首页 > 最新文献

Inquiry-An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy最新文献

英文 中文
Grounding physicalism and ‘Moorean’ connections 基础物理主义和“摩尔式”联系
2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-10-17 DOI: 10.1080/0020174x.2023.2253863
Alex Moran
Grounding physicalism is the doctrine that mental properties are metaphysically grounded in underlying physical properties. The present paper develops a novel challenge to this view derived from two main claims: one of them concerning the natures of phenomenal properties, the other concerning the relation between grounding and essence. The central goal of the paper is to explain how grounding physicalists can meet this challenge by means of appealing to grounding laws, thereby making room for ‘Moorean’ connections between distinct types of property.
基础物理主义是指精神属性在形而上学上以潜在的物理属性为基础的学说。本文从两个主要观点出发,对这一观点提出了新的挑战:一个是关于现象性质的本质,另一个是关于基础与本质之间的关系。本文的中心目标是解释基础物理学家如何通过诉诸基础定律来应对这一挑战,从而为不同类型的属性之间的“摩尔式”联系腾出空间。
{"title":"Grounding physicalism and ‘Moorean’ connections","authors":"Alex Moran","doi":"10.1080/0020174x.2023.2253863","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174x.2023.2253863","url":null,"abstract":"Grounding physicalism is the doctrine that mental properties are metaphysically grounded in underlying physical properties. The present paper develops a novel challenge to this view derived from two main claims: one of them concerning the natures of phenomenal properties, the other concerning the relation between grounding and essence. The central goal of the paper is to explain how grounding physicalists can meet this challenge by means of appealing to grounding laws, thereby making room for ‘Moorean’ connections between distinct types of property.","PeriodicalId":47504,"journal":{"name":"Inquiry-An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135943956","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Duties of social identity? Intersectional objections to Sen’s identity politics 社会认同的责任?对森的身份政治的交叉反对
2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-10-17 DOI: 10.1080/0020174x.2023.2270527
Alex Madva, Katherine Gasdaglis, Shannon Doberneck
ABSTRACTAmartya Sen argues that sectarian discord and violence are fueled by confusion about the nature of identity, including the pervasive tendency to see ourselves as members of singular social groups standing in opposition to other groups (e.g. Democrat vs. Republican, Muslim vs. Christian, etc.). Sen defends an alternative model of identity, according to which we all inevitably belong to a plurality of discrete identity groups (including ethnicities, classes, genders, races, religions, careers, hobbies, etc.) and are obligated to choose, in any given context, which among our multiple affiliations to prioritize. While Sen’s model of discrete identity prioritization is a clear advance over single-factor accounts, it overlooks significant lessons about identity from over 150 years of scholarship by feminists of color. In ignoring the experiences of women of color, Sen’s model falsely assumes that identities are in-principle separable for the purposes of practical deliberation; and, in obligating individuals to make such identity-based ‘reasoned choices,’ Sen’s model forces those with multiply marginalized identities to choose from a set of externally defined identity options, none of which sufficiently captures their experiences.KEYWORDS: Social IdentityAmartya Senintersectionalityfeminism AcknowledgmentsThis paper has benefited greatly from audiences at the Mind, Language, and Social Change Conference in Knoll Farm, VT in August 2021, especially from Gabbrielle Johnson, Kate Ritchie, Umrao Sethi, Rima Basu, Jessica Moss, Michael Brownstein, Daniel Kelly, Ellen Fridland, Daniel Harris, Jonathan Phillips, and Peter Epstein; at the Philosophy of Social Science Roundtable in Vancouver in May 2017, especially from Fiona Jenkins, Georgie Warnke, and Derick Hughes; and at the Pacific Division meeting of the American Philosophical Association in April 2015, where Ranjoo Herr provided extremely helpful and incisive commentary.Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1 Among work contemporaneous with Sen’s, and as we will gesture toward in §6, we are most sympathetic with, and influenced by, Alcoff (Citation2006; but see also Afshar, Aitken, and Franks Citation2005; Appiah Citation2007; Barvosa Citation2008; Phillips Citation2009; Warnke Citation2008).2 Sen’s Identity and Violence is cited over 5,550 times on Google Scholar but typically just in passing or sloganized form. We cite theorists who engage more carefully with his work on identity in what follows.3 We find this example phenomenologically implausible (must a person choose rather than discover their rooting preference?) and return to related concerns in §2.2.4 See Wills (Citation2018) for discussion of the shortcomings of class-reductionist readings of Marx. Wills (Citation2018, 236, original emphasis) also draws a key distinction between class exploitation and ‘classism’: ‘Workers do experience ‘classism’ – oppression on the basis of their workin
,威尔克森(citation) 2009 .19甚至就印巴分界而言,Parul Sehgal (Citation2022)提出了一个令人信服的观点,即暴力的爆发并不能最好地理解为印度教徒和穆斯林之间的单一反对因素。他认为,它还必须被理解为与性别和性行为交叉,因为它涉及普遍的宗教间和宗教内的“性恐怖主义”。虽然对单一模式的明确支持很难找到,但相比之下,我们可以找到许多案例,这些案例似乎包含了对严格优先级的明确支持,但这些例子往往给我们留下深刻的印象,因为它们是理性选择或理性说服的结果,就像在詹姆斯和梅斯呼吁优先考虑他们的美国印第安人身份而不是他们的性别,或者呼吁优先考虑阶级而不是种族(§1),以及我们在以下讨论的案例我们并不是说所有的暴力政治行为都是“极端主义”。有些是反抗压迫的正当行为。我们的观点只是,个人经常被招募到支持严格优先顺序的群体中,通过理性的、叙述的过程(而不是突然的、无意识的屠杀)参见,例如,约翰S.莫斯比(引文1907)给塞缪尔查普曼的信。或者,也许像莫斯比这样的南方人(假设我们可以从表面上理解他们后来对奴隶制的否认)应该把他们的群体关系放在一起,只是做正义所要求的事情。见注8.22也见与Gries及其同事的目标文章一起发表的评论和答复调查委员会的一名裁判表示,对森的这种评论是人身攻击。事实并非如此。它们是我们未能找到Sen引用的任何书目证据或以其他方式参与交叉学术的报告。
{"title":"Duties of social identity? Intersectional objections to Sen’s identity politics","authors":"Alex Madva, Katherine Gasdaglis, Shannon Doberneck","doi":"10.1080/0020174x.2023.2270527","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174x.2023.2270527","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTAmartya Sen argues that sectarian discord and violence are fueled by confusion about the nature of identity, including the pervasive tendency to see ourselves as members of singular social groups standing in opposition to other groups (e.g. Democrat vs. Republican, Muslim vs. Christian, etc.). Sen defends an alternative model of identity, according to which we all inevitably belong to a plurality of discrete identity groups (including ethnicities, classes, genders, races, religions, careers, hobbies, etc.) and are obligated to choose, in any given context, which among our multiple affiliations to prioritize. While Sen’s model of discrete identity prioritization is a clear advance over single-factor accounts, it overlooks significant lessons about identity from over 150 years of scholarship by feminists of color. In ignoring the experiences of women of color, Sen’s model falsely assumes that identities are in-principle separable for the purposes of practical deliberation; and, in obligating individuals to make such identity-based ‘reasoned choices,’ Sen’s model forces those with multiply marginalized identities to choose from a set of externally defined identity options, none of which sufficiently captures their experiences.KEYWORDS: Social IdentityAmartya Senintersectionalityfeminism AcknowledgmentsThis paper has benefited greatly from audiences at the Mind, Language, and Social Change Conference in Knoll Farm, VT in August 2021, especially from Gabbrielle Johnson, Kate Ritchie, Umrao Sethi, Rima Basu, Jessica Moss, Michael Brownstein, Daniel Kelly, Ellen Fridland, Daniel Harris, Jonathan Phillips, and Peter Epstein; at the Philosophy of Social Science Roundtable in Vancouver in May 2017, especially from Fiona Jenkins, Georgie Warnke, and Derick Hughes; and at the Pacific Division meeting of the American Philosophical Association in April 2015, where Ranjoo Herr provided extremely helpful and incisive commentary.Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1 Among work contemporaneous with Sen’s, and as we will gesture toward in §6, we are most sympathetic with, and influenced by, Alcoff (Citation2006; but see also Afshar, Aitken, and Franks Citation2005; Appiah Citation2007; Barvosa Citation2008; Phillips Citation2009; Warnke Citation2008).2 Sen’s Identity and Violence is cited over 5,550 times on Google Scholar but typically just in passing or sloganized form. We cite theorists who engage more carefully with his work on identity in what follows.3 We find this example phenomenologically implausible (must a person choose rather than discover their rooting preference?) and return to related concerns in §2.2.4 See Wills (Citation2018) for discussion of the shortcomings of class-reductionist readings of Marx. Wills (Citation2018, 236, original emphasis) also draws a key distinction between class exploitation and ‘classism’: ‘Workers do experience ‘classism’ – oppression on the basis of their workin","PeriodicalId":47504,"journal":{"name":"Inquiry-An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135995970","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Nothing explains essence 什么也解释不了本质
2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-10-17 DOI: 10.1080/0020174x.2023.2269576
Taylor-Grey Miller
ABSTRACTI argue that there is significant pressure to adopt a domain-fixing conception of essence if one wants to vindicate the claim that essentialist facts are proper ends of metaphysical explanation. I then argue that the zero-ground account best accommodates a domain-fixing view. I then respond to a number of objections to the zero-ground account and show how they can be met. I conclude that there is good reason to give the zerogrounding view more serious attention than it has received.KEYWORDS: EssencegroundexplanationZero-Groundmodality Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1 For discussion of fundamentality see Fine (Citation2001), Schaffer (Citation2010), Bennett (Citation2017) and Sider (Citation2011), among others.2 For discussion of zero-grounding see Fine (Citation2012), Litland (Citation2017), Donaldson (Citation2017), Muñoz (Citation2020), and more recently, Kappes (Citation2020a; Citation2020b; Citation2022). The notion of being generated from nothing may be stronger in the case of grounding than in corresponding case of theorems. Given that validity is monotonic, it follows that a theorem is also derivable from any set of premises. But because ground is not monotonic, it may turn out that a zero-grounded fact is only grounded in the zero-ground.3 I’m not the first to advance the zero-grounding view in relation to the explanatory distinctiveness of the essentialist facts. Miller (Citation2022) and Kappes (Citation2020a) both argue that this view is motivated by taking the essentialist facts to play the role of explanatory links. These sorts of considerations will not play a particularly significant role in the argument of this paper.4 I borrow this term from Raven (Citation2020).5 In particular that it is asymmetric, transitive, irreflexive. We thus obtain a partial ordering over the domain of facts. I note the standard assumptions here to help the reader gain a sense of what grounding is supposed to be, although nothing I say in what follows hangs on these assumptions being wholly vindicated across all instances of grounding. I also take partial ground to be definable in terms of full ground. P is a partial ground for Q just in case P on its own or together with some other facts fully grounds Q. See Fine (Citation2012, 50).6 See e.g., Mason’s (Citation1967) translation of the Leibniz-Arnauld Correspondence p. 13–17 for a rich expression of Leibniz’s view.7 One must, however, be careful here. On this framing, it appears that objects can have essences without existing which engages with some rather delicate issues about being, existence, and quantification, the discussion of which lie beyond the scope of the present paper. In particular, such a conception appears in tension with what Williamson calls the being constraint. Roughly, the being constraint says that having properties requires existence, and it corresponds model-theoretically to the domain constraint; that all predicate e
摘要本文认为,如果要证明“本质主义事实是形而上学解释的正当目的”这一主张是正确的,那么就有很大的压力采用一种固定领域的本质概念。然后,我认为零基础账户最适合领域固定观点。然后,我回应了一些对零基础账户的反对意见,并展示了如何满足这些反对意见。我的结论是,有充分的理由给予零基础观点比它所受到的更认真的关注。关键词:本质基础解释零基础披露声明作者未报告潜在利益冲突。注1关于基本面的讨论见Fine (Citation2001)、Schaffer (Citation2010)、Bennett (Citation2017)和Sider (Citation2011)等有关零接地的讨论,请参见Fine (Citation2012), Litland (Citation2017), Donaldson (Citation2017), Muñoz (Citation2020),以及最近的Kappes (Citation2020a;Citation2020b;Citation2022)。从无到有的概念在根据的情况下可能比在相应的定理的情况下更有力。假设有效性是单调的,那么定理也可以从任何前提集推导出来。但是因为根据不是单调的,所以一个零根据的事实可能只在零根据中成立我并不是第一个提出零基础观点的人关于本质主义事实的解释性。Miller (Citation2022)和Kappes (Citation2020a)都认为,这种观点的动机是采取本质主义事实来发挥解释环节的作用。这类考虑在本文的论证中不会起特别重要的作用我从Raven (Citation2020)那里借用了这个术语特别是它是不对称的,传递的,非自反的。这样我们就得到了事实域上的偏序。我注意到这里的标准假设是为了帮助读者了解什么是基础,尽管我在下面所说的一切都不依赖于这些假设在所有基础实例中被完全证明是正确的。我也让部分接地可以用全接地来定义。P是Q的部分根据,只是在P单独或与其他事实一起充分证明Q的情况下。参见Fine (Citation2012, 50)例如,参见梅森(Citation1967)翻译的莱布尼茨-阿诺德通信第13-17页,以获得莱布尼茨观点的丰富表达然而,在这里必须小心。在这个框架下,似乎物体可以有本质而不存在,这涉及到一些关于存在、存在和量化的相当微妙的问题,对这些问题的讨论超出了本文的范围。特别地,这样一个概念出现在Williamson所谓的存在约束的张力中。大致说来,存在约束是指具有属性需要存在,它在模型上与领域约束相对应;所有谓词的扩展都是从那个世界的域中得出的。参见Williamson (Citation2013)§4.1进行批判性讨论这个例子是从Kment (Citation2014)§6.2.1.9借来的,值得在这里停下来指出,以这种方式调用本质看起来像是诉诸于文献中经常提到的“本质基础先验”(EGP) s:□xP p P.这一原则在形而上学家在本质和基础方面理论化的重要部分或最近的工作中显得很重要。然而,它最近受到了更多的审查。参见Kment (Citation2014)和Rosen (Citation2015)对EGP的支持讨论,以及Glazier (Citation2017)和Zylstra (Citation2019)的反对意见。在这里,对于原理所表示的概括的真理性,并没有采取任何立场。只要本质理论家认为本质以上述方式在解释上是独特的,他们就会认识到大量EGP实例的真实性。我们现在感兴趣的是发展一种关于本质的解释,以解释它是如何发挥上述在大量这类例子中所展示的解释作用的。尽管目前没有人对EGP中所表达的概括采取立场,但值得注意的是,如果这种概括是正确的,那么它将与接下来几节中所发展的论点密切相关。正如Kappes (Citation2020a)所指出的那样,根据EGP,对零接地账户开放的压力很大。以下是对卡普斯论点的简要概括。假设本质迭代,本质事实在进一步(迭代)的本质事实中被解释(类似于EGP的方式)。但卡普斯认为,将被解释的本质事实作为被解释的本质事实获得的原因是错误的。相反,他的建议是,解释本质的事实是他所谓的“空基解释”的一个环节,它从无中生有地产生了被解释的本质。 这与本文件中提出的建议类似。卡普斯把从无到有产生本质主义事实的解释性联系作为进一步的本质主义事实,而目前的建议表明,这种联系是零基础的一个实例。卡普斯(Citation2020a)预见到了这一点,他后来辩称,如果我们不满意他把本质主义事实作为解释联系的说法,我们或许可以求助于零基础的基础,以此来理解本质状态解释背后的直觉。理解本文目的的一种方法是增加我们对Kappes (Citation2020a)声明的信心Fine (Citation2005)的特点是超脱世俗,而不是世俗。对于Fine来说,一个真理/事实是世俗的,只要它在世界的环境中被证明是真实的。它是非世俗的,只是以防它是真实的,不管/在形而上学上独立于世界的环境。这一区别是作为一种模态平行于在某一时刻为真和永远为真之间的区别Raven最近明确表示,他并不打算将此作为本质本身的概念。更确切地说,它是关于某些本质主义事实的根据的某种观点。它的目的是开放其他本质主义事实是否不是建立在生成事实的基础上。然而,值得注意的是,它们可能是令人满意的止点,只不过意义不同于目前正在讨论的止点。Glazier部分是出于对作为解释目的的基础理论理解方式的不满,提出了本质主义解释作为一种独特的解释。在他看来,本质主义事实可以作为解释的终点,如果它们不允许进一步的本质主义解释。参见Glazier (Citation2017)。很可能的情况是,生成观点的支持者仍然可以坚持,本质主义事实在这种特殊的非基于理论的意义上具有解释上的独特性。感谢一位匿名的裁判强调了这一点格雷泽(Citation2017)反对本质主义事实的根本性的论点采用了这条路线这个类比是由于Fine (Citation2012)和Litland (Citation2017)一些人认为,禁足并不意味着必要。例如,Leuenberger (Citation2014)和Skiles (Citation2015)。典型的担忧源于难以讲述一个动机良好的故事,即什么是某些普遍概括的基础。我发现这类担忧通常不会让人动容。关于令人信服的回答,见DeRosset (Citation2023,第8章第3节)这通常是根据模态重组原则兑现的。重组应该遵循休谟的原则,即在完全不同的实体之间没有必要的联系。参见Lewis (Citation1999;Citation2001)。有一个有趣的问题是,如何确定两个实体(在本例中是事实)何时可能无法重叠。Dixon (Citation2016)提出了一种关于事实之间重叠的特征,他称之为groverlap。如果两个事实是不同的,它们就会在以下情况下重叠:(1)其中一个部分地为另一个提供依据,或(2)它们有共同的依据。基本事实当然不会消失。在此基础上,人们可以试图直接为基本事实证明模态重组原则是正确的。关于这类论点的讨论见王(Citation2016).17在这里,我们依靠接地机的比喻来兑现零接地的概念。尽管隐喻具有强大的力量,但如果能对
{"title":"Nothing explains essence","authors":"Taylor-Grey Miller","doi":"10.1080/0020174x.2023.2269576","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174x.2023.2269576","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTI argue that there is significant pressure to adopt a domain-fixing conception of essence if one wants to vindicate the claim that essentialist facts are proper ends of metaphysical explanation. I then argue that the zero-ground account best accommodates a domain-fixing view. I then respond to a number of objections to the zero-ground account and show how they can be met. I conclude that there is good reason to give the zerogrounding view more serious attention than it has received.KEYWORDS: EssencegroundexplanationZero-Groundmodality Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1 For discussion of fundamentality see Fine (Citation2001), Schaffer (Citation2010), Bennett (Citation2017) and Sider (Citation2011), among others.2 For discussion of zero-grounding see Fine (Citation2012), Litland (Citation2017), Donaldson (Citation2017), Muñoz (Citation2020), and more recently, Kappes (Citation2020a; Citation2020b; Citation2022). The notion of being generated from nothing may be stronger in the case of grounding than in corresponding case of theorems. Given that validity is monotonic, it follows that a theorem is also derivable from any set of premises. But because ground is not monotonic, it may turn out that a zero-grounded fact is only grounded in the zero-ground.3 I’m not the first to advance the zero-grounding view in relation to the explanatory distinctiveness of the essentialist facts. Miller (Citation2022) and Kappes (Citation2020a) both argue that this view is motivated by taking the essentialist facts to play the role of explanatory links. These sorts of considerations will not play a particularly significant role in the argument of this paper.4 I borrow this term from Raven (Citation2020).5 In particular that it is asymmetric, transitive, irreflexive. We thus obtain a partial ordering over the domain of facts. I note the standard assumptions here to help the reader gain a sense of what grounding is supposed to be, although nothing I say in what follows hangs on these assumptions being wholly vindicated across all instances of grounding. I also take partial ground to be definable in terms of full ground. P is a partial ground for Q just in case P on its own or together with some other facts fully grounds Q. See Fine (Citation2012, 50).6 See e.g., Mason’s (Citation1967) translation of the Leibniz-Arnauld Correspondence p. 13–17 for a rich expression of Leibniz’s view.7 One must, however, be careful here. On this framing, it appears that objects can have essences without existing which engages with some rather delicate issues about being, existence, and quantification, the discussion of which lie beyond the scope of the present paper. In particular, such a conception appears in tension with what Williamson calls the being constraint. Roughly, the being constraint says that having properties requires existence, and it corresponds model-theoretically to the domain constraint; that all predicate e","PeriodicalId":47504,"journal":{"name":"Inquiry-An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135994900","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Encapsulation, inference and utterance interpretation 封装、推理和话语解释
2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-10-13 DOI: 10.1080/0020174x.2023.2267084
Nicholas Allott
While utterance interpretation is standardly understood as context-sensitive inference, there are prima facie reasons to doubt it is fully unencapsulated. First, utterance interpretation is normally fast and automatic, while it has been argued that unencapsulated processes are slow and reflective. Secondly, certain illusions appear to show that the processing of utterances is unrevisable in light of further information. I argue that these reasons are not conclusive, and utterance interpretation relies on indefinite tracts of background knowledge and contextual information.
虽然话语解释通常被理解为上下文敏感推理,但有初步的理由怀疑它是完全未封装的。首先,话语解释通常是快速和自动的,而非封装的过程则是缓慢和反思的。其次,某些错觉似乎表明,根据进一步的信息,话语的加工是不可修改的。我认为这些原因不是决定性的,话语解释依赖于不确定的背景知识和语境信息。
{"title":"Encapsulation, inference and utterance interpretation","authors":"Nicholas Allott","doi":"10.1080/0020174x.2023.2267084","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174x.2023.2267084","url":null,"abstract":"While utterance interpretation is standardly understood as context-sensitive inference, there are prima facie reasons to doubt it is fully unencapsulated. First, utterance interpretation is normally fast and automatic, while it has been argued that unencapsulated processes are slow and reflective. Secondly, certain illusions appear to show that the processing of utterances is unrevisable in light of further information. I argue that these reasons are not conclusive, and utterance interpretation relies on indefinite tracts of background knowledge and contextual information.","PeriodicalId":47504,"journal":{"name":"Inquiry-An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135853009","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Why Twitter does not gamify communication 为什么Twitter没有将交流游戏化
2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-10-13 DOI: 10.1080/0020174x.2023.2261489
Jacob Browning, Zed Adams
ABSTRACTA central question for understanding social media platforms is whether the design of these systems is itself responsible for the harmful effects they have on society. Do these systems push users toward unhealthy forms of engagement? Is there something inherently toxic about the design that distorts who we are when we use it? In a recent paper, Thi Nguyen argues that the design of Twitter is responsible for many of its most toxic outcomes. Nguyen’s argument is based on an analogy between Twitter and games. He argues that Twitter’s game-like features encourage users to rack up Likes and Retweets rather than engaging in the rich and subtle activity of communication. For Nguyen, this drive for high scores leads to many of the toxic effects of the platform. In this paper, we critique Nguyen’s argument. We contend that, in a crucial respect that matters, Twitter is not game-like. We show that the apparent plausibility of Nguyen’s argument rests upon overlooking this crucial disanalogy. Moreover, drawing out how Nguyen’s analogy breaks down makes clear not just that his account fails to explain Twitter’s toxicity, but also that it actively occludes the design choices that have negative effects on its users.KEYWORDS: Social mediaphilosophy of technologynormativity of artifactsargument by analogy Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1 Unless noted, all emphases are in original.2 Another objection might arise at this point: what if there are games that do not have constitutive rules that sculpt temporary agency? This is an interesting objection, but it is first-and-foremost an objection to Nguyen’s account of games. If there are games that do not have constitutive rules that sculpt temporary agency, Nguyen would have to draw his proposed analogy between Twitter and games somewhere else.
理解社交媒体平台的核心问题是,这些系统的设计本身是否应对它们对社会的有害影响负责。这些系统是否将用户推向不健康的参与形式?当我们使用设计时,是否存在某种固有的有毒物质扭曲了我们是谁?Thi Nguyen在最近的一篇论文中指出,Twitter的设计导致了许多最糟糕的结果。Nguyen的观点是基于Twitter和游戏之间的类比。他认为,Twitter的游戏式功能鼓励用户累积点赞和转发,而不是参与丰富而微妙的交流活动。对于Nguyen来说,这种对高分的追求导致了这个平台的许多负面影响。在本文中,我们对Nguyen的论点进行了批判。我们认为,在一个至关重要的方面,Twitter不像游戏。我们表明,阮的论点表面上的合理性是建立在忽视这一关键的差异之上的。此外,通过分析Nguyen的类比是如何被打破的,我们可以清楚地看到,他的描述不仅无法解释Twitter的毒性,而且还积极地屏蔽了对用户产生负面影响的设计选择。关键词:社会媒体技术哲学人工制品规范性类比论证披露声明作者未报告潜在的利益冲突。注1除特别注明外,所有重点均为原文此时可能会出现另一种反对意见:如果有些游戏没有塑造临时代理的构成规则会怎样?这是一个有趣的反对意见,但它首先是对Nguyen游戏描述的反对意见。如果有些游戏没有塑造临时代理的基本规则,Nguyen就不得不将Twitter与其他地方的游戏进行类比。
{"title":"Why Twitter does not gamify communication","authors":"Jacob Browning, Zed Adams","doi":"10.1080/0020174x.2023.2261489","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174x.2023.2261489","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTA central question for understanding social media platforms is whether the design of these systems is itself responsible for the harmful effects they have on society. Do these systems push users toward unhealthy forms of engagement? Is there something inherently toxic about the design that distorts who we are when we use it? In a recent paper, Thi Nguyen argues that the design of Twitter is responsible for many of its most toxic outcomes. Nguyen’s argument is based on an analogy between Twitter and games. He argues that Twitter’s game-like features encourage users to rack up Likes and Retweets rather than engaging in the rich and subtle activity of communication. For Nguyen, this drive for high scores leads to many of the toxic effects of the platform. In this paper, we critique Nguyen’s argument. We contend that, in a crucial respect that matters, Twitter is not game-like. We show that the apparent plausibility of Nguyen’s argument rests upon overlooking this crucial disanalogy. Moreover, drawing out how Nguyen’s analogy breaks down makes clear not just that his account fails to explain Twitter’s toxicity, but also that it actively occludes the design choices that have negative effects on its users.KEYWORDS: Social mediaphilosophy of technologynormativity of artifactsargument by analogy Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1 Unless noted, all emphases are in original.2 Another objection might arise at this point: what if there are games that do not have constitutive rules that sculpt temporary agency? This is an interesting objection, but it is first-and-foremost an objection to Nguyen’s account of games. If there are games that do not have constitutive rules that sculpt temporary agency, Nguyen would have to draw his proposed analogy between Twitter and games somewhere else.","PeriodicalId":47504,"journal":{"name":"Inquiry-An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135855207","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Precis of prejudice: a study in non-ideal epistemology 偏见的精确性:非理想认识论研究
2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-10-13 DOI: 10.1080/0020174x.2023.2269228
Endre Begby
ABSTRACTThis article provides an overview of ideas and arguments developed in my book Prejudice: A Study in Non-Ideal (Oxford University Press, 2021; paperback edition, 2022).KEYWORDS: Epistemologysocial epistemologynon-ideal epistemoloyepistemic rationalityprejudice Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1 To be clear, this is not meant to tell us anything about whether particular prejudiced individuals are justified in believing as they do, whether particular kinds prejudiced beliefs are typically justified, and so on. Indeed, part of the point of the book is to discourage these sorts of questions: for virtually any class of beliefs, the question of whether a subject is justified in having such beliefs can only be answered after careful examination of their evidential situation and their cognitive processing. Given the proper methodology, we should not expect broad generalizations at this level. More about this in my response to Thomas Kelly below.2 Moreover, reflection suggests that even true beliefs can be prejudicially deployed in context, as I argue in Begby (Citation2021, 10–11).3 Indeed, on my view, stereotype-reasoning just is the manifestation of categorization in the domain of social cognition. To argue that our cognition should only ever track individuals qua individuals is basically to give up on the idea of social cognition altogether.4 Recall Fricker’s stipulation that ‘[t]he idea of a prejudice is […] most naturally interpreted […] as a judgement made or maintained without proper regard to the evidence’ (Fricker Citation2007, 32–33, my emphasis.)5 The fact that so-called ‘looping effects’ (cf. Haslanger Citation2011, 196–198, drawing on Hacking Citation1999) might be in play here, does nothing to change the fact that these observations might nonetheless constitute evidence.6 More about this in my response to Giulia Napolitano below.7 Note the echoes of Gordon Allport’s view (Citation1954, 9) that ‘[p]rejudgments become prejudices only if they are not reversible when exposed to new knowledge. A prejudice, unlike a simple misconception, is actively resistant to all evidence that would unseat it’.8 In particular, it helps shed light on the phenomenon of ‘echo chamber construction’, as argued in Nguyen (Citation2020).9 The mechanics of evidential preemption is further discussed in my response to Thomas Kelly below.10 These issues receive further discussion in my response to Renee Jorgensen below.11 Correspondingly, when we talk about ‘algorithmic bias’, it seems natural to assume that the phenomenon arises specifically from the deployment of algorithms in decision making (perhaps computerized algorithms, in particular).12 On this, see Begby (Citation2018). In the book (Begby Citation2021, 161–163), I explore and cautiously endorse the possibility that the considerations levied by moral encroachment are good ones: the only problem is that they don’t, strictly speaking, bear on belief, b
摘要本文概述了我的著作《偏见:非理想研究》(牛津大学出版社,2021;平装版,2022年)。关键词:认识论;社会认识论;非理想认识论;注1:需要明确的是,这并不是要告诉我们,特定的有偏见的个人是否有理由相信他们所做的事情,特定种类的有偏见的信仰是否通常是合理的,等等。事实上,这本书的部分观点就是反对这类问题:对于几乎任何类型的信念,一个主体是否有理由拥有这样的信念的问题,只能在仔细检查他们的证据情况和他们的认知过程之后才能回答。考虑到适当的方法,我们不应该期望在这个层次上进行广泛的概括。在下面我对托马斯·凯利的回应中有更多关于这一点的信息此外,反思表明,就像我在Begby (Citation2021, 10-11)中所说的那样,即使是真实的信念也可能在语境中被偏见地运用事实上,在我看来,刻板印象推理只是分类在社会认知领域的表现。认为我们的认知只应该以个体的身份来追踪个体,基本上等于完全放弃了社会认知的观点回想Fricker的规定,“偏见的概念是[…]最自然地解释[…]作为一种没有适当考虑证据的判断”(Fricker Citation2007, 32-33,我的重点。)5所谓的“循环效应”(参见Haslanger Citation2011, 196-198,引用Hacking Citation1999)可能在这里发挥作用,但这并不能改变这些观察可能构成证据的事实在我对朱莉娅·纳波利塔诺(Giulia Napolitano)的回应中,有更多关于这一点的内容请注意Gordon Allport的观点(引文1954,9)的呼应:“重新判断只有在接触新知识时不可逆转时才会成为偏见。”偏见不同于简单的误解,它会积极抵制一切能推翻它的证据特别是,正如Nguyen (Citation2020)所指出的那样,它有助于阐明“回音室建设”现象证据优先购买权的机制将在下文我对托马斯·凯利的回复中进一步讨论这些问题将在下文我对蕾妮·乔根森的答复中得到进一步讨论相应地,当我们谈论“算法偏差”时,似乎很自然地假设这种现象特别来自于决策中算法的部署(特别是计算机化算法)关于这一点,请参见Begby (Citation2018)。在这本书中(Begby Citation2021, 161-163),我探索并谨慎地赞同道德侵犯所带来的考虑是好的可能性:唯一的问题是,严格来说,它们与信仰无关,而是与一种被称为“接受”的独特心理功能有关。我在这里不考虑这一点,但希望在今后的工作中进一步发展这个想法有关这方面的更多信息,请参见Begby (Citation2021, 165-170)为了说明这些不同的责任维度是如何被编纂的,这本书分别介绍了提供刑法和侵权法基础的责任基础的不同概念:简而言之,刑法只有在满足最低限度的“犯罪意图”(“犯罪心理”)标准时才要求人们负责。相比之下,侵权行为法即使在承认人们不知道自己的行为是错误的情况下,也可以要求人们对损害赔偿承担责任非常感谢Holly K. Andersen提供的宝贵反馈,感谢Giulia, Renee和Tom同意担任评论家,感谢Paul Silva Jr.和科隆概念中心主办最初的研讨会,该研讨会仍可在https://youtu.be/C-1j8j4OSpY?si=e1q8bO9KEXpgEMIl上查看。
{"title":"Precis of prejudice: a study in non-ideal epistemology","authors":"Endre Begby","doi":"10.1080/0020174x.2023.2269228","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174x.2023.2269228","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTThis article provides an overview of ideas and arguments developed in my book Prejudice: A Study in Non-Ideal (Oxford University Press, 2021; paperback edition, 2022).KEYWORDS: Epistemologysocial epistemologynon-ideal epistemoloyepistemic rationalityprejudice Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1 To be clear, this is not meant to tell us anything about whether particular prejudiced individuals are justified in believing as they do, whether particular kinds prejudiced beliefs are typically justified, and so on. Indeed, part of the point of the book is to discourage these sorts of questions: for virtually any class of beliefs, the question of whether a subject is justified in having such beliefs can only be answered after careful examination of their evidential situation and their cognitive processing. Given the proper methodology, we should not expect broad generalizations at this level. More about this in my response to Thomas Kelly below.2 Moreover, reflection suggests that even true beliefs can be prejudicially deployed in context, as I argue in Begby (Citation2021, 10–11).3 Indeed, on my view, stereotype-reasoning just is the manifestation of categorization in the domain of social cognition. To argue that our cognition should only ever track individuals qua individuals is basically to give up on the idea of social cognition altogether.4 Recall Fricker’s stipulation that ‘[t]he idea of a prejudice is […] most naturally interpreted […] as a judgement made or maintained without proper regard to the evidence’ (Fricker Citation2007, 32–33, my emphasis.)5 The fact that so-called ‘looping effects’ (cf. Haslanger Citation2011, 196–198, drawing on Hacking Citation1999) might be in play here, does nothing to change the fact that these observations might nonetheless constitute evidence.6 More about this in my response to Giulia Napolitano below.7 Note the echoes of Gordon Allport’s view (Citation1954, 9) that ‘[p]rejudgments become prejudices only if they are not reversible when exposed to new knowledge. A prejudice, unlike a simple misconception, is actively resistant to all evidence that would unseat it’.8 In particular, it helps shed light on the phenomenon of ‘echo chamber construction’, as argued in Nguyen (Citation2020).9 The mechanics of evidential preemption is further discussed in my response to Thomas Kelly below.10 These issues receive further discussion in my response to Renee Jorgensen below.11 Correspondingly, when we talk about ‘algorithmic bias’, it seems natural to assume that the phenomenon arises specifically from the deployment of algorithms in decision making (perhaps computerized algorithms, in particular).12 On this, see Begby (Citation2018). In the book (Begby Citation2021, 161–163), I explore and cautiously endorse the possibility that the considerations levied by moral encroachment are good ones: the only problem is that they don’t, strictly speaking, bear on belief, b","PeriodicalId":47504,"journal":{"name":"Inquiry-An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135854082","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A monstrous account of non-deictic readings of complex demonstratives 复杂指示词的非指示性解读
2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-10-11 DOI: 10.1080/0020174x.2023.2267099
Joan Gimeno-Simó
ABSTRACTComplex demonstratives are often seen as a source of trouble for the idea that demonstratives are directly referential. Several authors have provided an array of counterexamples that preclude us from treating complex demonstratives as devices of direct reference, since they could hardly be considered rigid designators. In this paper I argue that a revision of the classic theories can accommodate all the counterevidence from non-deictic uses of complex demonstratives. Namely, I argue that the two chief objections that have been posed to the traditional picture, the so-called ‘quantification in’ and ‘no demonstration, no speaker reference’ problems, can be given a unified solution by treating them as instances of monstrous quantification into the character of the term.KEYWORDS: Rigid designationdirect referencemonstersindexicalityquantifying in AcknowldgementsI wish to thank Derek Ball, María de Ponte, Manuel García-Carpintero, Stefano Predelli and Jordi Valor for their comments on earlier versions of this paper, and to an anonymous reviewer for a very thorough and constructive report.Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1 It is in this sense that the nominal can be said to contribute to character. In these theories, the character of a complex demonstrative of the form ⟦that P⟧ is not a function F such that, for each context c, f(c) = dc, but rather a proper subfunction of F: one whose domain only includes contexts c such that ⟦P⟧()(dc) = 1. The character of any complex demonstrative is always given by a subfunction of F, and the role of the nominal is to determine exactly which of these subfunctions is to be selected.2 The validity of these arguments is debatable (cf. Braun Citation2008a, 70, footnotes 20–24), but this is not in conflict with the kind of approach advocated by c-theorists.3 Predelli (Citation2001) has posed a challenge to c-theories based on anaphora, but I have argued elsewhere that the counterevidence he points out can be given an alternative explanation (Gimeno-Simó Citation2021).4 King (Citation2001) also provides some syntactic evidence that seems to point towards the idea that complex demonstratives are quantifiers, but it has been subject to severe criticism (Altshuler Citation2007).5 Some defenders of the traditional paradigm have tried to explain away these readings by arguing that complex demonstratives can act as ‘stylistically altered definite descriptions’ (Dever Citation2001, 286; Salmon Citation2002, 522; Citation2006a, 446; Citation2006b, 272, footnote 11; Corazza Citation2003, 272; Georgi Citation2012). These ambiguity theories have been severely criticised by Ethan Nowak (Citation2014; Citation2021a; Citation2022).6 Notice in fact that the problem can be posed without even resorting to the third sentence in (18): (18*) [A student]1 was sitting in the library. Another student was sitting across from her1.Who is the referent of ‘her’ on this occasio
摘要复杂指示词通常被认为是直接指称的一个麻烦来源。几位作者提供了一系列反例,使我们无法将复杂指示语视为直接指称的手段,因为它们很难被视为严格的指示语。在本文中,我认为对经典理论的修正可以容纳复杂指示语非指示用法的所有反证据。也就是说,我认为,对传统图景提出的两个主要反对意见,即所谓的“量化”和“没有证明,没有说话人参考”问题,可以通过将它们视为对术语特征进行可怕量化的实例来给出统一的解决方案。我要感谢Derek Ball, María de Ponte, Manuel García-Carpintero, Stefano Predelli和Jordi Valor对本文早期版本的评论,以及一位非常全面和建设性的匿名审稿人。披露声明作者未报告潜在的利益冲突。注1正是在这个意义上,名义上的东西可以说对性格有贡献。在这些理论中,形式为:::::::形式为:::::::在这些理论中,形式为:::::::::::在这些理论中,形式为::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::任何复数指示的性质总是由F的子函数给出,而标称函数的作用是确定这些子函数中究竟选择哪一个这些论点的有效性是有争议的(参见Braun Citation2008a, 70,脚注20-24),但这与c-理论家所提倡的方法并不冲突Predelli (Citation2001)对基于回指的c理论提出了挑战,但我在其他地方争论过,他指出的反证可以给出另一种解释(Gimeno-Simó Citation2021)King (Citation2001)也提供了一些句法证据,似乎指向了复杂指示词是量词的观点,但它受到了严厉的批评(Altshuler Citation2007)一些传统范式的捍卫者试图解释这些解读,他们认为复杂指示可以作为“风格上改变的明确描述”(Dever citation2001,286;三文鱼引文,2002,522;Citation2006a, 446;Citation2006b, 272,脚注11;科拉扎引文2003,272;格奥尔基Citation2012)。这些歧义理论受到了Ethan Nowak (citation; 2014;Citation2021a;Citation2022)。6请注意,事实上,这个问题甚至可以不借助(18)中的第三句话来提出:(18*)[一个学生]1坐在图书馆里。另一个学生坐在她对面。在这种情况下,“她”指的是谁?让我们假设是玛丽。在这种情况下,这两个句子在任何一个世界里都是正确的,在这个世界里,任何一个学生坐在图书馆里,而玛丽坐在另一个学生对面,比如说在咖啡店里。由于同样的原因,这是错误的为简单起见,这个词汇条目将许多与当前讨论不直接相关的细节(如远性或复数)放在一边。我也没有提到诸如空术语的可解释性和如何处理多次出现的指示词等问题要确定的是,(26)所陈述的并不是对于每一个实际的红色物体x,存在一个可能的世界w,使得x在w中发光,相反,我们希望所有实际的红色物体在一个世界中一起发光。它也没有说明存在一个可能的世界w,使得对于每个x, x是w中的红色物体,x在w中是闪亮的。如果我们只有一个评估参数的世界,我们就会不知所措:我们需要根据初始世界对“红色”进行评估,这意味着它的范围应该比“可能”更广,但同时“红色”应该在量词“一切”的范围内,而“一切”又应该在“可能”的范围内,以便所有这些事物在一个单一的世界中共同发光。因此,作用域是不兼容的Schaffer强调了模态和时域之间的类比(Citation2012)。参见Neale (Citation2006)有些作者经常在形容词中加入显性世界变量,因为这个想法提供了一种很好的方式来解释所谓的“Fodor读数”(范围既不窄也不宽;参见Heim and von Fintel (Citation2011,§8)的概述。但是,正如Musan (Citation1995)和Kusumoto (Citation1999)的论点所表明的那样,具有显式形容词变量的系统通常会过度生成,因为它们预测许多句子的读数实际上并没有显示出来。 我不愿意失去句子的表面形式和深层形式之间的对应关系;因此,我不会包括那些不是由句子的某些显式元素所贡献的变量人们普遍认为,过去时通常是指代性的,如帕蒂(Citation1973)的著名例子“我没有关掉炉子”。在这里,关于现在时刻的先验是预先假定的,而不是断言的。然而,这并不意味着某些句子不能提供现在时的明确表示。相反,表征现在时对于确保预设材料被正确解释是必要的。例如,在像von Stechow (Citation2003)这样的系统中,任何包含参照使用的过去时的句子p都会收到一个类似于(a)的LF,其中包含一个显式现在时变量:(a) t0 [t0 < t1pres] (p)12在这个系统中,共同标引是必要的,否则我们最终会将(26)这样的句子不具有的阅读归为它。然而,也有其他选择。例如,同样的结果可以通过在每个句子前面加上两个变量来实现,这两个变量总是挑选出环境的参数,并且通过让标记为指示符的任何变量具有以下预设语义:Gc (wn)这里n是任意自然数。(n) = λc: gc(tn) = gc(t0)。Gc (tn)其中n是任意自然数。为了简单起见,我将采用联合索引诚然,后一种阅读更难实现,但如果提供一些背景,它可以变得非常贴切,甚至比前一种阅读更受欢迎。想象一下,你和我是茱莉亚的同学,我们正在交谈,回忆过去的时光。如果我在这种情况下说出(31),第二段阅读就更明显了实际上,这就是我在整篇论文中处理这个表达式的方法。其他作者更喜欢将其视为语义上空洞的表达式,并将lambda作为隐蔽元素添加到关系子句本身中。我看不出这两种方法有什么真正的区别,我的建议两者都适用高类型跟踪是解决语义中一些难题的一种相对常见的方法,它们通常与新的组合原则的引入密切相关(关于手册处理,参见Heim和von Fintel Citation2011, 94-95)。诚然,引入这种机制并不是没有成本的,但是为了达到正确的结果,而不诉诸于更可疑的资源(如非正统的语法),这通常是必要的。重要的是,引入这种方法不仅仅是为了解释与复杂指示词相关的问题:我们在这里处理的同样的问题可以提出给任何包含关系从句的NP,比如(31)中的一个,它可以类似地解决(见脚注17)有些哲学家可能不愿意采用另一种构成原则。然而,请注意,环境规范是对上述个体识别的补充,这意味着它不会带来更大的概念成本,更不用说考虑到引入它的唯一原因是为了保持从采用类型>派生的整体简单性——毕竟,在内涵设置中,这是一种远不常见的类型该系统预测(31)可能接收到两种不同的逻辑形式:(31a) λ。[一个同学谁[Ǝt3: t3 < t1] (r2戴眼镜)]λ4。玛丽嫁给了r4(31b) λ。[一个同学who2 [Ǝt3: t3 < t1] (R2戴眼镜)]λ4。玛丽嫁给了r4,这两者之间唯一的区别是运动痕迹的类型。在(31a)中,根据个人识别,“
{"title":"A monstrous account of non-deictic readings of complex demonstratives","authors":"Joan Gimeno-Simó","doi":"10.1080/0020174x.2023.2267099","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174x.2023.2267099","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTComplex demonstratives are often seen as a source of trouble for the idea that demonstratives are directly referential. Several authors have provided an array of counterexamples that preclude us from treating complex demonstratives as devices of direct reference, since they could hardly be considered rigid designators. In this paper I argue that a revision of the classic theories can accommodate all the counterevidence from non-deictic uses of complex demonstratives. Namely, I argue that the two chief objections that have been posed to the traditional picture, the so-called ‘quantification in’ and ‘no demonstration, no speaker reference’ problems, can be given a unified solution by treating them as instances of monstrous quantification into the character of the term.KEYWORDS: Rigid designationdirect referencemonstersindexicalityquantifying in AcknowldgementsI wish to thank Derek Ball, María de Ponte, Manuel García-Carpintero, Stefano Predelli and Jordi Valor for their comments on earlier versions of this paper, and to an anonymous reviewer for a very thorough and constructive report.Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1 It is in this sense that the nominal can be said to contribute to character. In these theories, the character of a complex demonstrative of the form ⟦that P⟧ is not a function F such that, for each context c, f(c) = dc, but rather a proper subfunction of F: one whose domain only includes contexts c such that ⟦P⟧(<wc, tc>)(dc) = 1. The character of any complex demonstrative is always given by a subfunction of F, and the role of the nominal is to determine exactly which of these subfunctions is to be selected.2 The validity of these arguments is debatable (cf. Braun Citation2008a, 70, footnotes 20–24), but this is not in conflict with the kind of approach advocated by c-theorists.3 Predelli (Citation2001) has posed a challenge to c-theories based on anaphora, but I have argued elsewhere that the counterevidence he points out can be given an alternative explanation (Gimeno-Simó Citation2021).4 King (Citation2001) also provides some syntactic evidence that seems to point towards the idea that complex demonstratives are quantifiers, but it has been subject to severe criticism (Altshuler Citation2007).5 Some defenders of the traditional paradigm have tried to explain away these readings by arguing that complex demonstratives can act as ‘stylistically altered definite descriptions’ (Dever Citation2001, 286; Salmon Citation2002, 522; Citation2006a, 446; Citation2006b, 272, footnote 11; Corazza Citation2003, 272; Georgi Citation2012). These ambiguity theories have been severely criticised by Ethan Nowak (Citation2014; Citation2021a; Citation2022).6 Notice in fact that the problem can be posed without even resorting to the third sentence in (18): (18*) [A student]1 was sitting in the library. Another student was sitting across from her1.Who is the referent of ‘her’ on this occasio","PeriodicalId":47504,"journal":{"name":"Inquiry-An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"136210505","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Towards an account of basic final value 对基本最终价值的描述
2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-10-01 DOI: 10.1080/0020174x.2023.2262758
Timothy Perrine
ABSTRACTOrdinary and philosophical thought suggests recognizing a distinction between two ways something can be of final value. Something can be of final value in virtue of its connection to other things of value (‘non-basic final value’) or something can be of final value regardless of its connection to other things of value (‘basic final value’). The primary aim of this paper is to provide an account of this distinction. I argue that we have reason to draw this distinction as it helps avoid certain problems. I criticize accounts of this distinction due to Warren Quinn, Fred Feldman, and Michael Zimmerman. I then provide my own positive account which incorporates several of the insights of those accounts while avoiding their pitfalls. I conclude by relating my account to issues concerning partiality and appropriate attitudes.KEYWORDS: Final valuebasic final valuepro-attitudesFred FeldmanMichael Zimmerman Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author.Notes1 As the examples illustrate, by things of value, I have in mind facts, events, states of affairs, or ways the world could be. I don’t have in mind specific concrete objects, like a frying pan. See fn. 3 for further relevant discussion.2 See, for instance, Brentano (Citation1902, 15f.), Ross (Citation1939, 279, 282), Ewing (Citation1947, 146ff.) Chisholm (Citation1986, 47ff.), Anderson (Citation1993, 2–3), Lemos (Citation1994, 6ff.), Scanlon (Citation1998, 78ff.), Zimmerman (Citation2001), Audi (Citation2004, 125). Merely maintaining that there is a substantive normative connection in no way identifies which property cluster is more fundamental. Further, this assumption does not require the particular kind of buck-passing popularized by Scanlon that is open to the wrong kind of reason objection. For a discussion of this last point, see Zimmerman (Citation2010).3 I focus on relationships between states of affairs of final value. Some authors might be interested in the relationships between concrete things that are of final value. For instance, Langton (Citation2007) suggests that something—e.g. a wedding ring—might be of final value but in virtue of something else—e.g., a personal relationship (see also Korsgaard (Citation1983)). These cases are sometimes called cases of ‘extrinsic final value,’ since the wedding ring is of final value, but the ‘source’ of its value is extrinsic to it. Since these cases involve individual objects, they are not the focus of my discussion. It’s an interesting question how exactly views about extrinsic final value interact with my proposals here. I don’t see any grand conflict. After all, if an object is of extrinsic final value, there’s a state of affairs about that object and its source of value that is, presumably, of final value. But I hope to explore this question in future work. For a negative view of how they might interact, see Bradley (Citation2006); for a critical discussion of extrinsic final value in general, see Tucker
普通的哲学思维意味着认识到某物具有最终价值的两种方式之间的区别。某物可以由于与其他有价值的事物的联系而具有最终价值(“非基本最终价值”),也可以由于与其他有价值的事物的联系而具有最终价值(“基本最终价值”)。本文的主要目的是提供这种区别的说明。我认为我们有理由做出这种区分,因为它有助于避免某些问题。我批评Warren Quinn, Fred Feldman和Michael Zimmerman对这种区别的描述。然后,我提供了我自己的积极的解释,其中包含了这些解释的一些见解,同时避免了它们的陷阱。最后,我将我的叙述与偏袒和适当态度的问题联系起来。关键词:最终价值基本最终价值倾向弗雷德·费尔德曼迈克尔·齐默曼披露声明作者未报告潜在利益冲突。注1:正如这些例子所说明的,我所说的有价值的东西,指的是事实、事件、事态或世界可能的样子。我脑子里没有具体的东西,比如煎锅。看到fn。3 .进行进一步的相关讨论例如,参见布伦塔诺(Citation1902, 15f.),罗斯(Citation1939, 279, 282),尤因(Citation1947, 146ff.)奇泽姆(Citation1986, 47页)、安德森(Citation1993, 2-3页)、莱莫斯(Citation1994, 6页)、斯坎隆(Citation1998, 78页)、齐默尔曼(Citation2001)、奥迪(Citation2004, 125页)。仅仅认为存在实质性的规范联系并不能确定哪个属性集群更基本。此外,这一假设并不需要斯坎伦推广的那种特别的推诿责任,这种推诿责任对错误的理性反对是开放的。关于最后一点的讨论,请参见Zimmerman (Citation2010)我关注的是具有最终价值的事物状态之间的关系。有些作者可能对具有最终价值的具体事物之间的关系感兴趣。例如,兰顿(Citation2007)认为某些东西——例如:一枚结婚戒指——可能具有最终价值,但却有其他用处——例如:(参见Korsgaard (Citation1983))。这些情况有时被称为“外在最终价值”的情况,因为结婚戒指具有最终价值,但其价值的“来源”是外在的。由于这些情况涉及单个对象,因此它们不是我讨论的重点。这是一个有趣的问题,关于外在最终价值的观点是如何与我的建议相互作用的。我看不出有什么大的冲突。毕竟,如果一个物体具有外在的最终价值,那么这个物体的状态和它的价值来源大概就是最终价值。但我希望在未来的工作中探索这个问题。关于两者如何相互作用的负面观点,请参见Bradley (Citation2006);关于外在最终价值的批判性讨论,请参见Tucker (Citation2016)原因是由哈曼(Citation1967),费尔德曼(Citation2000)和齐默尔曼(Citation2001)提出的,尽管陈述是我的。另见摩尔(Citation1912, 36页)和罗斯(Citation1930, 68页)我并不认为复杂事态的价值总是完全由其组成部分的价值决定。尽管如此,我确实认为,有时复杂事态的价值至少部分地取决于其组成部分的价值。此外,我不认为,如果一个复杂状态的价值是由其各部分的价值决定的,那么它就是以一种简单的、加性的方式决定的对于我在这里的讨论,我想保留这样一种可能性,即存在一些不具有基本价值的事物状态,但其价值并不能被具有基本价值的事物状态完全解释。如果存在这样的事件状态,那么对复杂事件状态的最终价值的全面估算——就像整个可能的世界一样——可能也必须考虑到它们。关于相反的方法,请参阅Feldman (Citation2000, 333)(感谢审稿人和Peter Finocchiaro对该主题的讨论)简而言之,假设S是基本终值。由基本终值3 (b)可知,我们不需要对S的任何固有部分采取任何亲态度。因此,由基本终值3 (a)可知,S的任何固有部分都不具有基本终值。假设S的某个固有部分S*是终值,但不是基本终值。在Zimmerman对终值的定义(Citation2001, 122)中,S*包含了一些基本终值的部分。鉴于部分的及物性,那么就可以得出S包含一个具有基本最终值的部分,我们已经知道这是不可能发生的。因此,S的固有部分不可能是非基本终值。因为所有的终值都是基本的或非基本的,如果S是基本的终值,则S的固有部分没有任何终值。
{"title":"Towards an account of basic final value","authors":"Timothy Perrine","doi":"10.1080/0020174x.2023.2262758","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174x.2023.2262758","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTOrdinary and philosophical thought suggests recognizing a distinction between two ways something can be of final value. Something can be of final value in virtue of its connection to other things of value (‘non-basic final value’) or something can be of final value regardless of its connection to other things of value (‘basic final value’). The primary aim of this paper is to provide an account of this distinction. I argue that we have reason to draw this distinction as it helps avoid certain problems. I criticize accounts of this distinction due to Warren Quinn, Fred Feldman, and Michael Zimmerman. I then provide my own positive account which incorporates several of the insights of those accounts while avoiding their pitfalls. I conclude by relating my account to issues concerning partiality and appropriate attitudes.KEYWORDS: Final valuebasic final valuepro-attitudesFred FeldmanMichael Zimmerman Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author.Notes1 As the examples illustrate, by things of value, I have in mind facts, events, states of affairs, or ways the world could be. I don’t have in mind specific concrete objects, like a frying pan. See fn. 3 for further relevant discussion.2 See, for instance, Brentano (Citation1902, 15f.), Ross (Citation1939, 279, 282), Ewing (Citation1947, 146ff.) Chisholm (Citation1986, 47ff.), Anderson (Citation1993, 2–3), Lemos (Citation1994, 6ff.), Scanlon (Citation1998, 78ff.), Zimmerman (Citation2001), Audi (Citation2004, 125). Merely maintaining that there is a substantive normative connection in no way identifies which property cluster is more fundamental. Further, this assumption does not require the particular kind of buck-passing popularized by Scanlon that is open to the wrong kind of reason objection. For a discussion of this last point, see Zimmerman (Citation2010).3 I focus on relationships between states of affairs of final value. Some authors might be interested in the relationships between concrete things that are of final value. For instance, Langton (Citation2007) suggests that something—e.g. a wedding ring—might be of final value but in virtue of something else—e.g., a personal relationship (see also Korsgaard (Citation1983)). These cases are sometimes called cases of ‘extrinsic final value,’ since the wedding ring is of final value, but the ‘source’ of its value is extrinsic to it. Since these cases involve individual objects, they are not the focus of my discussion. It’s an interesting question how exactly views about extrinsic final value interact with my proposals here. I don’t see any grand conflict. After all, if an object is of extrinsic final value, there’s a state of affairs about that object and its source of value that is, presumably, of final value. But I hope to explore this question in future work. For a negative view of how they might interact, see Bradley (Citation2006); for a critical discussion of extrinsic final value in general, see Tucker","PeriodicalId":47504,"journal":{"name":"Inquiry-An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135408864","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Substructural heresies 子结构异端
2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-09-29 DOI: 10.1080/0020174x.2023.2254816
Bogdan Dicher
ABSTRACTThis paper discusses two revisionary views about substructurality. The first attempts to reduce the structural features of a logic to properties of its logical vocabulary. It will be found to be untenable. The second aims to separate the structural features of a logic from the properties of logical consequence and to reinterpreted them as sui generis proof resources. I will argue that it is a viable path for a renewed understanding of substructurality.KEYWORDS: Substructural logiclogical consequencesequents Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1 These ‘collections’ can be sequences (lists), multisets (lists with repetitions but without order), sets simpliciter, etc. A full characterisation of a sequent (in a specific calculus) requires the specification of their precise mathematical nature. But here we allow, in principle, variations of the components of the sequents. Therefore generality is preferable to precision hence the use of the term ‘collection’ – with the caveat that the default choice will be to treat collections as sets.2 I follow the usual notational conventions and use minuscules from the second half of the Latin alphabet as sentential variables. Majuscules, with or without superscripts, from the beginning of the alphabet are metavariables ranging over sentential variables while those from its end range over collections (see the previous note) of formulae.3 An anonymous referee points out that the same view appears in Sambin, Battilotti, and Faggian (Citation2000). I am not convinced that this is the position advocated in that paper. The matter deserves more attention than I can give it here, but the following passage from Sambin, Battilotti, and Faggian (Citation2000) seems to be decisive for the overall understanding of their position: ‘It is an ambition of basic logic to offer a new perspective and new tools to the search for unity in logic. …[O]ur plan is to look for the basic principles and structures common to many different logics. So one aim is to obtain each specific logic by the addition of rules concerning exclusively the structure (i.e. structural rules dealing only with assertions), while keeping the logic of propositions (i.e. operational rules dealing with logical constants) absolutely fixed’. I take this to indicate a commitment to the priority of the structural level over the operational one which is quite antithetical to A-heresy.4 Henceforth I will use ‘structural property’ and ‘structural rule’ interchangeably. Each structural rules generates a structural property and each structural property correlates in some way with a structural rule.5 By ‘set-theoretic aggregate’ I mean any kind of collection that can be represented within set-theory; that includes sequences, multisets, sequences of set-theoretic aggregates, etc. For the most part, however, I will represent these using the set-theoretic accolades.6 See note 16 for details and examples.7 A model is a
在文献中有观点认为,前提组合不是独立于连接构成的,就像连接不是独立于前提组合构成的一样(Dicher Citation2016, Citation2020)。根据这些论证,逻辑的结构性质和逻辑的算子处于一种共定关系中。然而,由于这些论点所涉及的资源太过特殊,无法被扎尔迪尼所接受,而且他们的辩护也太过复杂,因此我不作进一步讨论对于Ai∈X(i=1,2,3,…,n),重复应用演绎定理可以将X,A∈B转化为∈A1→(A2→…(A→B)…)。精明的读者可能会想,为什么多个前提被解释为连接而不是连接条件?虽然我不知道扎尔迪尼的确切目标。他谈论的是"蕴涵",而似乎不关心诸如区分作为行为的推理和作为客体的推理(=结论主张)等更细微的问题这一点被认为是加雷思·埃文斯在《休史密斯和斯迈利》(Citation1978)中提出的,在其他文献中也出现过,参见达米特(Citation1991);斯坦伯格(Citation2010)含量也许有一种方法可以做到鱼与熊掌兼得,但那将发生在一家完全不同的餐厅,比如Dicher (Citation2019)它们的缺失会对“词汇”产生影响,正如第5页上面已经提到的那样。在线性逻辑中可互导的运算规则在线性逻辑中不再是等价的。例如,以下两个规则A,X:YA∧B,X:YB,X:YA∧B,X: yy与规则A,B,X:YA∧B,X: yy使用弱化和收缩是可导的。(对上排任意一条规则的前提应用弱化可以得到A, B,X:Y,而对下排规则可以得到A∧B,X:Y。反之,将顶规则应用于底规则的前提,并在A∧b上进行缩并。在线性逻辑中,我们可以区分出两种不同的连接词:由规则X:Y,AX:Y,BX:Y,A∧B∧RA,X:YA∧B,X:Y∧L1B,X:YA∧B,X:Y∧l2和由规则X:Y,AW:Z,BX,W:Y,Z,A⊗BA,B,X:YA⊗B,X:Y一般来说,LK的每一个二元连接词都是重复的(有人会说:消除歧义(Paoli Citation2007)),这样就有了一个加法和一个乘法的版本吉拉德使用“结果”一词是否与我在这里使用它的意思相同,或者相反,他使用它来表示本文意义上的“推论”,这是一个有争议的问题我感谢一位匿名的裁判,他提出了弱化和收缩的最后两种可能的解释,作为自定义的证明资源参见下面的讨论,包括注释20,以及Yagisawa (Citation1993)或Russell (Citation2018)对同一可能性的不同探索可以肯定的是,这一观点在一段时间内被广泛接受。Georgi (Citation2015)和Zardini (Citation2014)已经探索了处理指示/指示的逻辑,即使它们在论证中改变了引用某些结构规则可以用来控制在序列中出现的公式的同义词的(一般)想法起源于吉拉德(Citation1976);参见吉拉德,拉丰,泰勒(Citation1989)和迪彻(Citation2019)。22感谢Alef研讨会(罗马尼亚巴贝斯-博利亚大学)和langcog研讨会(葡萄牙里斯本大学哲学中心)的听众对本文以前版本的评论和建议。我还要感谢本刊一位匿名审稿人,他给了我许多建议和修改,大大改进了我的论文。我要特别感谢布鲁诺·哈辛托和埃利亚·扎尔迪尼,他们就这里所讨论的话题进行了多次对话。本研究由葡萄牙<s:1> <s:1> <s:1> para - Ciência e a tecologia基金(FCT)资助,资助项目CEECIND/02877/2018(“metainference: New perspectives on logic”)和2022.03194。PTDC (On Objects and Grounds of Substructural Rules)。进一步的资金支持来自欧盟,通过101086295号拨款(“亚结构性的哲学、逻辑和实验视角- plexus”,这是欧盟在地平线欧洲研究和创新计划下资助的玛丽·斯克洛多夫斯卡-居里行动)。
{"title":"Substructural heresies","authors":"Bogdan Dicher","doi":"10.1080/0020174x.2023.2254816","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174x.2023.2254816","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTThis paper discusses two revisionary views about substructurality. The first attempts to reduce the structural features of a logic to properties of its logical vocabulary. It will be found to be untenable. The second aims to separate the structural features of a logic from the properties of logical consequence and to reinterpreted them as sui generis proof resources. I will argue that it is a viable path for a renewed understanding of substructurality.KEYWORDS: Substructural logiclogical consequencesequents Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1 These ‘collections’ can be sequences (lists), multisets (lists with repetitions but without order), sets simpliciter, etc. A full characterisation of a sequent (in a specific calculus) requires the specification of their precise mathematical nature. But here we allow, in principle, variations of the components of the sequents. Therefore generality is preferable to precision hence the use of the term ‘collection’ – with the caveat that the default choice will be to treat collections as sets.2 I follow the usual notational conventions and use minuscules from the second half of the Latin alphabet as sentential variables. Majuscules, with or without superscripts, from the beginning of the alphabet are metavariables ranging over sentential variables while those from its end range over collections (see the previous note) of formulae.3 An anonymous referee points out that the same view appears in Sambin, Battilotti, and Faggian (Citation2000). I am not convinced that this is the position advocated in that paper. The matter deserves more attention than I can give it here, but the following passage from Sambin, Battilotti, and Faggian (Citation2000) seems to be decisive for the overall understanding of their position: ‘It is an ambition of basic logic to offer a new perspective and new tools to the search for unity in logic. …[O]ur plan is to look for the basic principles and structures common to many different logics. So one aim is to obtain each specific logic by the addition of rules concerning exclusively the structure (i.e. structural rules dealing only with assertions), while keeping the logic of propositions (i.e. operational rules dealing with logical constants) absolutely fixed’. I take this to indicate a commitment to the priority of the structural level over the operational one which is quite antithetical to A-heresy.4 Henceforth I will use ‘structural property’ and ‘structural rule’ interchangeably. Each structural rules generates a structural property and each structural property correlates in some way with a structural rule.5 By ‘set-theoretic aggregate’ I mean any kind of collection that can be represented within set-theory; that includes sequences, multisets, sequences of set-theoretic aggregates, etc. For the most part, however, I will represent these using the set-theoretic accolades.6 See note 16 for details and examples.7 A model is a ","PeriodicalId":47504,"journal":{"name":"Inquiry-An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135199759","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
AI and bureaucratic discretion 人工智能与官僚裁量权
2区 哲学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2023-09-29 DOI: 10.1080/0020174x.2023.2261468
Kate Vredenburgh
Algorithmic decision-making has the potential to radically reshape policy-making and policy implementation. Many of the moral examinations of AI in government take AI to be a neutral epistemic tool or the value-driven analogue of a policymaker. In this paper, I argue that AI systems in public administration are often better analogised to a street-level bureaucrat. Doing so opens up a host of questions about the moral dispositions of such AI systems. I argue that AI systems in public administration often act as indifferent bureaucrats, and that this can introduce a problematic homogeneity in the moral dispositions in administrative agencies.
算法决策有可能从根本上重塑政策制定和政策实施。许多对政府中人工智能的道德审查都将人工智能视为一种中立的认知工具,或者是政策制定者的价值驱动的模拟物。在本文中,我认为公共管理中的人工智能系统通常更适合类比于街头官僚。这样做会引发一系列关于此类人工智能系统道德倾向的问题。我认为,公共行政中的人工智能系统经常扮演冷漠的官僚角色,这可能会在行政机构的道德倾向中引入有问题的同质性。
{"title":"AI and bureaucratic discretion","authors":"Kate Vredenburgh","doi":"10.1080/0020174x.2023.2261468","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174x.2023.2261468","url":null,"abstract":"Algorithmic decision-making has the potential to radically reshape policy-making and policy implementation. Many of the moral examinations of AI in government take AI to be a neutral epistemic tool or the value-driven analogue of a policymaker. In this paper, I argue that AI systems in public administration are often better analogised to a street-level bureaucrat. Doing so opens up a host of questions about the moral dispositions of such AI systems. I argue that AI systems in public administration often act as indifferent bureaucrats, and that this can introduce a problematic homogeneity in the moral dispositions in administrative agencies.","PeriodicalId":47504,"journal":{"name":"Inquiry-An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135200472","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Inquiry-An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1