie Ziegler of the Moritz Law Library and the secretarial assistance of Allyson Hennelly. 2 BOSTON UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 100:1 able to withstand the barrage of insults they typically encounter when seeking effective relief. Straw houses are too easy to blow down. 2020] THE POWER OF INSULTS 3","PeriodicalId":47323,"journal":{"name":"Boston University Law Review","volume":"100 1","pages":"1"},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2020-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68604723","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Death of a Copyright 版权的终结
IF 1.7 3区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2019-01-01 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.3524899
Paul R. Gugliuzza
{"title":"Death of a Copyright","authors":"Paul R. Gugliuzza","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.3524899","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3524899","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":47323,"journal":{"name":"Boston University Law Review","volume":"99 1","pages":"2581"},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2019-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68602553","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Is patent enforcement efficient? 专利执行有效吗?
IF 1.7 3区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2018-03-07 DOI: 10.4337/9781788116633.00025
Mark A. Lemley, Robin C. Feldman
Traditional justifications for patents are all based on direct or indirect contribution to the creation of new products. Patents serve the social interest if they provide not just invention, but innovation the world would not otherwise have. Non-practicing entities (“NPEs”) as well as product-producing companies can sometimes provide such innovation, either directly, through working the patent or transferring technology to others who do, or indirectly, when others copy the patented innovation. The available evidence suggests, however, that patent licensing demands and lawsuits from NPEs are normally not cases that involve any of these activities. Some scholars have argued that patents can be valuable even without technology transfer because the ability to exclude others from the market may drive commercialization that would not otherwise occur. We demonstrate that even if various commercialization theories can sometimes justify patent protection, they cannot justify most NPE lawsuits or licensing demands.
传统的专利理由都是基于对新产品创造的直接或间接贡献。如果专利提供的不仅是发明,而且是创新,那么它就符合社会利益。非实践实体(“npe”)以及产品生产公司有时可以提供这种创新,或者直接通过使用专利或将技术转让给其他人,或者当其他人复制专利创新时间接提供这种创新。然而,现有证据表明,npe提出的专利许可要求和诉讼通常不涉及上述任何活动。一些学者认为,即使没有技术转让,专利也可能是有价值的,因为将他人排除在市场之外的能力可能会推动原本不会发生的商业化。我们证明,即使各种商业化理论有时可以证明专利保护的合理性,它们也不能证明大多数NPE诉讼或许可要求的合理性。
{"title":"Is patent enforcement efficient?","authors":"Mark A. Lemley, Robin C. Feldman","doi":"10.4337/9781788116633.00025","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4337/9781788116633.00025","url":null,"abstract":"Traditional justifications for patents are all based on direct or indirect contribution to the creation of new products. Patents serve the social interest if they provide not just invention, but innovation the world would not otherwise have. Non-practicing entities (“NPEs”) as well as product-producing companies can sometimes provide such innovation, either directly, through working the patent or transferring technology to others who do, or indirectly, when others copy the patented innovation. The available evidence suggests, however, that patent licensing demands and lawsuits from NPEs are normally not cases that involve any of these activities. \u0000 \u0000Some scholars have argued that patents can be valuable even without technology transfer because the ability to exclude others from the market may drive commercialization that would not otherwise occur. We demonstrate that even if various commercialization theories can sometimes justify patent protection, they cannot justify most NPE lawsuits or licensing demands.","PeriodicalId":47323,"journal":{"name":"Boston University Law Review","volume":"98 1","pages":"649"},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2018-03-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46526533","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
A Government of Laws and Not of Machines 法律政府而非机器政府
IF 1.7 3区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2018-01-09 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.3098995
E. Berman
The technological tool du jour is known as “machine learning,” a powerful form of data mining that uses mathematical algorithms to construct computer models that provide hidden insights by extracting patterns from enormous historical data sets, often for the purpose of making predictions about the future. Machine learning is all around us — it is used for spam filters, facial recognition, the detection of bank fraud and much more — and it is immensely powerful. It can analyze enormous amounts of information and extract relationships in the data that no human would ever discover. Despite its promise, there are reasons to remain skeptical of using machine learning predictions. Existing critiques of machine learning usually focus on one of two types of concerns — one identifies and aims to address the many potential pitfalls that might result in inaccurate models and the other assesses machine learning’s consistency with norms such as transparency, accountability, and due process. This paper takes a step back from the nuts and bolts questions surrounding the implementation of predictive analytics to consider whether and when it is appropriate to use machine learning to make government decisions in the contexts of national security and law enforcement. It argues that certain characteristics of machine-learning generate tensions with rule-of-law principles and that, as a result, machine-learning predictions can be valuable instruments in some decision-making contexts but constitute a threat to fundamental values in others. The paper concludes that government actors should exploit the benefits of machine learning when they enjoy broad decision-making discretion in making decisions, while eschewing it when government discretion is highly constrained.
目前的技术工具被称为“机器学习”,这是一种强大的数据挖掘形式,它使用数学算法构建计算机模型,通过从庞大的历史数据集中提取模式来提供隐藏的见解,通常是为了预测未来。机器学习无处不在——它被用于垃圾邮件过滤器、面部识别、银行欺诈检测等等——而且它非常强大。它可以分析大量信息,并从数据中提取出人类永远不会发现的关系。尽管它很有前景,但仍有理由对使用机器学习预测持怀疑态度。现有的对机器学习的批评通常集中在两种担忧中的一种——一种是识别并旨在解决可能导致模型不准确的许多潜在陷阱,另一种是评估机器学习与透明度、问责制和正当程序等规范的一致性。本文从围绕预测分析实施的细节问题后退了一步,以考虑在国家安全和执法的背景下,使用机器学习做出政府决策是否合适以及何时合适。它认为,机器学习的某些特征会与法治原则产生紧张关系,因此,机器学习预测在某些决策环境中可能是有价值的工具,但在其他决策环境中对基本价值构成威胁。该论文的结论是,当政府行为者在决策中享有广泛的决策自由裁量权时,他们应该利用机器学习的好处,而当政府自由裁量权受到高度约束时,他们应该避开机器学习。
{"title":"A Government of Laws and Not of Machines","authors":"E. Berman","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.3098995","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.3098995","url":null,"abstract":"The technological tool du jour is known as “machine learning,” a powerful form of data mining that uses mathematical algorithms to construct computer models that provide hidden insights by extracting patterns from enormous historical data sets, often for the purpose of making predictions about the future. Machine learning is all around us — it is used for spam filters, facial recognition, the detection of bank fraud and much more — and it is immensely powerful. It can analyze enormous amounts of information and extract relationships in the data that no human would ever discover. Despite its promise, there are reasons to remain skeptical of using machine learning predictions. Existing critiques of machine learning usually focus on one of two types of concerns — one identifies and aims to address the many potential pitfalls that might result in inaccurate models and the other assesses machine learning’s consistency with norms such as transparency, accountability, and due process. This paper takes a step back from the nuts and bolts questions surrounding the implementation of predictive analytics to consider whether and when it is appropriate to use machine learning to make government decisions in the contexts of national security and law enforcement. It argues that certain characteristics of machine-learning generate tensions with rule-of-law principles and that, as a result, machine-learning predictions can be valuable instruments in some decision-making contexts but constitute a threat to fundamental values in others. The paper concludes that government actors should exploit the benefits of machine learning when they enjoy broad decision-making discretion in making decisions, while eschewing it when government discretion is highly constrained.","PeriodicalId":47323,"journal":{"name":"Boston University Law Review","volume":"98 1","pages":"1277"},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2018-01-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.3098995","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45944462","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 22
Civilizing Criminal Settlements 刑事和解的文明化
IF 1.7 3区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2017-10-22 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2944152
Russell M. Gold, Carissa Byrne Hessick, F. A. Hessick
INTRODUCTIONMost cases today are resolved by settlement. Studies suggest that over ninety percent of criminal and civil cases settle before trial.1 This high rate of settlement is necessary, it is often said, to avoid overwhelming the judicial system.Although settlements are the norm in both the criminal and civil systems, the two systems facilitate settlements in extremely different ways. The criminal system promotes settlements by empowering prosecutors to make the price of going to trial and risking conviction intolerably high for defendants.3 Multiple statutes create different crimes for similar misconduct, and the prosecutor has the power to pick which charges to bring against a defendant.4 Moreover, the sentences prescribed for defendants who are convicted after trial are extremely high. These high penalties are, in some instances, legislatively designed to impose the appropriate punishment only when discounted for guilty pleas. Accordingly, a prosecutor seeking to secure a guilty plea may exert significant pressure on a defendant to enter the plea by charging the defendant with an array of crimes with high sentences, and then offering to reduce or dismiss various charges in exchange for a defendant waiving her right to a trial and all of the procedural protections associated with that trial. These advantages give prosecutors the ability virtually to force defendants to enter into plea bargains.The civil system facilitates settlement in a very different way.5 It does not seek to induce settlements by giving the plaintiffthe power to recover disproportionate damages upon a jury verdict. With few exceptions, plaintiffs may recover only compensation for their harms. Instead of handing one side a bludgeon, the civil system encourages settlement through various procedures. Some of these procedures, such as rules requiring alternative dispute resolution, directly encourage settlement. Others, such as motions for summary judgment and pretrial conferences, facilitate settlement more indirectly. They do so in at least four ways. First, they improve the parties' access to information about their adversaries' case to allow for more informed bargaining. Second, they provide opportunities for the judge or another neutral arbiter to preview her view of the merits to help debias the parties' views of their case. Third, they increase the costs of litigation such that avoiding further procedure saves money for both sides and creates a bargaining range. Fourth, they create moments in which attorneys from both sides simultaneously focus on the case. In addition to facilitating settlements, these procedures help avoid trials by screening out meritless cases, thereby alleviating pressure on defendants to settle the "wrong" cases.The criminal system does not have similar procedures. Most jurisdictions provide no procedures, such as arbitration or mediation, to encourage or facilitate plea bargaining.6 To the contrary, many jurisdictions, including the federal sy
引言今天的大多数案件都是通过和解解决的。研究表明,超过90%的刑事和民事案件在审判前结案。1人们常说,为了避免司法系统不堪重负,这种高结案率是必要的。尽管和解是刑事和民事制度的规范,但这两种制度以极其不同的方式促进和解。刑事系统通过授权检察官使被告接受审判的代价和被定罪的风险高得令人无法容忍,从而促进和解。3多项法规对类似的不当行为规定了不同的罪行,检察官有权选择对被告提起哪些指控。4此外,对经审判而被定罪的被告人规定的刑罚是非常高的。在某些情况下,这些高额惩罚是立法设计的,目的是只有在认罪时才给予适当的惩罚。因此,寻求认罪的检察官可能会对被告施加巨大压力,要求其认罪,方法是指控被告犯有一系列重罪,然后提出减少或驳回各种指控,以换取被告放弃审判权和与审判相关的所有程序保护。这些优势使检察官实际上有能力迫使被告进行辩诉交易。民事制度以一种非常不同的方式促进和解。5它并不试图通过赋予原告在陪审团裁决后收回不成比例的损害赔偿的权力来诱导和解。除了少数例外,原告只能就其伤害获得赔偿。民事制度鼓励通过各种程序解决问题,而不是向一方施压。其中一些程序,例如要求以替代方式解决争端的规则,直接鼓励解决争端。其他动议,如简易判决动议和审前会议,更间接地促进了和解。他们至少有四种方式。首先,他们改善了各方获取对手案件信息的途径,以便进行更知情的谈判。其次,它们为法官或另一位中立的仲裁者提供了预览她对案情的看法的机会,以帮助debias各方对其案件的看法。第三,它们增加了诉讼成本,从而避免进一步的诉讼程序为双方节省了资金,并创造了讨价还价的范围。第四,它们创造了双方律师同时关注案件的时刻。除了促进和解外,这些程序还通过筛选毫无价值的案件来避免审判,从而减轻被告解决“错误”案件的压力。刑事系统没有类似的程序。大多数司法管辖区没有提供仲裁或调解等程序来鼓励或促进认罪谈判。6相反,包括联邦系统在内的许多司法管辖区禁止司法部门参与认罪谈判。7刑事系统通常也没有提供广泛的信息交流或程序,如简易判决,这有助于debias各方,并迫使他们评估自己案件的实力。刑事系统也缺乏在审判前筛选无价值案件的有效机制。这些缺陷使得刑事制度在产生和解的方式上不如民事制度。首先,刑事制度未能促进知情和解。另一方面,刑事系统经常迫使被告解决毫无价值的案件或进行审判,并面临大幅加重刑期的风险。刑事制度基本上允许检察官选择和解条款,而不是根据被告所犯罪行和对他们不利的证据来为和解提供便利。8因为检察官有太多的影响力,被告往往发现自己无法拒绝甚至糟糕的和解条款并进行审判…
{"title":"Civilizing Criminal Settlements","authors":"Russell M. Gold, Carissa Byrne Hessick, F. A. Hessick","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2944152","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2944152","url":null,"abstract":"INTRODUCTIONMost cases today are resolved by settlement. Studies suggest that over ninety percent of criminal and civil cases settle before trial.1 This high rate of settlement is necessary, it is often said, to avoid overwhelming the judicial system.Although settlements are the norm in both the criminal and civil systems, the two systems facilitate settlements in extremely different ways. The criminal system promotes settlements by empowering prosecutors to make the price of going to trial and risking conviction intolerably high for defendants.3 Multiple statutes create different crimes for similar misconduct, and the prosecutor has the power to pick which charges to bring against a defendant.4 Moreover, the sentences prescribed for defendants who are convicted after trial are extremely high. These high penalties are, in some instances, legislatively designed to impose the appropriate punishment only when discounted for guilty pleas. Accordingly, a prosecutor seeking to secure a guilty plea may exert significant pressure on a defendant to enter the plea by charging the defendant with an array of crimes with high sentences, and then offering to reduce or dismiss various charges in exchange for a defendant waiving her right to a trial and all of the procedural protections associated with that trial. These advantages give prosecutors the ability virtually to force defendants to enter into plea bargains.The civil system facilitates settlement in a very different way.5 It does not seek to induce settlements by giving the plaintiffthe power to recover disproportionate damages upon a jury verdict. With few exceptions, plaintiffs may recover only compensation for their harms. Instead of handing one side a bludgeon, the civil system encourages settlement through various procedures. Some of these procedures, such as rules requiring alternative dispute resolution, directly encourage settlement. Others, such as motions for summary judgment and pretrial conferences, facilitate settlement more indirectly. They do so in at least four ways. First, they improve the parties' access to information about their adversaries' case to allow for more informed bargaining. Second, they provide opportunities for the judge or another neutral arbiter to preview her view of the merits to help debias the parties' views of their case. Third, they increase the costs of litigation such that avoiding further procedure saves money for both sides and creates a bargaining range. Fourth, they create moments in which attorneys from both sides simultaneously focus on the case. In addition to facilitating settlements, these procedures help avoid trials by screening out meritless cases, thereby alleviating pressure on defendants to settle the \"wrong\" cases.The criminal system does not have similar procedures. Most jurisdictions provide no procedures, such as arbitration or mediation, to encourage or facilitate plea bargaining.6 To the contrary, many jurisdictions, including the federal sy","PeriodicalId":47323,"journal":{"name":"Boston University Law Review","volume":"97 1","pages":"1607"},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2017-10-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46961625","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
A Particularly Serious Exception to the Categorical Approach 分类法的一个特别严重的例外
IF 1.7 3区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2017-06-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2989913
F. Marouf
IntroductionUnder the Immigration and Nationality Act ("INA"), a noncitizen facing deportation who demonstrates a greater than fifty percent chance of persecution on account of race, religion, nationality, membership in a particular social group, or political opinion may be eligible for a form of relief called "withholding of removal."1 The Refugee Act of 1980 incorporated withholding of removal into the INA in order to comply with the international obligation of nonrefoulement under the 1951 United Nations Convention Relating to the Status of Refugees and the 1967 Protocol Relating to the Status of Refugees (the "Refugee Convention" and the "Protocol," respectively).2 This obligation prohibits the United States from sending someone to a country where her life or freedom would be threatened.3 There are, however, certain exceptions to this prohibition. If it is determined that "the alien, having been convicted by a final judgment of a particularly serious crime is a danger to the community of the United States," then the person is barred from withholding of removal and ordered deported despite a potentially serious risk of persecution or death.4 This statutory provision mirrors the language of the Refugee Convention and is commonly known as the "particularly serious crime" bar.5The test currently used by the Board of Immigration Appeals ("BIA") to determine whether the particularly serious crime bar applies combines an examination of the elements of a crime with an inquiry into some of the individualized facts.6 This approach is inconsistent with the categorical approach for analyzing convictions, which focuses on the elements of the crime. Several recent Supreme Court decisions have addressed the categorical approach, clarifying various splits among the courts of appeals regarding how this approach should be applied and emphasizing the importance of the statutory term "convicted" in triggering a categorical analysis.7 In light of these decisions, an April 2015 opinion by Attorney General Eric Holder vacated an earlier decision by Attorney General Michael Mukasey that had permitted departures from the categorical approach for crimes involving moral turpitude ("CIMTs"); CIMTs are both a ground of deportability and a bar to certain forms of relief from removal under the INA.8 The new opinion underscores that the word "convicted" requires examining the elements of a crime rather than the underlying facts.9This Article argues that the categorical approach should also be applied to the particularly serious crime bar, which uses the word "convicted" but, strikingly, has never been subject to this analysis. The BIA has stated in dicta that the categorical approach does not apply to the particularly serious crime determination because the latter is discretionary.10 Yet appellate courts have not consistently treated this determination as discretionary, nor have most of them explicitly addressed the question of whether the statutory language requires a cate
引言根据《移民和国籍法》(“INA”),面临驱逐的非公民,如果因种族、宗教、国籍、特定社会群体的成员身份或政治观点而受到迫害的可能性超过50%,则有资格获得一种称为“拒绝遣返”的救济。“1 1980年《难民法》将拒绝遣返纳入《移民法》,以履行1951年《联合国难民地位公约》和1967年《难民地位议定书》(分别为“难民公约”和“议定书”)规定的不遣返国际义务.2这项义务禁止美国将某人送往其生命或自由可能受到威胁的国家。3然而,这项禁令也有某些例外。如果确定“被最终判决犯有特别严重罪行的外国人对美国社区构成危险”,则该人被禁止拒绝遣返,并被下令驱逐出境,尽管有可能遭受迫害或死亡。4这一法定条款反映了《难民公约》的语言,通常被称为“特别严重犯罪”条。5移民上诉委员会(“BIA”)目前用于确定特别严重犯罪条是否适用的测试结合了对犯罪要素的审查和对一些个别事实的调查。6这种方法与分析定罪的分类方法不一致,其侧重于犯罪要素。最高法院最近的几项裁决涉及分类法,澄清了上诉法院在如何应用这种方法方面的各种分歧,并强调了“已定罪”这一法定术语在引发分类分析方面的重要性。7鉴于这些裁决,2015年4月,司法部长埃里克·霍尔德的一份意见推翻了司法部长迈克尔·穆凯西早些时候的一项决定,该决定允许偏离对涉及道德败坏的犯罪(“CIMT”)的分类方法;CIMT既是可驱逐出境的理由,也是《移民法》规定的某些形式的驱逐救济的障碍。8新意见强调,“已定罪”一词需要审查犯罪要素,而不是根本事实,从未接受过这种分析。BIA在意见书中表示,分类法不适用于特别严重犯罪的认定,因为后者是自由裁量的。10然而,上诉法院并没有一贯将这一认定视为自由裁量,他们中的大多数人也没有明确解决法定语言是否需要根据最高法院最近的案件进行分类分析的问题。11因此,关于分类方法是否应适用于特别严重犯罪的酒吧,仍然存在一个悬而未决的法律问题。此外,即使法院决定不需要进行分类分析,本条也认为BIA应采用这种方法,以促进一致性和可预测性。本条第一部分解释了明确的方法,讨论了最高法院最近的裁决和Silva Trevino案中“已定罪”这一法定术语的重要性。然后,第一部分讨论了BIA目前用于确定特别严重犯罪标准是否适用的测试,以及该测试如何强调犯罪要素,但又偏离了分类方法。当前测试的主要问题之一是,BIA从未确定定罪构成特别严重犯罪所需的具体要素…
{"title":"A Particularly Serious Exception to the Categorical Approach","authors":"F. Marouf","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2989913","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2989913","url":null,"abstract":"IntroductionUnder the Immigration and Nationality Act (\"INA\"), a noncitizen facing deportation who demonstrates a greater than fifty percent chance of persecution on account of race, religion, nationality, membership in a particular social group, or political opinion may be eligible for a form of relief called \"withholding of removal.\"1 The Refugee Act of 1980 incorporated withholding of removal into the INA in order to comply with the international obligation of nonrefoulement under the 1951 United Nations Convention Relating to the Status of Refugees and the 1967 Protocol Relating to the Status of Refugees (the \"Refugee Convention\" and the \"Protocol,\" respectively).2 This obligation prohibits the United States from sending someone to a country where her life or freedom would be threatened.3 There are, however, certain exceptions to this prohibition. If it is determined that \"the alien, having been convicted by a final judgment of a particularly serious crime is a danger to the community of the United States,\" then the person is barred from withholding of removal and ordered deported despite a potentially serious risk of persecution or death.4 This statutory provision mirrors the language of the Refugee Convention and is commonly known as the \"particularly serious crime\" bar.5The test currently used by the Board of Immigration Appeals (\"BIA\") to determine whether the particularly serious crime bar applies combines an examination of the elements of a crime with an inquiry into some of the individualized facts.6 This approach is inconsistent with the categorical approach for analyzing convictions, which focuses on the elements of the crime. Several recent Supreme Court decisions have addressed the categorical approach, clarifying various splits among the courts of appeals regarding how this approach should be applied and emphasizing the importance of the statutory term \"convicted\" in triggering a categorical analysis.7 In light of these decisions, an April 2015 opinion by Attorney General Eric Holder vacated an earlier decision by Attorney General Michael Mukasey that had permitted departures from the categorical approach for crimes involving moral turpitude (\"CIMTs\"); CIMTs are both a ground of deportability and a bar to certain forms of relief from removal under the INA.8 The new opinion underscores that the word \"convicted\" requires examining the elements of a crime rather than the underlying facts.9This Article argues that the categorical approach should also be applied to the particularly serious crime bar, which uses the word \"convicted\" but, strikingly, has never been subject to this analysis. The BIA has stated in dicta that the categorical approach does not apply to the particularly serious crime determination because the latter is discretionary.10 Yet appellate courts have not consistently treated this determination as discretionary, nor have most of them explicitly addressed the question of whether the statutory language requires a cate","PeriodicalId":47323,"journal":{"name":"Boston University Law Review","volume":"97 1","pages":"1427-1485"},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2017-06-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49223976","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Resurrecting Miranda's Right to Counsel 恢复米兰达的律师权
IF 1.7 3区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2017-05-18 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2970526
David Rossman
IntroductionThe pedantic policeman's Miranda warning:OK. Listen up. I am going to read you your rights. You have the right to remain silent.1 Anything you say can be used against you.2 You have the right to an attorney.3 If you can't afford one, an attorney will be appointed for you.4Now that I've told you what the Supreme Court says I have to say, let me tell you what it really means.That right to silence I told you about, it's not exactly what it seems. It's true that I can't force you to talk. And it's certainly true that anything you say can be used against you. But not much else about it is really what it seems.For starters, I can keep asking you questions until you do make a statement.5 Unless you make it absolutely clear that you want to remain silent, by words and not by actions, nothing prevents me from keeping it up and getting you to say something that we can use in court.6 And you know what, even if you're absolutely clear about wanting to assert this socalled right to silence, I don't have to listen to you.7 I can keep on trying to get you to make a damaging statement, and according to the Supreme Court, I will have done nothing wrong.8 So long as the prosecutor doesn't use the statement itself, I will still be on the right side of the Constitution. Why would I do that? Because, even though you tried to assert your "right to silence," if I ignore you and get you to tell me something that provides a lead to evidence I can use against you or the name of a person who can testify against you, I can build up my case and use what I found in court.9 Plus-and this is the icing on the cake-even if I ignore your clear and unequivocal statement that you want to remain silent and keep asking questions that finally gets you to say something useful to me, the jury will learn about your statement if you take the stand and testify in your own defense.10And if you feel a little let down because the right to silence isn't quite what it seems, boy, wait until I spell out what the right to an attorney means. The first thing I want you to know is that, just like with the right to silence, this so-called right to an attorney won't even come into play unless you are unequivocally clear about what you want.11 And even if you have the presence of mind to come out with that kind of clear statement, I can ignore what you say, just like with the right to silence.12 Yeah, if I do ignore you and keep on questioning you, we can use whatever you say if you take the stand later,13 and we can use any leads you give us to find other evidence that can be introduced at trial.14But that's not the best part about this so-called right to an attorney. Even if you make one of those clear requests for a lawyer that most suspects find so hard to make, you will never, ever get an attorney to talk to you as part of a police interrogation. The best that will happen is that we'll stop questioning you, at least until you bring up the topic of our interrogation again, at which point
学究警察的米兰达警告:好的。听好。我要向你宣读你的权利。你有权保持沉默。1你说的任何话都可能被用来对付你。2你有权请律师。3如果你负担不起,我们会为你指定一名律师。4既然我已经告诉你最高法院说了我必须说的话,让我告诉你这到底意味着什么。我告诉过你的沉默权,并不像看上去的那样。我不能强迫你说话,这是真的。当然,你说的任何话都可能被用来对付你。但它的其他方面并不像看上去的那样。首先,我可以一直问你问题,直到你发表声明。5除非你明确表示你想保持沉默,通过言语而不是行动,否则没有什么能阻止我坚持下去,让你说一些我们可以在法庭上使用的话,我不必听你的。7我可以继续试图让你发表破坏性的声明,根据最高法院的说法,我不会做错任何事。8只要检察官不使用声明本身,我仍然站在宪法的正确一边。我为什么要那样做?因为,即使你试图维护你的“沉默权”,如果我不理你,让你告诉我一些可以用来指控你的证据,或者可以指证你的人的名字,我可以建立我的案件,并利用我在法庭上的发现。9此外,这是锦上添花,即使我无视你明确无误的声明,即你想保持沉默,不断提出问题,最终让你说一些对我有用的话,如果你站出来为自己辩护,陪审团就会了解你的陈述。10如果你因为沉默权与表面上的不一样而感到有点失望,孩子,等我把请律师的权利说清楚吧。我想让你知道的第一件事是,就像沉默权一样,除非你明确自己想要什么,否则这种所谓的请律师的权利甚至不会发挥作用,如果我真的无视你,继续审问你,如果你稍后出庭,我们可以使用你说的任何话,13我们可以利用你给我们的任何线索来寻找其他可以在审判中介绍的证据。14但这并不是所谓的请律师权的最佳部分。即使你对律师提出了大多数嫌疑人都觉得很难提出的明确要求,你也永远不会让律师作为警方审讯的一部分与你交谈。最好的办法是我们停止审问你,至少在你再次提出审问的话题之前,我们可以重新开始审问。15但那时你也找不到律师。任何警察都不可能允许律师进入审讯室。伙计,你要靠自己了。这位迂腐的警察米兰达警告中的一切都是对法律的准确陈述。米兰达学说是沃伦法院崇高的、事后看来极其天真的观点的产物,即其由四部分组成的警告将使审讯过程更加公平。从那以后,米兰达在很大程度上被法官们抛弃了,他们不认同前任对嫌疑人权利和警方审讯之间正确平衡的看法。米兰达代表了20世纪60年代刑事诉讼革命的高潮。16最高法院大胆解决警察逼供问题,引发了长达数十年的争议。然而,在其历史的这一点上,米兰达在智力和实际效果方面都破产了…
{"title":"Resurrecting Miranda's Right to Counsel","authors":"David Rossman","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2970526","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2970526","url":null,"abstract":"IntroductionThe pedantic policeman's Miranda warning:OK. Listen up. I am going to read you your rights. You have the right to remain silent.1 Anything you say can be used against you.2 You have the right to an attorney.3 If you can't afford one, an attorney will be appointed for you.4Now that I've told you what the Supreme Court says I have to say, let me tell you what it really means.That right to silence I told you about, it's not exactly what it seems. It's true that I can't force you to talk. And it's certainly true that anything you say can be used against you. But not much else about it is really what it seems.For starters, I can keep asking you questions until you do make a statement.5 Unless you make it absolutely clear that you want to remain silent, by words and not by actions, nothing prevents me from keeping it up and getting you to say something that we can use in court.6 And you know what, even if you're absolutely clear about wanting to assert this socalled right to silence, I don't have to listen to you.7 I can keep on trying to get you to make a damaging statement, and according to the Supreme Court, I will have done nothing wrong.8 So long as the prosecutor doesn't use the statement itself, I will still be on the right side of the Constitution. Why would I do that? Because, even though you tried to assert your \"right to silence,\" if I ignore you and get you to tell me something that provides a lead to evidence I can use against you or the name of a person who can testify against you, I can build up my case and use what I found in court.9 Plus-and this is the icing on the cake-even if I ignore your clear and unequivocal statement that you want to remain silent and keep asking questions that finally gets you to say something useful to me, the jury will learn about your statement if you take the stand and testify in your own defense.10And if you feel a little let down because the right to silence isn't quite what it seems, boy, wait until I spell out what the right to an attorney means. The first thing I want you to know is that, just like with the right to silence, this so-called right to an attorney won't even come into play unless you are unequivocally clear about what you want.11 And even if you have the presence of mind to come out with that kind of clear statement, I can ignore what you say, just like with the right to silence.12 Yeah, if I do ignore you and keep on questioning you, we can use whatever you say if you take the stand later,13 and we can use any leads you give us to find other evidence that can be introduced at trial.14But that's not the best part about this so-called right to an attorney. Even if you make one of those clear requests for a lawyer that most suspects find so hard to make, you will never, ever get an attorney to talk to you as part of a police interrogation. The best that will happen is that we'll stop questioning you, at least until you bring up the topic of our interrogation again, at which point","PeriodicalId":47323,"journal":{"name":"Boston University Law Review","volume":"73 1","pages":"1129"},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2017-05-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44386374","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Divorce All the Way Down: Local Voice and Family Law's Democratic Deficit 离婚一路向下:地方声音和家庭法的民主赤字
IF 1.7 3区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2017-04-19 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2955198
Sean Williams
Elections for local judges are parodies of democracy, and yet family court judges are tasked with making a series of value judgments in the course of exercising their broad discretion. Those idiosyncratic value judgments determine who gets custody and under what conditions. They determine who deserves more of the marital property and how much of it there is. Over the last thirty-five years, reformers have asked state legislators and appellate courts to cabin judicial discretion by imposing top-down rules that govern these issues. These reforms have uniformly failed. This Article outlines a reform strategy that is novel along two dimensions. First, it turns the attention of reformers downward, not upward. The future of family law reform is local. Second, it introduces family law reformers to a new space along the rules-standards continuum: rules of thumb. Although each of these two innovations — localism and rules of thumb — could be pursued independently, the combination yields important synergies. Empowering cities and school boards to weigh in on family law issues provides them with a new and muscular voice that can amplify the impact of communities that are excluded from existing power structures at the state level. Local influence over family law also generates much-needed policy experiments, creates new opportunities for expressive sorting, and has the potential to reinvigorate citizen engagement with local politics. Channeling this influence through local rules of thumb eliminates over and under inclusion problems and significantly mitigates fears that local politicians will be able to oppress local minorities.
地方法官的选举是民主主义的模仿,而家庭法院法官在行使广泛的自由裁量权的过程中,要做出一系列的价值判断。这些特殊的价值判断决定了谁在什么条件下获得监护权。他们决定谁应该得到更多的婚姻财产,以及有多少财产。在过去的35年里,改革者要求州议员和上诉法院通过实施自上而下的规则来管理这些问题,从而减少司法自由裁量权。这些改革都以失败告终。本文从两个方面概述了一种新颖的改革策略。首先,它将改革者的注意力向下转移,而不是向上。家庭法改革的未来是地方性的。其次,它将家庭法改革者引入了规则-标准连续体的新空间:经验法则。尽管这两种创新——地方主义和经验法则——都可以独立进行,但两者结合起来会产生重要的协同效应。赋予城市和学校董事会在家庭法问题上的发言权,为他们提供了一种新的有力的声音,可以扩大被排除在州一级现有权力结构之外的社区的影响。地方对家庭法的影响也催生了急需的政策实验,为表达性分类创造了新的机会,并有可能重振公民对地方政治的参与。通过当地的经验法则来引导这种影响,消除了过度和缺乏包容的问题,并大大减轻了对当地政客可能压迫当地少数民族的担忧。
{"title":"Divorce All the Way Down: Local Voice and Family Law's Democratic Deficit","authors":"Sean Williams","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2955198","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2955198","url":null,"abstract":"Elections for local judges are parodies of democracy, and yet family court judges are tasked with making a series of value judgments in the course of exercising their broad discretion. Those idiosyncratic value judgments determine who gets custody and under what conditions. They determine who deserves more of the marital property and how much of it there is. Over the last thirty-five years, reformers have asked state legislators and appellate courts to cabin judicial discretion by imposing top-down rules that govern these issues. These reforms have uniformly failed. This Article outlines a reform strategy that is novel along two dimensions. First, it turns the attention of reformers downward, not upward. The future of family law reform is local. Second, it introduces family law reformers to a new space along the rules-standards continuum: rules of thumb. Although each of these two innovations — localism and rules of thumb — could be pursued independently, the combination yields important synergies. Empowering cities and school boards to weigh in on family law issues provides them with a new and muscular voice that can amplify the impact of communities that are excluded from existing power structures at the state level. Local influence over family law also generates much-needed policy experiments, creates new opportunities for expressive sorting, and has the potential to reinvigorate citizen engagement with local politics. Channeling this influence through local rules of thumb eliminates over and under inclusion problems and significantly mitigates fears that local politicians will be able to oppress local minorities.","PeriodicalId":47323,"journal":{"name":"Boston University Law Review","volume":"98 1","pages":"579"},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2017-04-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.2955198","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47988751","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Transparency and Truth during Custodial Interrogations and Beyond 监禁审讯期间及以后的透明度和真相
IF 1.7 3区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2017-01-15 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2907069
S. Klein
My goal in this symposium is not to disrespect the Warren Court Revolution. The Court's constitutionalization of the rules of criminal procedure during the 1960s were quite clearly necessary at the time they were imposed, in large measure to end the miserably unjust treatment of African Americans living in the South, and in part to foster the values of privacy, autonomy, fairness, and protection of the innocent enshrined in the Bill of Rights but ignored by many state criminal justice actors. The three most famous and important decisions by the Warren Court were vital to the health of the criminal justice system when they were rendered. The exclusionary remedy incorporated in Mapp v. Ohio was critical in persuading peace officers to learn about and then protect Fourth Amendment values; the Miranda v. Arizona warnings seemed the only way to limit abusive police behavior at the stationhouse while still encouraging uncompelled confessions, and the right to counsel offered in Gideon v. Wainwright was essential to separating guilty from innocent defendants. Unfortunately, and perhaps somewhat ironically, doctrine concerning the Fourth and Fifth Amendments have been contorted in their definitions and subject to a constant stream of exceptions by the Burger, Rehnquist, and Roberts Courts. They have come to contribute to and in fact embody the now unnecessarily adversarial and deceptive nature of many citizen-peace officer encounters. The upshot of our last fifty years of constitutional criminal procedure rules combined with certain historical events I describe below is that some citizens and law enforcement may view each other as the enemy. This is not useful to law enforcement's primary purpose of protecting us from harm and separating the innocent from the guilty. What are we to do with such a messy and quite frankly depressing state of affairs? At this juncture, it might be preferable to shape rules that are less adversarial and more inquisitorial. It certainly would be an improvement to announce transparent rules. Rather than having decision rules for cases and conduct rules for officers, we need one set of clear and well publicized rules that everyone knows and follows. And that set of rules need not be the same in every jurisdiction, so long as what officers tell citizens is the truth. Confining my remaining comments to the fifth amendment context, in Part II, I argue that the Miranda warnings, regardless of their intent and effect at the time, have become perverse and ought to be retired for five reasons. (1) They are false and deceptive. (2) They assist primarily guilty recividists and the wealthy, all other suspects waive their rights. (3) They fail to achieve either of their stated goals of "adequately and effectively" apprising suspects of their rights and regulating police conduct. Instead, suspects are confused and deceived, and the fact that the Miranda warnings were read essentially guarantees that any subsequent statements are admissib
我这次研讨会的目的不是不尊重沃伦法院革命。20世纪60年代,最高法院将刑事诉讼程序规则宪法化,这在当时显然是必要的,在很大程度上是为了结束生活在南方的非裔美国人遭受的悲惨不公正待遇,在一定程度上是为了促进《权利法案》中所载的隐私、自主、公平和保护无辜者的价值观,但这些价值观被许多州的刑事司法行为者所忽视。沃伦法院作出的三项最著名和最重要的裁决对刑事司法制度的健全至关重要。在马普诉俄亥俄州案中纳入的排他性补救措施对于说服治安官员了解并保护第四修正案的价值观至关重要;米兰达诉亚利桑那州案的警告似乎是限制警察在派出所的虐待行为,同时又能鼓励非强迫招供的唯一办法,而在吉迪恩诉温赖特案中,获得律师帮助的权利对于区分有罪和无辜的被告至关重要。不幸的是,也许有点讽刺的是,有关第四和第五修正案的原则在定义上被扭曲了,并受到伯格、伦奎斯特和罗伯茨法院不断的例外的影响。它们助长并实际上体现了许多公民与和平官员接触中现在不必要的对抗和欺骗性质。我们过去五十年的宪法刑事诉讼规则与我下面描述的某些历史事件相结合的结果是,一些公民和执法部门可能将对方视为敌人。这对执法部门保护我们免受伤害和区分无辜与有罪的主要目的是没有帮助的。面对如此混乱、坦率地说令人沮丧的局面,我们该怎么办呢?在这个关键时刻,最好是制定一些不那么对抗性、更注重探究性的规则。宣布透明的规则当然是一种改进。我们需要的不是案件的裁决规则和官员的行为规则,而是一套清晰、广为人知、人人都知道并遵守的规则。这一套规则不必在每个司法管辖区都是一样的,只要官员告诉公民的是事实。在第二部分中,我将剩下的评论局限于第五修正案的背景下,我认为,米兰达警告,无论其当时的意图和效果如何,已经变得反常,应该被废除,原因有五个。它们是虚假的、具有欺骗性的。他们主要协助惯犯和富人,所有其他嫌疑人放弃他们的权利。(3)它们没有实现“充分和有效地”告知嫌疑人其权利和规范警察行为的既定目标。相反,嫌疑人是被迷惑和欺骗的,米兰达警告被宣读的事实基本上保证了随后的任何陈述都是可接受的,无论它们是否在正当程序“全部情况”检验的意义上是“自愿的”。(四)不能识别和排除虚假供词的。无罪运动已经证明,大多数虚假供词来自青少年和有精神障碍的人,米兰达警告对这些群体无效。它们与历史实践和我们当前共有的道德价值观不相容。在第三部分,我建议司法管辖区开始用更有效和透明的替代方案取代米兰达警告,我认为这一举动在当前最高法院的原则下是允许的。我建议大中型警察部门在其派出所人员中增加一个新的“治安官”职位,由司法部门任命,并用这些治安官对重罪嫌疑人进行更文明的录音讯问来补充或取代警察的拘留讯问。被捕者将被告知,他们没有权利避免某种拘留审讯,并准确描述他们的实际选择。我进一步建议严格禁止制造虚假证据以鼓励嫌疑人招供的做法,并讨论在拘留审讯期间使用欺骗手段,限制纽约公职人员,并将其减少为书面形式。审讯过程的透明度将是一种文明的影响,并将导致更准确的信息。允许地方立法机构制定规范审讯的规则,可以将任何被允许的欺骗行为的责任从警察身上转移出去,从而改善执法人员与他们所服务的公民之间的关系。最后,在第四部分中,我开始想象这样一个世界,在这个世界里,警察只有在绝对必要的时候才会使用欺骗,而且只有在事先得到当地政府官员的同意的情况下才会使用欺骗。 不仅任何警告都是准确的,而且在审讯过程中一些最恶劣的欺骗行为可能也会受到限制。这可能会渗透到卧底行动中,因为许多法院已经在寻找扩大诱捕辩护的方法。如果警官和公民之间的关系得到改善,特别是在少数民族社区,那么使用预测性和社区警务以及其他基于证据的执法工具是可能的。许多可能在搜寻罪犯和预防犯罪方面有效的做法首先依赖于与社区的合作。如果没有一些透明度和信任作为这种关系的基础,这种合作几乎是不可能的。修订《米兰达》将是一个开始。
{"title":"Transparency and Truth during Custodial Interrogations and Beyond","authors":"S. Klein","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2907069","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2907069","url":null,"abstract":"My goal in this symposium is not to disrespect the Warren Court Revolution. The Court's constitutionalization of the rules of criminal procedure during the 1960s were quite clearly necessary at the time they were imposed, in large measure to end the miserably unjust treatment of African Americans living in the South, and in part to foster the values of privacy, autonomy, fairness, and protection of the innocent enshrined in the Bill of Rights but ignored by many state criminal justice actors. The three most famous and important decisions by the Warren Court were vital to the health of the criminal justice system when they were rendered. The exclusionary remedy incorporated in Mapp v. Ohio was critical in persuading peace officers to learn about and then protect Fourth Amendment values; the Miranda v. Arizona warnings seemed the only way to limit abusive police behavior at the stationhouse while still encouraging uncompelled confessions, and the right to counsel offered in Gideon v. Wainwright was essential to separating guilty from innocent defendants. Unfortunately, and perhaps somewhat ironically, doctrine concerning the Fourth and Fifth Amendments have been contorted in their definitions and subject to a constant stream of exceptions by the Burger, Rehnquist, and Roberts Courts. They have come to contribute to and in fact embody the now unnecessarily adversarial and deceptive nature of many citizen-peace officer encounters. \u0000The upshot of our last fifty years of constitutional criminal procedure rules combined with certain historical events I describe below is that some citizens and law enforcement may view each other as the enemy. This is not useful to law enforcement's primary purpose of protecting us from harm and separating the innocent from the guilty. What are we to do with such a messy and quite frankly depressing state of affairs? At this juncture, it might be preferable to shape rules that are less adversarial and more inquisitorial. It certainly would be an improvement to announce transparent rules. Rather than having decision rules for cases and conduct rules for officers, we need one set of clear and well publicized rules that everyone knows and follows. And that set of rules need not be the same in every jurisdiction, so long as what officers tell citizens is the truth. \u0000Confining my remaining comments to the fifth amendment context, in Part II, I argue that the Miranda warnings, regardless of their intent and effect at the time, have become perverse and ought to be retired for five reasons. (1) They are false and deceptive. (2) They assist primarily guilty recividists and the wealthy, all other suspects waive their rights. (3) They fail to achieve either of their stated goals of \"adequately and effectively\" apprising suspects of their rights and regulating police conduct. Instead, suspects are confused and deceived, and the fact that the Miranda warnings were read essentially guarantees that any subsequent statements are admissib","PeriodicalId":47323,"journal":{"name":"Boston University Law Review","volume":"97 1","pages":"993"},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2017-01-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.2907069","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48185033","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Un)Reasonable Royalties 联合国)合理的使用费
IF 1.7 3区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2016-12-12 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2884387
M. Risch
Though reasonable royalty damages are ubiquitous in patent litigation, they are only one-hundred years old. But in that time they have become deeply misunderstood. This Article returns to the development and origins of reasonable royalties, exploring both why and how courts originally assessed them.It then turns a harsh eye toward all that we think we know about reasonable royalties. No current belief is safe from criticism, from easy targets such as the 25% “rule of thumb” to fundamental dogma such as the hypothetical negotiation. In short, the Article concludes that we are doing it wrong, and have been for some time.This Article is agnostic as to outcome; departure from traditional methods can and has led to both over- and under-compensation. But it challenges those who support departure from historic norms—all the while citing cases from the same time period—to justify new rules, many of which fail any economic justification.
虽然合理的特许权使用费损害赔偿在专利诉讼中无处不在,但它们只有一百年的历史。但在这段时间里,他们被深深地误解了。本文回归到合理版税的发展和起源,探讨法院最初评估它们的原因和方式。然后,它对我们所知道的关于合理版税的一切都持严厉的态度。从25%的“经验法则”这样的简单目标,到假设谈判这样的基本教条,目前没有一种信念是可以免于批评的。简而言之,这篇文章的结论是,我们的做法是错误的,而且已经有一段时间了。这篇文章对结果是不可知论的;对传统方法的背离可能而且已经导致薪酬过高或过低。但它挑战了那些支持背离历史规范的人——他们总是引用同一时期的案例——来为新规则辩护,其中许多规则没有任何经济理由。
{"title":"Un)Reasonable Royalties","authors":"M. Risch","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2884387","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2884387","url":null,"abstract":"Though reasonable royalty damages are ubiquitous in patent litigation, they are only one-hundred years old. But in that time they have become deeply misunderstood. This Article returns to the development and origins of reasonable royalties, exploring both why and how courts originally assessed them.It then turns a harsh eye toward all that we think we know about reasonable royalties. No current belief is safe from criticism, from easy targets such as the 25% “rule of thumb” to fundamental dogma such as the hypothetical negotiation. In short, the Article concludes that we are doing it wrong, and have been for some time.This Article is agnostic as to outcome; departure from traditional methods can and has led to both over- and under-compensation. But it challenges those who support departure from historic norms—all the while citing cases from the same time period—to justify new rules, many of which fail any economic justification.","PeriodicalId":47323,"journal":{"name":"Boston University Law Review","volume":"59 1","pages":"187"},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2016-12-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68416806","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 16
期刊
Boston University Law Review
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1