首页 > 最新文献

Duke Law Journal最新文献

英文 中文
One Good Plaintiff Is Not Enough 一个好的原告是不够的
IF 1.9 2区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2017-12-13 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2901122
A. Bruhl
This Article concerns an aspect of Article III standing that has figured in many of the highest-profile controversies of recent years, including litigation over the Affordable Care Act, immigration policy, and climate change. Although the federal courts constantly emphasize the importance of ensuring that only proper plaintiffs invoke the federal judicial power, the Supreme Court and other federal courts have developed a significant exception to the usual requirement of standing. This exception holds that a court entertaining a multiple-plaintiff case may dispense with inquiring into the standing of each plaintiff as long as the court finds that one plaintiff has standing. This practice of partially bypassing the requirement of standing is not limited to cases in which the plaintiffs are about to lose on other grounds anyway. Put differently, courts are willing to assume that all plaintiffs have standing as long as one plaintiff has it and then decide the merits either for or against all plaintiffs despite doubts as to the standing of some of those plaintiffs. We could call this the “one-plaintiff rule.”This Article examines the one-plaintiff rule from normative and positive perspectives. On the normative side, the goal is to establish that the one-plaintiff rule is erroneous in light of principle, precedent, and policy. All plaintiffs need standing, even if all of them present similar legal claims and regardless of the form of relief they seek. To motivate the normative inquiry, the Article also explains why the one-plaintiff rule is harmful as a practical matter, namely because it assigns concrete benefits and detriments to persons to whom they do not belong. The Article’s other principal goal is to explain the puzzle of how the mistaken one-plaintiff rule could attain such widespread acceptance. The explanatory account assigns the blame for the one-plaintiff rule to the incentives of courts and litigants as well as to the development of certain problematic understandings of the nature of judicial power.
本文关注的是近年来在许多最引人注目的争议中出现的第三条地位的一个方面,包括有关《平价医疗法案》、移民政策和气候变化的诉讼。尽管联邦法院不断强调确保只有合适的原告才能援引联邦司法权的重要性,但最高法院和其他联邦法院对通常的诉讼资格要求提出了一个重要的例外。这一例外认为,受理多原告案件的法院只要认定一名原告具有诉讼资格,就可以不调查每一原告的诉讼资格。这种部分绕过诉讼资格要求的做法并不局限于原告无论如何都将在其他理由上败诉的案件。换句话说,法院愿意假设所有原告都有诉讼资格,只要一个原告有诉讼资格,然后决定对所有原告有利或不利的是非曲直,尽管对其中一些原告的诉讼资格存在疑问。我们可以称之为“一原告规则”。本文从规范和积极的角度对原告一人规则进行了考察。在规范方面,目标是确立一原告规则在原则、先例和政策方面是错误的。所有原告都需要诉讼资格,即使他们都提出了类似的法律主张,也不管他们寻求何种形式的救济。为了激发规范性探究,文章还解释了为什么一原告规则作为一个实际问题是有害的,即因为它将具体的利益和损害分配给了不属于他们的人。该条的另一个主要目的是解释为何错误的一原告规则会获得如此广泛的接受。解释性解释将一原告规则的责任归咎于法院和诉讼当事人的动机,以及对司法权性质的某些有问题的理解的发展。
{"title":"One Good Plaintiff Is Not Enough","authors":"A. Bruhl","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2901122","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2901122","url":null,"abstract":"This Article concerns an aspect of Article III standing that has figured in many of the highest-profile controversies of recent years, including litigation over the Affordable Care Act, immigration policy, and climate change. Although the federal courts constantly emphasize the importance of ensuring that only proper plaintiffs invoke the federal judicial power, the Supreme Court and other federal courts have developed a significant exception to the usual requirement of standing. This exception holds that a court entertaining a multiple-plaintiff case may dispense with inquiring into the standing of each plaintiff as long as the court finds that one plaintiff has standing. This practice of partially bypassing the requirement of standing is not limited to cases in which the plaintiffs are about to lose on other grounds anyway. Put differently, courts are willing to assume that all plaintiffs have standing as long as one plaintiff has it and then decide the merits either for or against all plaintiffs despite doubts as to the standing of some of those plaintiffs. We could call this the “one-plaintiff rule.”This Article examines the one-plaintiff rule from normative and positive perspectives. On the normative side, the goal is to establish that the one-plaintiff rule is erroneous in light of principle, precedent, and policy. All plaintiffs need standing, even if all of them present similar legal claims and regardless of the form of relief they seek. To motivate the normative inquiry, the Article also explains why the one-plaintiff rule is harmful as a practical matter, namely because it assigns concrete benefits and detriments to persons to whom they do not belong. The Article’s other principal goal is to explain the puzzle of how the mistaken one-plaintiff rule could attain such widespread acceptance. The explanatory account assigns the blame for the one-plaintiff rule to the incentives of courts and litigants as well as to the development of certain problematic understandings of the nature of judicial power.","PeriodicalId":47625,"journal":{"name":"Duke Law Journal","volume":"67 1","pages":"481-556"},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2017-12-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43939269","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Don’t Try This at Home: the FDA’s Restrictive Regulation of Home Testing Devices. 不要在家里尝试:FDA对家庭测试设备的限制性规定。
IF 1.9 2区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2017-11-01
Shelby Baird

Over the past forty years, the Food and Drug Administration (FDA) has successfully restricted consumers' access to home-testing applications based on the notion that it should protect individuals from their own reactions to test results. In the 1970s, the FDA briefly denied women access to home pregnancy tests that were identical to those used in laboratories. In the late 1980s and early 1990s, it relied on concerns about consumer responses to HIV status results to justify a categorical ban on applications for HIV home-testing technology. More recently, it placed burdensome restrictions on direct-to-consumer (DTC) genetic testing companies, such as 23andMe, based on fears that consumerswould make irrational medical decisions after receiving genetic variant results. Although the FDA has the statutory authority to ensure the "safety and effectiveness" of medical devices, it has expansively interpreted the term "safety" to encompass considerations of how consumers might use test results provided by purely informative devices. This Noteargues that courts should not give the FDA deference on its broad interpretation of safety" in restricting home-testing devices. It documents the evolution of the expertise-based rationale for judicial deference, noting that courts typically provide scientific agencies, including the FDA, "super deference" because of the complicated nature of their work. Ultimately, courts should not defer to the FDA's interpretation of "safety" because it did not use its scientific expertisewhen it considered how consumers might react to HIV home-testing and DTC genetic testing results. Further, the FDA should not have the authority to make decisions based on its view of "safety" because it should not have the power to make value judgments for consumers about whether they should seek their personal medical information.

在过去的四十年里,美国食品和药物管理局(FDA)已经成功地限制了消费者使用家庭测试应用程序,其理念是它应该保护个人免受自己对测试结果的反应。在20世纪70年代,FDA曾短暂地拒绝女性使用与实验室使用的相同的家用验孕棒。在20世纪80年代末和90年代初,由于担心消费者对艾滋病毒检测结果的反应,它明确禁止使用艾滋病毒家庭检测技术。最近,由于担心消费者在收到基因变异结果后会做出不合理的医疗决定,它对23andMe等直接面向消费者(DTC)的基因检测公司施加了繁重的限制。尽管FDA有法定权力确保医疗器械的“安全性和有效性”,但它对“安全性”一词的解释过于宽泛,包括考虑消费者如何使用纯信息设备提供的检测结果。本报告认为,法院不应在限制家庭检测设备时服从FDA对“安全”的广义解释。它记录了基于专业知识的司法尊重的基本原理的演变,指出法院通常会向包括FDA在内的科学机构提供“超级尊重”,因为它们的工作性质复杂。最终,法院不应该听从FDA对“安全”的解释,因为它在考虑消费者对HIV家庭检测和DTC基因检测结果的反应时没有使用其科学专业知识。此外,FDA不应该有权力根据其对“安全”的看法做出决定,因为它不应该有权力就消费者是否应该寻求他们的个人医疗信息做出价值判断。
{"title":"Don’t Try This at Home: the FDA’s Restrictive Regulation of Home Testing Devices.","authors":"Shelby Baird","doi":"","DOIUrl":"","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Over the past forty years, the Food and Drug Administration (FDA) has successfully restricted consumers' access to home-testing applications based on the notion that it should protect individuals from their own reactions to test results. In the 1970s, the FDA briefly denied women access to home pregnancy tests that were identical to those used in laboratories. In the late 1980s and early 1990s, it relied on concerns about consumer responses to HIV status results to justify a categorical ban on applications for HIV home-testing technology. More recently, it placed burdensome restrictions on direct-to-consumer (DTC) genetic testing companies, such as 23andMe, based on fears that consumers\u0000would make irrational medical decisions after receiving genetic variant results. Although the FDA has the statutory authority to ensure the \"safety and effectiveness\" of medical devices, it has expansively interpreted the term \"safety\" to encompass considerations of how consumers might use test results provided by purely informative devices. This Note\u0000argues that courts should not give the FDA deference on its broad interpretation of safety\" in restricting home-testing devices. It documents the evolution of the expertise-based rationale for judicial deference, noting that courts typically provide scientific agencies, including the FDA, \"super deference\" because of the complicated nature of their work. Ultimately, courts should not defer to the FDA's interpretation of \"safety\" because it did not use its scientific expertise\u0000when it considered how consumers might react to HIV home-testing and DTC genetic testing results. Further, the FDA should not have the authority to make decisions based on its view of \"safety\" because it should not have the power to make value judgments for consumers about whether they should seek their personal medical information.</p>","PeriodicalId":47625,"journal":{"name":"Duke Law Journal","volume":"67 2","pages":"383-426"},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2017-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"35854122","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Exiting Congressional-Executive Agreements 退出国会行政协议
IF 1.9 2区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2017-10-25 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.3049279
C. Bradley
Some commentators have argued that, even if the President has the unilateral authority to terminate Article II treaties concluded with the Senate’s advice and consent, the President lacks the unilateral authority to terminate “congressional-executive agreements” concluded with majority congressional approval, such as the North American Free Trade Agreement (NAFTA). This paper challenges that claim. If one accepts a presidential authority to terminate Article II treaties, this paper contends, there is no compelling reason to conclude differently with respect to congressional-executive agreements. Congressional-executive agreements have become largely interchangeable with Article II treaties as a matter of domestic law and practice, and, thus, for example, either instrument can be used to address matters relating to international commerce and trade. Moreover, while presidents do not have the authority to unilaterally terminate statutes, congressional-executive agreements are not mere statutes; they are, like Article II treaties, binding international instruments that can be concluded by the United States only through presidential action. These agreements also typically contain withdrawal clauses similar to the ones contained in Article II treaties that presidents have long claimed the authority to invoke unilaterally, and Congress has never indicated that it views presidents as having less withdrawal authority for such agreements. Indeed, in its trade legislation, Congress appears to have accepted that presidents may invoke such clauses unilaterally.
一些评论家认为,即使总统有权单方面终止经参议院建议和同意缔结的第二条条约,总统也没有单方面终止经国会多数批准缔结的“国会-行政协定”的权力,例如北美自由贸易协定(NAFTA)。本文对这种说法提出了挑战。如果一个人接受总统的权力来终止第二条条约,本文认为,就国会-行政协议而言,没有令人信服的理由得出不同的结论。作为国内法和实践的问题,国会-行政协定在很大程度上已经与第二条条约可以互换,因此,例如,任何一种文书都可以用来处理与国际商业和贸易有关的问题。此外,虽然总统没有权力单方面终止成文法,但国会-行政机构协议并不仅仅是成文法;它们就像第二条条约一样,是具有约束力的国际文书,只有通过总统的行动才能由美国缔结。这些协议通常还包含类似于美国总统长期以来声称有权单方面援引的第二条条约中的退出条款,而国会从未表示,它认为总统在这类协议中的退出权力更小。事实上,在其贸易立法中,国会似乎已经接受了总统可以单方面援引此类条款。
{"title":"Exiting Congressional-Executive Agreements","authors":"C. Bradley","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.3049279","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.3049279","url":null,"abstract":"Some commentators have argued that, even if the President has the unilateral authority to terminate Article II treaties concluded with the Senate’s advice and consent, the President lacks the unilateral authority to terminate “congressional-executive agreements” concluded with majority congressional approval, such as the North American Free Trade Agreement (NAFTA). This paper challenges that claim. If one accepts a presidential authority to terminate Article II treaties, this paper contends, there is no compelling reason to conclude differently with respect to congressional-executive agreements. Congressional-executive agreements have become largely interchangeable with Article II treaties as a matter of domestic law and practice, and, thus, for example, either instrument can be used to address matters relating to international commerce and trade. Moreover, while presidents do not have the authority to unilaterally terminate statutes, congressional-executive agreements are not mere statutes; they are, like Article II treaties, binding international instruments that can be concluded by the United States only through presidential action. These agreements also typically contain withdrawal clauses similar to the ones contained in Article II treaties that presidents have long claimed the authority to invoke unilaterally, and Congress has never indicated that it views presidents as having less withdrawal authority for such agreements. Indeed, in its trade legislation, Congress appears to have accepted that presidents may invoke such clauses unilaterally.","PeriodicalId":47625,"journal":{"name":"Duke Law Journal","volume":"67 1","pages":"1615-1645"},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2017-10-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.3049279","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42847092","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Fixing Law Reviews 修正法律检讨
IF 1.9 2区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2017-07-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.3011602
Barry D. Friedman
Very few people are happy at present with the law review publishing process, from article submission and selection to editing. Complaints are longstanding, and similar ones emerge from faculty and students alike. Yet, heretofore, change has not occurred. Instead, we are locked in our ugly world of submit and expedite, stepping on the toes of numerous student editors in the process. And the editing process falls far short of ideal. This Article recommends wholesale change to the submission and editing process. The first part details the dysfunctions of the current system, including everything from lack of student capacity to evaluate faculty scholarship — particularly under the gun of the expedite process — to faculty submitting subpar work in light of rigid submission cycles. It then turns to making a perverse defense of the current system. In light of technological change, law reviews play a very different function at present than even twenty years ago. Most faculty publish their work on electronic databases even prior to submission to law reviews. Law reviews serve as the final resting place of those articles for archival purposes, while ostensibly providing students with a sound pedagogical experience. Part three undercuts the perverse defense by pointing to the huge and unacceptable costs of the present system, in which student editors scramble over one another to accept manuscripts, often wasting time on rejected submissions, while faculty labor with student-overediting, all in the service of articles that for the most part are rarely or never cited. The final part of this article is a raft of suggestions to change the present system to produce better published scholarship, at lower cost to faculty and students, including blind submission, elimination of submitting articles to one’s own school, some form of peer review, and limiting submissions or requiring authors to accept the offer they receive. The suggestions extend to the editing process, which — at present — is out of control, and does little to make scholarship the best it can be.
目前,很少有人对法律评论的发布过程感到满意,从文章提交、选择到编辑。投诉由来已久,师生之间也出现了类似的投诉。然而,到目前为止,变化还没有发生。相反,我们被困在提交和加速的丑陋世界里,在这个过程中踩到了无数学生编辑的脚趾。编辑过程远远达不到理想。本文建议对提交和编辑过程进行全面修改。第一部分详细介绍了当前系统的功能失调,包括从学生缺乏评估教师奖学金的能力——尤其是在快速程序的枪口下——到教师根据严格的提交周期提交不合格的作品。然后,它转而对现行制度进行不正当的辩护。鉴于技术的变化,法律评论在目前发挥着与二十年前截然不同的作用。大多数教员甚至在提交法律审查之前就在电子数据库上公布了他们的工作。法律评论是这些文章的最后安息之地,用于档案目的,同时表面上为学生提供了良好的教学体验。第三部分指出了现行制度的巨大且不可接受的成本,从而削弱了这种不正当的辩护。在这种制度中,学生编辑们争先恐后地接受稿件,经常在被拒绝的稿件上浪费时间,而教师们则忙于学生的过度编辑,所有这些都是为了服务于大多数很少或从未被引用的文章。这篇文章的最后一部分是一系列建议,旨在改变现行制度,以更低的成本为师生提供更好的奖学金,包括盲目提交、取消向自己的学校提交文章、某种形式的同行评审,以及限制提交或要求作者接受他们收到的录取通知书。这些建议延伸到了编辑过程,目前编辑过程已经失控,对学术界的最佳表现几乎没有帮助。
{"title":"Fixing Law Reviews","authors":"Barry D. Friedman","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.3011602","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.3011602","url":null,"abstract":"Very few people are happy at present with the law review publishing process, from article submission and selection to editing. Complaints are longstanding, and similar ones emerge from faculty and students alike. Yet, heretofore, change has not occurred. Instead, we are locked in our ugly world of submit and expedite, stepping on the toes of numerous student editors in the process. And the editing process falls far short of ideal. \u0000This Article recommends wholesale change to the submission and editing process. The first part details the dysfunctions of the current system, including everything from lack of student capacity to evaluate faculty scholarship — particularly under the gun of the expedite process — to faculty submitting subpar work in light of rigid submission cycles. It then turns to making a perverse defense of the current system. In light of technological change, law reviews play a very different function at present than even twenty years ago. Most faculty publish their work on electronic databases even prior to submission to law reviews. Law reviews serve as the final resting place of those articles for archival purposes, while ostensibly providing students with a sound pedagogical experience. Part three undercuts the perverse defense by pointing to the huge and unacceptable costs of the present system, in which student editors scramble over one another to accept manuscripts, often wasting time on rejected submissions, while faculty labor with student-overediting, all in the service of articles that for the most part are rarely or never cited. \u0000The final part of this article is a raft of suggestions to change the present system to produce better published scholarship, at lower cost to faculty and students, including blind submission, elimination of submitting articles to one’s own school, some form of peer review, and limiting submissions or requiring authors to accept the offer they receive. The suggestions extend to the editing process, which — at present — is out of control, and does little to make scholarship the best it can be.","PeriodicalId":47625,"journal":{"name":"Duke Law Journal","volume":"67 1","pages":"1297-1380"},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2017-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49109088","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 7
Data Privacy and Dignitary Privacy: Google Spain, the Right to Be Forgotten, and the Construction of the Public Sphere 数据隐私与尊严隐私:谷歌西班牙、被遗忘权与公共领域的构建
IF 1.9 2区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2017-04-15 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2953468
R. Post
In 2014, the decision of the European Court of Justice in Google Spain SL v. Agencia Espanola de Proteccion de Datos (“Google Spain”) set off a firestorm by holding that the fair information practices set forth in EU Directive 95/46/EC, which is probably the most influential data privacy text in the world, require that Google remove from search results links to websites that contain true information. Google Spain held that the Directive gives persons a “right to be forgotten.” As a result of Google Spain, Google has processed 703,910 requests to remove 1,948,737 URLs from its search engine, and some 43.2% of these URLs have been erased from searches made under the name of the person requesting removal. The world-wide influence of Google Spain is likely to become even greater when the EU promulgates it General Data Protection Regulation (“GDPR”) in 2018. At stake in Google Spain were both privacy values and freedom of expression values. Google Spain inadequately analyzes both. With regard to the latter, Google Spain fails to recognize that the circulation of texts of common interest among strangers makes possible the emergence of a “public” capable of forming “public opinion.” The creation of public opinion is essential for democratic self-governance and is a central purpose for protecting freedom of expression. As the rise of American newspapers in the 19th and 20th Century demonstrates, the press underwrites the public sphere by creating a structure of communication that is responsive to public curiosity and that is independent of the content of any particular news story. Google sustains the virtual public sphere by creating an analogous structure of communication. Even though Google is not itself an “author,” it should nevertheless have been accorded the same legal status as traditional press. With regard to privacy values, EU law, like the law of many nations, recognizes two distinct forms of privacy. The first is data privacy, which is protected by Article 8 of the Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union. Data privacy is safeguarded by fair information practices designed to ensure (among other things) that personal data is used only for the specified purposes for which it has been legally gathered. Data privacy operates according to an instrumental logic, and it applies whenever personal information is processed. Its object is ensure that persons retain “control” over their personal data. Google Spain interprets the Directive to give persons a right to have their personal data “forgotten” or erased whenever it is “inadequate, irrelevant or no longer relevant, or excessive in relation to the purposes of the processing at issue carried out by the operator of the search engine.” It is not necessary to show that the processing of such data will cause harm. In contrast to data privacy, Article 7 of the Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union is entitled “Respect for Family and Private Life.” Article 7 is to be understood
2014年,欧洲法院在Google Spain SL诉Agencia Espanola de Proteccion de Datos(“Google Spain”)一案中的裁决引发了轩然大波,认为欧盟指令95/46/EC中规定的公平信息做法可能是世界上最具影响力的数据隐私文本,要求谷歌从搜索结果中删除包含真实信息的网站链接。谷歌西班牙认为,该指令赋予了人们“被遗忘权”。由于谷歌西班牙,谷歌已经处理了703910个请求,从其搜索引擎中删除1948737个URL,其中约43.2%的URL已从以请求删除的人的名义进行的搜索中删除。当欧盟于2018年颁布《通用数据保护条例》(“GDPR”)时,谷歌西班牙的全球影响力可能会变得更大。谷歌西班牙的利害关系是隐私价值观和言论自由价值观。谷歌西班牙公司对两者的分析都不充分。关于后者,谷歌西班牙没有认识到,陌生人之间共同感兴趣的文本的传播使得能够形成“舆论”的“公众”的出现成为可能。创造舆论对民主自治至关重要,也是保护言论自由的核心目的。正如19世纪和20世纪美国报纸的兴起所表明的那样,新闻界通过创造一种回应公众好奇心、独立于任何特定新闻报道内容的传播结构来为公共领域提供支持。谷歌通过创建类似的通信结构来维持虚拟公共领域。尽管谷歌本身不是“作者”,但它本应被赋予与传统媒体相同的法律地位。关于隐私价值观,欧盟法律与许多国家的法律一样,承认两种不同形式的隐私。第一个是数据隐私,它受到《欧洲联盟基本权利宪章》第八条的保护。数据隐私受到公平信息做法的保护,该做法旨在确保(除其他外)个人数据仅用于合法收集的特定目的。数据隐私根据工具逻辑运作,无论何时处理个人信息,它都适用。其目的是确保个人保留对其个人数据的“控制权”。谷歌西班牙公司对该指令的解释是,当个人数据“与搜索引擎运营商进行的处理目的不充分、不相关或不再相关或过度”时,赋予人们“遗忘”或删除其个人数据的权利。没有必要证明处理此类数据会造成伤害。与数据隐私相反,《欧洲联盟基本权利宪章》第7条题为“尊重家庭和私人生活”。第7条的理解类似于欧洲人权法院对《欧洲公约》第8条的解释。因此,《宪章》第七条保护人的尊严,控制可能使人受到侮辱、羞辱或羞辱的不当通信。第7条中有争议的隐私遵循一个规范逻辑,防止违反文明规则对人格造成伤害。第7条包含了与美国公开披露私人事实侵权行为所保护的隐私价值观相同的隐私价值。它保护我们可以称之为“政要隐私”的东西。在世界各地,法院通过平衡通信可能对个人诚信造成的伤害与通信对民主自治所必需的公共话语的重要性来保护政要隐私。数据隐私的工具逻辑不适用于公共话语,这就是为什么该指令和GDPR都包含对新闻活动的贬损。公共领域的交流行为特征是由主体间对话组成的,这与数据隐私的工具理性及其确保个人信息控制的愿望背道而驰。因此,谷歌西班牙公司将该指令的公平信息实践应用于谷歌搜索引擎是一个错误。但谷歌西班牙的意见也援引了第7条,最终该意见制定了一些理论规则,这些规则大致让人想起了那些用来保护政要隐私的规则。因此,谷歌西班牙的意见对其希望保护的隐私深感困惑。无法确定该决定是为了保护数据隐私还是为了保护政要隐私。谷歌西班牙最终被推向了政要隐私的方向,因为它很清楚政要隐私要求如何与公共话语的要求相协调。 尽管权贵隐私的规范逻辑可能与言论自由相矛盾,但它并不像数据隐私的工具逻辑那样与言论自由不相容。就言论自由因其促进民主自治而受到重视而言,如果没有一点文明,公共话语就无法成为有效的自治工具。然而,谷歌西班牙公司的决定只是以一种基本且令人不满意的方式承认了政要的隐私。它没有充分理论化谷歌链接可能造成的危害,以及这些链接对公共话语的贡献。此外,如果谷歌西班牙公司更明确地关注政要隐私的要求,它就不可能如此鲜明地将谷歌与谷歌链接所指的底层网站区分开来。谷歌西班牙不可能轻而易举地将被遗忘权的执行外包给谷歌这样的私人公司。
{"title":"Data Privacy and Dignitary Privacy: Google Spain, the Right to Be Forgotten, and the Construction of the Public Sphere","authors":"R. Post","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2953468","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2953468","url":null,"abstract":"In 2014, the decision of the European Court of Justice in Google Spain SL v. Agencia Espanola de Proteccion de Datos (“Google Spain”) set off a firestorm by holding that the fair information practices set forth in EU Directive 95/46/EC, which is probably the most influential data privacy text in the world, require that Google remove from search results links to websites that contain true information. Google Spain held that the Directive gives persons a “right to be forgotten.” As a result of Google Spain, Google has processed 703,910 requests to remove 1,948,737 URLs from its search engine, and some 43.2% of these URLs have been erased from searches made under the name of the person requesting removal. The world-wide influence of Google Spain is likely to become even greater when the EU promulgates it General Data Protection Regulation (“GDPR”) in 2018. \u0000At stake in Google Spain were both privacy values and freedom of expression values. Google Spain inadequately analyzes both. With regard to the latter, Google Spain fails to recognize that the circulation of texts of common interest among strangers makes possible the emergence of a “public” capable of forming “public opinion.” The creation of public opinion is essential for democratic self-governance and is a central purpose for protecting freedom of expression. As the rise of American newspapers in the 19th and 20th Century demonstrates, the press underwrites the public sphere by creating a structure of communication that is responsive to public curiosity and that is independent of the content of any particular news story. Google sustains the virtual public sphere by creating an analogous structure of communication. Even though Google is not itself an “author,” it should nevertheless have been accorded the same legal status as traditional press. \u0000With regard to privacy values, EU law, like the law of many nations, recognizes two distinct forms of privacy. The first is data privacy, which is protected by Article 8 of the Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union. Data privacy is safeguarded by fair information practices designed to ensure (among other things) that personal data is used only for the specified purposes for which it has been legally gathered. Data privacy operates according to an instrumental logic, and it applies whenever personal information is processed. Its object is ensure that persons retain “control” over their personal data. Google Spain interprets the Directive to give persons a right to have their personal data “forgotten” or erased whenever it is “inadequate, irrelevant or no longer relevant, or excessive in relation to the purposes of the processing at issue carried out by the operator of the search engine.” It is not necessary to show that the processing of such data will cause harm. \u0000In contrast to data privacy, Article 7 of the Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union is entitled “Respect for Family and Private Life.” Article 7 is to be understood","PeriodicalId":47625,"journal":{"name":"Duke Law Journal","volume":"67 1","pages":"981-1072"},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2017-04-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.2953468","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49291425","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 18
Contracts: Ex Machina 合同:机械交货
IF 1.9 2区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2017-03-18 DOI: 10.5040/9781509937059.ch-001
K. Werbach, N. Cornell
Smart contracts are self-executing digital transactions using decentralized cryptographic mechanisms for enforcement. They were theorized more than twenty years ago, but the recent development of Bitcoin and blockchain technologies has rekindled excitement about their potential among technologists and industry. Startup companies and major enterprises alike are now developing smart contract solutions for an array of markets, purporting to offer a digital bypass around traditional contract law. For legal scholars, smart contracts pose a significant question: Can smart contracts offer a superior solution to the problem that contract law addresses? In this article, we aim to understand both the potential and the limitations of smart contracts. We conclude that smart contracts offer novel possibilities, may significantly alter the commercial world, and will demand new legal responses. But smart contracts will not displace contract law. Understanding why not brings into focus the essential role of contract law as a remedial institution. In this way, smart contracts actually can illuminate the role of contract law more than they can obviate it.
智能合约是使用去中心化加密机制进行强制执行的自动执行数字交易。它们是20多年前理论化的,但比特币和区块链技术的最新发展重新点燃了技术专家和行业对其潜力的兴奋。初创公司和大企业现在都在为一系列市场开发智能合同解决方案,旨在绕过传统合同法提供数字绕过。对于法律学者来说,智能合约提出了一个重要的问题:智能合约能否为合同法所解决的问题提供更好的解决方案?在本文中,我们旨在了解智能合约的潜力和局限性。我们得出的结论是,智能合约提供了新的可能性,可能会显著改变商业世界,并需要新的法律回应。但智能合约不会取代合同法。理解为什么不让人们关注合同法作为一种补救制度的基本作用。通过这种方式,智能合约实际上可以阐明合同法的作用,而不是排除它。
{"title":"Contracts: Ex Machina","authors":"K. Werbach, N. Cornell","doi":"10.5040/9781509937059.ch-001","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5040/9781509937059.ch-001","url":null,"abstract":"Smart contracts are self-executing digital transactions using decentralized cryptographic mechanisms for enforcement. They were theorized more than twenty years ago, but the recent development of Bitcoin and blockchain technologies has rekindled excitement about their potential among technologists and industry. Startup companies and major enterprises alike are now developing smart contract solutions for an array of markets, purporting to offer a digital bypass around traditional contract law. For legal scholars, smart contracts pose a significant question: Can smart contracts offer a superior solution to the problem that contract law addresses? In this article, we aim to understand both the potential and the limitations of smart contracts. We conclude that smart contracts offer novel possibilities, may significantly alter the commercial world, and will demand new legal responses. But smart contracts will not displace contract law. Understanding why not brings into focus the essential role of contract law as a remedial institution. In this way, smart contracts actually can illuminate the role of contract law more than they can obviate it.","PeriodicalId":47625,"journal":{"name":"Duke Law Journal","volume":"67 1","pages":"313-382"},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2017-03-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42858515","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 140
Ad Hoc Diplomats 特设外交官
IF 1.9 2区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2017-03-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2926010
Ryan M. Scoville
Article II of the Constitution grants the president power to appoint “Ambassadors” and “other public Ministers” with the advice and consent of the Senate. By all accounts, this language requires Senate confirmation for the appointment of resident ambassadors and other diplomats of similar rank and tenure. Yet these are hardly the only agents of U.S. foreign relations. Ad hoc diplomats — individuals chosen exclusively by the president to complete limited and temporary assignments — play a comparably significant role in addressing international crises, negotiating treaties, and otherwise executing foreign policy. This Article critically examines the appointments process for such irregular agents. An orthodox view holds it permissible for the president to dispatch any ad hoc diplomat without Senate confirmation, but this view does not accord with the original meaning of Article II. Scrutinizing text and an extensive collection of original historical sources, I show that, under a formalist reading of the Constitution, the appointment of most ad hoc diplomats requires the advice and consent of the Senate because these agents are typically “public Ministers” and “Officers of the United States” under the Appointments Clause. The analysis makes several contributions. First, it provides the first thorough account of the original meaning of “public Ministers” — a term that appears several times in the Constitution but lacks precise contours in contemporary scholarship and practice. Second, for formalists, the analysis reorients longstanding debates about the process of treaty-making and empowers the Senate to exert greater influence over a wide variety of presidential initiatives, including communications with North Korea, the renegotiation of trade agreements, the campaign to defeat ISIS, and the stabilization of Ukraine, all of which depend on the work of ad hoc diplomats. At a time of trepidation over the nature of U.S. foreign policy, such influence might operate as a stabilizing force. Third, the analysis illuminates rhetorical and doctrinal maneuvers that have facilitated the rise of the modern presidency, including historical revisionism and the marginalization of international law as an input in constitutional interpretation. These maneuvers complicate the political valence of originalism and cast the Justice Department’s Office of Legal Counsel (OLC) — a key proponent of the orthodox view — as a motivated expositor of the separation of powers.
宪法第二条赋予总统在参议院的建议和同意下任命“大使”和“其他公使”的权力。大家都说,这种措词需要参议院批准才能任命驻地大使和具有类似级别和任期的其他外交官。然而,这些并不是美国外交关系的唯一代理人。临时外交官——由总统专门挑选来完成有限和临时任务的个人——在处理国际危机、谈判条约和执行外交政策方面发挥着相当重要的作用。这篇文章批判性地审查了这种非正规代理人的任命过程。传统观点认为,总统可以在没有参议院批准的情况下派遣特别外交官,但这种观点与宪法第二条的原意不符。在仔细审查文本和大量收集的原始历史资料后,我表明,根据对宪法的形式主义解读,大多数临时外交官的任命需要参议院的建议和同意,因为根据任命条款,这些代理人通常是“公共部长”和“美国官员”。该分析有几点贡献。首先,它提供了对“公共部长”原意的第一次彻底的解释——这个术语在宪法中出现了几次,但在当代学术和实践中缺乏精确的轮廓。其次,对于形式主义者来说,该分析重新定位了长期以来关于条约制定过程的争论,并赋予参议院对总统的各种倡议施加更大影响的权力,包括与朝鲜的沟通、重新谈判贸易协定、打击ISIS的行动,以及稳定乌克兰局势,所有这些都依赖于特别外交官的工作。在人们对美国外交政策的本质感到不安的时候,这种影响力可能会起到稳定力量的作用。第三,分析阐明了促进现代总统崛起的修辞和理论手段,包括历史修正主义和将国际法边缘化,将其作为宪法解释的输入。这些策略使原旨主义的政治价值复杂化,并使司法部法律顾问办公室(OLC)——正统观点的关键支持者——成为三权分立的积极阐释者。
{"title":"Ad Hoc Diplomats","authors":"Ryan M. Scoville","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2926010","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2926010","url":null,"abstract":"Article II of the Constitution grants the president power to appoint “Ambassadors” and “other public Ministers” with the advice and consent of the Senate. By all accounts, this language requires Senate confirmation for the appointment of resident ambassadors and other diplomats of similar rank and tenure. Yet these are hardly the only agents of U.S. foreign relations. Ad hoc diplomats — individuals chosen exclusively by the president to complete limited and temporary assignments — play a comparably significant role in addressing international crises, negotiating treaties, and otherwise executing foreign policy. \u0000 \u0000This Article critically examines the appointments process for such irregular agents. An orthodox view holds it permissible for the president to dispatch any ad hoc diplomat without Senate confirmation, but this view does not accord with the original meaning of Article II. Scrutinizing text and an extensive collection of original historical sources, I show that, under a formalist reading of the Constitution, the appointment of most ad hoc diplomats requires the advice and consent of the Senate because these agents are typically “public Ministers” and “Officers of the United States” under the Appointments Clause. \u0000 \u0000The analysis makes several contributions. First, it provides the first thorough account of the original meaning of “public Ministers” — a term that appears several times in the Constitution but lacks precise contours in contemporary scholarship and practice. Second, for formalists, the analysis reorients longstanding debates about the process of treaty-making and empowers the Senate to exert greater influence over a wide variety of presidential initiatives, including communications with North Korea, the renegotiation of trade agreements, the campaign to defeat ISIS, and the stabilization of Ukraine, all of which depend on the work of ad hoc diplomats. At a time of trepidation over the nature of U.S. foreign policy, such influence might operate as a stabilizing force. Third, the analysis illuminates rhetorical and doctrinal maneuvers that have facilitated the rise of the modern presidency, including historical revisionism and the marginalization of international law as an input in constitutional interpretation. These maneuvers complicate the political valence of originalism and cast the Justice Department’s Office of Legal Counsel (OLC) — a key proponent of the orthodox view — as a motivated expositor of the separation of powers.","PeriodicalId":47625,"journal":{"name":"Duke Law Journal","volume":"68 1","pages":"907-1002"},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2017-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44968747","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Health Care's Other "Big Deal": Direct Primary Care Regulation in Contemporary American Health Law. 医疗保健的另一个“大交易”:当代美国卫生法中的直接初级保健监管。
IF 1.9 2区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2017-03-01
Glenn E Chappell

Direct primary care is a promising, market-based alternative to the fee-for-service payment structure that shapes doctor–patientrelationships in America. Instead of billing patients and insurers service by service, direct primary care doctors charge their patients a periodic, prenegotiated fee in exchange for providing a wide range of healthcare services and increased availability compared to traditional practices. This “subscription” model is intended to eliminate the administrative burdens associated with insurer interaction, which, in theory, allows doctors to spend more time with their patients and less time doing paperwork.Direct practices have become increasingly popular since Congress passed the Affordable Care Act (ACA). This growth has been driven by legislation in several states that resolves a number of legal questions that slowed the model’s growth and by the ACA’srecognition of the model as a permissible way to cover primary care in "approved" health plans. Yet legal scholars have hardly focused on direct primary care. Given the model’s growth, however, the time is ripe for a more focused legal inquiry. This Note begins that inquiry. After tracing the model’s evolution and its core components, this Note substantively examines the laws instates that regulate direct practices and analyzes how those laws address a number of potential policy concerns. It then analyzes direct primary care’s broader role in the contemporary American healthcare marketplace. Based upon that analysis, this Note concludes that direct primary care is a beneficial innovation that harmonizes well with a cooperative-federalism-based healthcare policy model.

直接初级保健是一种很有前途的、以市场为基础的替代方案,它取代了影响美国医患关系的按服务收费的支付结构。直接初级保健医生不是按服务向患者和保险公司收费,而是定期向患者收取预先商定的费用,以换取提供广泛的医疗保健服务,并与传统做法相比增加了可用性。这种“订阅”模式旨在消除与保险公司互动相关的行政负担,从理论上讲,这使得医生可以花更多的时间与病人在一起,而不用花更多的时间做文书工作。自国会通过《平价医疗法案》(ACA)以来,直接实践越来越受欢迎。这一增长是由几个州的立法推动的,这些立法解决了许多减缓该模式发展的法律问题,同时ACA也承认该模式是一种在“批准的”健康计划中涵盖初级保健的允许方式。然而,法律学者很少关注直接初级保健。然而,鉴于该模式的发展,进行更有针对性的法律调查的时机已经成熟。本照会开始进行这项调查。在追踪了模型的演变及其核心组成部分之后,本说明实质性地检查了规范直接实践的法律状态,并分析了这些法律如何处理一些潜在的政策问题。然后分析了直接初级保健在当代美国医疗保健市场中更广泛的作用。根据这一分析,本文得出结论,直接初级保健是一项有益的创新,它与基于合作联邦制的医疗保健政策模型很好地协调一致。
{"title":"Health Care's Other \"Big Deal\": Direct Primary Care Regulation in Contemporary American Health Law.","authors":"Glenn E Chappell","doi":"","DOIUrl":"","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Direct primary care is a promising, market-based alternative to the fee-for-service payment structure that shapes doctor–patient\u0000relationships in America. Instead of billing patients and insurers service by service, direct primary care doctors charge their patients a periodic, prenegotiated fee in exchange for providing a wide range of healthcare services and increased availability compared to traditional practices. This “subscription” model is intended to eliminate the administrative burdens associated with insurer interaction, which, in theory, allows doctors to spend more time with their patients and less time doing paperwork.\u0000Direct practices have become increasingly popular since Congress passed the Affordable Care Act (ACA). This growth has been driven by legislation in several states that resolves a number of legal questions that slowed the model’s growth and by the ACA’s\u0000recognition of the model as a permissible way to cover primary care in \"approved\" health plans. Yet legal scholars have hardly focused on direct primary care. Given the model’s growth, however, the time is ripe for a more focused legal inquiry. This Note begins that inquiry. After tracing the model’s evolution and its core components, this Note substantively examines the laws in\u0000states that regulate direct practices and analyzes how those laws address a number of potential policy concerns. It then analyzes direct primary care’s broader role in the contemporary American healthcare marketplace. Based upon that analysis, this Note concludes that direct primary care is a beneficial innovation that harmonizes well with a cooperative-federalism-based healthcare policy model.</p>","PeriodicalId":47625,"journal":{"name":"Duke Law Journal","volume":"66 6","pages":"1331-70"},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2017-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"34885109","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Rape Beyond Crime. 强奸超越犯罪。
IF 1.9 2区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2017-02-01
Margo Kaplan

Public health experts agree that sexual violence constitutes a significant public health issue. Yet criminal law dominates rape law almost completely, with public health law playing at best a small supporting role. Recent civil law developments, such as university disciplinary proceedings, similarly fixate on how best to find and penalize perpetrators. As a result, rape law continues to spin its wheels in the same arguments and obstacles. This Article argues that, without broader cultural changes, criminal law faces a double bind: rape laws will either be ineffective or neglect the importance of individual culpability. Public health law provides more promising terrain for rape prevention because it is a strong legal framework that can engage the complex causes of rape, including the social norms that promote sexual aggression. While criminal law can only punish bad behavior, public health interventions can use the moreeffective prevention strategy of promoting positive behaviors and relationships. They can also address the myriad sexual behaviors and social determinants that increase the risk of rape but are outside the scope of criminal law. Perhaps most importantly, public health law relies on evidence-based interventions and the expertise of public health authorities to ensure that laws and policies are effective. Transforming rape law in this way provides a framework for legalfeminism to undertake the unmet challenge of "theorizing yes," that is, moving beyond how to protect women’s right to refuse sex and toward promoting and exploring positive models of sex. Criminal law is simply incapable of meeting this challenge because it concerns only what sex should not be. A public health framework can give the law a richer role in addressing the full spectrum of sexual attitudes and behaviors.

公共卫生专家一致认为,性暴力构成了一个重大的公共卫生问题。然而,刑法几乎完全支配着强奸法,公共卫生法充其量只是一个小小的辅助作用。最近民法的发展,如大学纪律处分程序,同样关注于如何最好地发现和惩罚犯罪者。因此,强奸法继续在同样的争论和障碍中旋转。本文认为,如果没有更广泛的文化变革,刑法将面临双重困境:强奸法要么无效,要么忽视个人罪责的重要性。公共卫生法为预防强奸提供了更有希望的领域,因为它是一个强有力的法律框架,可以涉及强奸的复杂原因,包括促进性侵犯的社会规范。虽然刑法只能惩罚不良行为,但公共卫生干预措施可以采用促进积极行为和关系的更有效的预防策略。他们还可以解决无数的性行为和社会决定因素,这些行为和社会决定因素增加了强奸的风险,但不在刑法的范围之内。也许最重要的是,公共卫生法依赖于以证据为基础的干预措施和公共卫生当局的专门知识,以确保法律和政策的有效性。以这种方式改变强奸法,为法律女权主义提供了一个框架,使其能够承担“理论化是”的挑战,也就是说,超越如何保护女性拒绝性行为的权利,走向促进和探索积极的性模式。刑法根本无法应对这一挑战,因为它只关注什么是不应该发生的性。公共卫生框架可使法律在处理各种性态度和性行为方面发挥更大作用。
{"title":"Rape Beyond Crime.","authors":"Margo Kaplan","doi":"","DOIUrl":"","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Public health experts agree that sexual violence constitutes a significant public health issue. Yet criminal law dominates rape law almost completely, with public health law playing at best a small supporting role. Recent civil law developments, such as university disciplinary proceedings, similarly fixate on how best to find and penalize perpetrators. As a result, rape law continues to spin its wheels in the same arguments and obstacles. This Article argues that, without broader cultural changes, criminal law faces a double bind: rape laws will either be ineffective or neglect the importance of individual culpability. Public health law provides more promising terrain for rape prevention because it is a strong legal framework that can engage the complex causes of rape, including the social norms that promote sexual aggression. While criminal law can only punish bad behavior, public health interventions can use the more\u0000effective prevention strategy of promoting positive behaviors and relationships. They can also address the myriad sexual behaviors and social determinants that increase the risk of rape but are outside the scope of criminal law. Perhaps most importantly, public health law relies on evidence-based interventions and the expertise of public health authorities to ensure that laws and policies are effective. Transforming rape law in this way provides a framework for legal\u0000feminism to undertake the unmet challenge of \"theorizing yes,\" that is, moving beyond how to protect women’s right to refuse sex and toward promoting and exploring positive models of sex. Criminal law is simply incapable of meeting this challenge because it concerns only what sex should not be. A public health framework can give the law a richer role in addressing the full spectrum of sexual attitudes and behaviors.</p>","PeriodicalId":47625,"journal":{"name":"Duke Law Journal","volume":"66 5","pages":"1045-111"},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2017-02-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"34761658","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Class is Greener on the Other Side: How Private Donations to Public Schools Play into Fair Funding 另一边的课堂更环保:私立学校的捐款如何成为公平的资助
IF 1.9 2区 社会学 Q1 LAW Pub Date : 2017-01-09 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2915479
A. Frisch
Public schools have long drawn on private sources of funding to supplement federal, state, and local public funding. In the last thirty years, private funding has grown in sophistication and prominence, leading many schools to increasingly rely on formal educational support organizations to meet their budgetary needs. This trend, however, may be in tension with state funding schemes that attempt to weaken the link between a community's wealth and the quality of its schools. Educational support organizations appear to feature the same socioeconomic stratification that gave rise to the need for state formulas to mitigate differences in local funding based on the wealth of the community. Yet, there is no state legislation that speaks to the equitable results of private funding for public schools. This Note argues that it is an appropriate time for state legislatures to address the interplay between private donations and public school funding, and provides several frameworks by which to balance the competing interests related to the provision of high quality education and fair funding.
长期以来,公立学校一直依靠私人资金来源来补充联邦、州和地方的公共资金。在过去的三十年里,私人资助变得越来越复杂和突出,导致许多学校越来越依赖正式的教育支持组织来满足他们的预算需求。然而,这种趋势可能与试图削弱社区财富与学校质量之间联系的国家资助计划相矛盾。教育支持组织似乎具有相同的社会经济阶层,这导致需要国家公式来缓解基于社区财富的地方资金差异。然而,没有一个州的立法对公立学校的私人资金的公平结果作出说明。本文认为,现在是州立法机构解决私人捐赠和公立学校资助之间相互作用的适当时机,并提供了几个框架,通过这些框架来平衡与提供高质量教育和公平资助相关的竞争利益。
{"title":"The Class is Greener on the Other Side: How Private Donations to Public Schools Play into Fair Funding","authors":"A. Frisch","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2915479","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2915479","url":null,"abstract":"Public schools have long drawn on private sources of funding to supplement federal, state, and local public funding. In the last thirty years, private funding has grown in sophistication and prominence, leading many schools to increasingly rely on formal educational support organizations to meet their budgetary needs. This trend, however, may be in tension with state funding schemes that attempt to weaken the link between a community's wealth and the quality of its schools. Educational support organizations appear to feature the same socioeconomic stratification that gave rise to the need for state formulas to mitigate differences in local funding based on the wealth of the community. Yet, there is no state legislation that speaks to the equitable results of private funding for public schools. This Note argues that it is an appropriate time for state legislatures to address the interplay between private donations and public school funding, and provides several frameworks by which to balance the competing interests related to the provision of high quality education and fair funding.","PeriodicalId":47625,"journal":{"name":"Duke Law Journal","volume":"67 1","pages":"427-478"},"PeriodicalIF":1.9,"publicationDate":"2017-01-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.2915479","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46022362","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
期刊
Duke Law Journal
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1