首页 > 最新文献

Linguistic Inquiry最新文献

英文 中文
Names, Light Nouns, and Countability 名称、轻名词和可计数性
IF 1.6 1区 文学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-12-22 DOI: 10.1162/ling_a_00437
Friederike Moltmann
Making use of Kayne’s (2005, 2010) theory of light nouns, this article argues that light nouns are part of (simple) names and that a mass/count distinction among light nouns explains the behavior of certain types of names in German as mass rather than count. The article elaborates the role of light nouns with new generalizations regarding their linguistic behavior in quantificational and pronominal NPs, their selection of relative pronouns in German, and a general difference in the support of plural anaphora between English and German.
本文利用Kayne(20052010)的轻名词理论,认为轻名词是(简单)名称的一部分,轻名词之间的质/数区分将德语中某些类型名称的行为解释为质而非数。本文阐述了轻名词在数量名词和代词名词中的作用,以及轻名词在德语中相对代词的选择,以及英语和德语在支持复数回指方面的普遍差异。
{"title":"Names, Light Nouns, and Countability","authors":"Friederike Moltmann","doi":"10.1162/ling_a_00437","DOIUrl":"10.1162/ling_a_00437","url":null,"abstract":"Making use of Kayne’s (2005, 2010) theory of light nouns, this article argues that light nouns are part of (simple) names and that a mass/count distinction among light nouns explains the behavior of certain types of names in German as mass rather than count. The article elaborates the role of light nouns with new generalizations regarding their linguistic behavior in quantificational and pronominal NPs, their selection of relative pronouns in German, and a general difference in the support of plural anaphora between English and German.","PeriodicalId":48044,"journal":{"name":"Linguistic Inquiry","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.6,"publicationDate":"2022-12-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49311562","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Extended Phase Boundaries and the Spell-Out Trap 扩展相位边界与拼写陷阱
IF 1.6 1区 文学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-12-22 DOI: 10.1162/ling_a_00483
Ken Safir
Grano and Lasnik (2008) argue that phases should be extended if features are still unvalued on the complement of a phase head at the end of what would normally be a phase. Thus, if pronouns are bound variables with unvalued features, then the phase that matters for resolving the unvalued features is extended. However, the one case that their generalization should not cover, namely, local anaphora, suggests that phase extension based on unvalued features is not the right explanation of the bound pronoun effect, and that phases for anaphora are not coordinated with phases that restrict the relations that the bound pronoun effect encompasses.
Grano和Lasnik(2008)认为,如果特征在通常阶段结束时阶段头的补码上仍然不取值,则阶段应该扩展。因此,如果代词是具有不值特征的有界变量,那么对解决不值特征重要的阶段是扩展的。然而,他们的概括不应该涵盖的一个例子,即局部回指,表明基于不值特征的阶段扩展并不是对束缚代词效应的正确解释,回指的阶段与限制束缚代词效应所包含关系的阶段不协调。
{"title":"Extended Phase Boundaries and the Spell-Out Trap","authors":"Ken Safir","doi":"10.1162/ling_a_00483","DOIUrl":"10.1162/ling_a_00483","url":null,"abstract":"Grano and Lasnik (2008) argue that phases should be extended if features are still unvalued on the complement of a phase head at the end of what would normally be a phase. Thus, if pronouns are bound variables with unvalued features, then the phase that matters for resolving the unvalued features is extended. However, the one case that their generalization should not cover, namely, local anaphora, suggests that phase extension based on unvalued features is not the right explanation of the bound pronoun effect, and that phases for anaphora are not coordinated with phases that restrict the relations that the bound pronoun effect encompasses.","PeriodicalId":48044,"journal":{"name":"Linguistic Inquiry","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.6,"publicationDate":"2022-12-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41409498","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Cyclic Expansion in Agree: Maximal Projections as Probes 同意中的循环展开:作为探针的极大投影
IF 1.6 1区 文学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-12-22 DOI: 10.1162/ling_a_00432
Emily Clem
When we couple the cyclic expansion of a probe’s domain assumed in Cyclic Agree (Rezac 2003, 2004, Béjar and Rezac 2009) with the lack of formal distinction between heads, intermediate projections, and phrases emphasized in Bare Phrase Structure (Chomsky 1995a,b), an interesting prediction arises. Maximal projections should be able to probe through the same mechanisms that allow intermediate projections to probe in familiar cases of Cyclic Agree. I argue that this prediction is borne out. I analyze agreeing adjunct C in Amahuaca (Panoan; Peru) as a maximal projection that probes its c-command domain in second-cycle Agree. This account derives C’s simultaneous sensitivity to DPs within its own clause and in the clause to which it adjoins. Therefore, I conclude that Amahuaca provides evidence that maximal projections can be probes. The account also yields insight into the syntax of switch-reference in Panoan and beyond.
当我们将循环同意(Rezac 2003, 2004, bzajar和Rezac 2009)中假设的探针域的循环扩展与Bare Phrase Structure (Chomsky 1995a,b)中强调的头部、中间预测和短语之间缺乏正式区分结合起来时,一个有趣的预测出现了。最大投影应该能够通过允许中间投影在熟悉的循环一致情况下探测的相同机制进行探测。我认为这个预言是被证实的。我分析了阿玛瓦卡语(帕诺瓦语;(秘鲁)作为在第二循环中探测其c命令域的最大投影。这一解释推导出C在其自己的条款和它所毗邻的条款中对dp的同时敏感性。因此,我得出结论,Amahuaca提供了最大投影可以探针的证据。这篇文章还深入了解了Panoan及其他语言中switch-reference的语法。
{"title":"Cyclic Expansion in Agree: Maximal Projections as Probes","authors":"Emily Clem","doi":"10.1162/ling_a_00432","DOIUrl":"10.1162/ling_a_00432","url":null,"abstract":"When we couple the cyclic expansion of a probe’s domain assumed in Cyclic Agree (Rezac 2003, 2004, Béjar and Rezac 2009) with the lack of formal distinction between heads, intermediate projections, and phrases emphasized in Bare Phrase Structure (Chomsky 1995a,b), an interesting prediction arises. Maximal projections should be able to probe through the same mechanisms that allow intermediate projections to probe in familiar cases of Cyclic Agree. I argue that this prediction is borne out. I analyze agreeing adjunct C in Amahuaca (Panoan; Peru) as a maximal projection that probes its c-command domain in second-cycle Agree. This account derives C’s simultaneous sensitivity to DPs within its own clause and in the clause to which it adjoins. Therefore, I conclude that Amahuaca provides evidence that maximal projections can be probes. The account also yields insight into the syntax of switch-reference in Panoan and beyond.","PeriodicalId":48044,"journal":{"name":"Linguistic Inquiry","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.6,"publicationDate":"2022-12-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41308528","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 18
Locality and Antilocality: The Logic of Conflicting Requirements 局部性与反局部性:需求冲突的逻辑
IF 1.6 1区 文学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-12-22 DOI: 10.1162/ling_a_00436
Kenyon Branan
This article discusses what happens when locality requirements—which favor short dependencies—come into conflict with antilocality requirements—which rule out dependencies that are too short. It is argued that in such circumstances, certain locality requirements may be minimally violated so that the antilocality requirement is satisfied. A theory along these lines is shown to derive a pervasive pattern of noniterative symmetry in A-movement—found in Haya and Luganda (Bantu), Tongan (Austronesian), and Japanese—in which the highest two arguments in a domain may undergo A-movement, but A-movement of lower arguments is systematically banned. The article concludes with some discussion of how interactions of this sort might be modeled in the grammar.
本文讨论了当局部性需求(支持短依赖关系)与反局部性需求冲突时会发生什么,反局部性要求排除了太短的依赖关系。有人认为,在这种情况下,某些局部性要求可能会被最低限度地违反,从而满足反局部性要求。沿着这些路线的一种理论被证明在A运动中推导出了一种普遍的非重复对称模式——在哈雅和卢甘达(班图语)、汤加语(南岛语)和日语中都有发现——在这种模式中,一个领域中最高的两个论点可能会经历A运动,但较低论点的A运动被系统地禁止。文章最后讨论了如何在语法中建模这类交互。
{"title":"Locality and Antilocality: The Logic of Conflicting Requirements","authors":"Kenyon Branan","doi":"10.1162/ling_a_00436","DOIUrl":"10.1162/ling_a_00436","url":null,"abstract":"This article discusses what happens when locality requirements—which favor short dependencies—come into conflict with antilocality requirements—which rule out dependencies that are too short. It is argued that in such circumstances, certain locality requirements may be minimally violated so that the antilocality requirement is satisfied. A theory along these lines is shown to derive a pervasive pattern of noniterative symmetry in A-movement—found in Haya and Luganda (Bantu), Tongan (Austronesian), and Japanese—in which the highest two arguments in a domain may undergo A-movement, but A-movement of lower arguments is systematically banned. The article concludes with some discussion of how interactions of this sort might be modeled in the grammar.","PeriodicalId":48044,"journal":{"name":"Linguistic Inquiry","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.6,"publicationDate":"2022-12-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42211533","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Suppletion in a Three-Way Number System: Evidence from Creek 三向数字系统的补充:来自克里克的证据
IF 1.6 1区 文学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-12-22 DOI: 10.1162/ling_a_00429
Kimberly Johnson
Suppletion is central to the debate on the nature of roots: whether roots are characterized by their phonology or are phonologically abstract. Borer (2014) holds that so-called suppletive verbs consist of different phonologically constant roots with overlapping semantics. Harley (2014), however, argues that suppletive verbs instantiate root suppletion: one abstract root with distinct phonological realizations dependent on grammatical environment. This squib presents additional evidence from verbal suppletion in Creek (Muskogean) that supports the view that roots are abstract. Creek suppletive verbs are part of a larger three-way number-marking paradigm and their distribution is dependent on the formal number features of their first argument.
补语是关于词根本质的争论的核心:词根是由其音系特征还是音系抽象。Borer(2014)认为所谓的补语动词是由不同音系不变的词根组成的,这些词根在语义上是重叠的。然而,Harley(2014)认为,补语动词实例化了词根补充:一个抽象词根,根据语法环境具有不同的语音实现。这个哑巴提供了来自克里克语(马斯科根语)补充语的额外证据,支持根是抽象的观点。希腊补语动词是一个更大的三向数字标记范式的一部分,它们的分布取决于它们的第一个参数的形式数字特征。
{"title":"Suppletion in a Three-Way Number System: Evidence from Creek","authors":"Kimberly Johnson","doi":"10.1162/ling_a_00429","DOIUrl":"10.1162/ling_a_00429","url":null,"abstract":"Suppletion is central to the debate on the nature of roots: whether roots are characterized by their phonology or are phonologically abstract. Borer (2014) holds that so-called suppletive verbs consist of different phonologically constant roots with overlapping semantics. Harley (2014), however, argues that suppletive verbs instantiate root suppletion: one abstract root with distinct phonological realizations dependent on grammatical environment. This squib presents additional evidence from verbal suppletion in Creek (Muskogean) that supports the view that roots are abstract. Creek suppletive verbs are part of a larger three-way number-marking paradigm and their distribution is dependent on the formal number features of their first argument.","PeriodicalId":48044,"journal":{"name":"Linguistic Inquiry","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.6,"publicationDate":"2022-12-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42285398","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 11
Why Plain Futurates are Different 为什么普通期货不同
IF 1.6 1区 文学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-12-22 DOI: 10.1162/ling_a_00435
Hotze Rullmann;Marianne Huijsmans;Lisa Matthewson;Neda Todorović
In English, simple present (plain) and present progressive constructions can make reference to the future, in constructions known as futurates. In previous literature, these two types of futurate have often been discussed separately or treated as more or less equivalent. This squib argues that they convey different meanings: plain futurates presuppose the existence of a schedule, while progressive futurates do not. We propose a formal definition of a schedule and present novel empirical data based on a questionnaire study. We show that plain futurates are restricted to contexts providing a schedule, but progressive futurates are not.
在英语中,简单现在(普通)和现在进行结构可以指未来,在被称为futures的结构中。在以前的文献中,这两种类型的未来主义经常被单独讨论,或者被视为或多或少的等价物。这个哑炮认为它们传达了不同的含义:简单的未来主义预设了时间表的存在,而进步的未来主义则没有。我们提出了时间表的正式定义,并在问卷调查的基础上提供了新的经验数据。我们表明,朴素的未来主义仅限于提供时间表的上下文,而进步的未来论则不然。
{"title":"Why Plain Futurates are Different","authors":"Hotze Rullmann;Marianne Huijsmans;Lisa Matthewson;Neda Todorović","doi":"10.1162/ling_a_00435","DOIUrl":"10.1162/ling_a_00435","url":null,"abstract":"In English, simple present (plain) and present progressive constructions can make reference to the future, in constructions known as futurates. In previous literature, these two types of futurate have often been discussed separately or treated as more or less equivalent. This squib argues that they convey different meanings: plain futurates presuppose the existence of a schedule, while progressive futurates do not. We propose a formal definition of a schedule and present novel empirical data based on a questionnaire study. We show that plain futurates are restricted to contexts providing a schedule, but progressive futurates are not.","PeriodicalId":48044,"journal":{"name":"Linguistic Inquiry","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.6,"publicationDate":"2022-12-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49252418","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Feature Geometry and Head Splitting in the Wolof Clausal Periphery Wolof Clausal外围的特征几何与头分裂
IF 1.6 1区 文学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-12-22 DOI: 10.1162/ling_a_00447
Martina Martinović
This article is a study of the morphosyntax of the clausal periphery in Wolof, specifically the two layers commonly labeled CP and IP. It has long been noted that (a) C and I share a number of properties, and (b) languages differ in the amount of structure over which functional features are distributed. I propose a structure-building mechanism that can both explain the C-I relationship and derive the variation in the distribution of features over syntactic heads. I argue that features of C and I are bundled together and that this feature bundle can be divided into multiple heads via Head Splitting, which allows parts of feature bundles to reproject. The proposal is illustrated through a detailed exploration of the C-I domain in Wolof, which bundles C and I into one head in some structures and splits them in others.
本文对Wolof小句末梢的形态语法进行了研究,特别是通常标记为CP和IP的两层。人们早就注意到(a) C和I有许多共同的属性,(b)语言在分布功能特性的结构数量上有所不同。我提出了一种结构构建机制,既可以解释C-I关系,又可以推导出语法头部特征分布的变化。我认为C和我的特性是捆绑在一起的,这个特性包可以通过Head Splitting分成多个Head,这允许部分特性包重新投影。通过对Wolof中C-I结构域的详细探索,该建议得到了说明,它将C和I捆绑在一些结构中的一个头部中,并将它们在其他结构中分开。
{"title":"Feature Geometry and Head Splitting in the Wolof Clausal Periphery","authors":"Martina Martinović","doi":"10.1162/ling_a_00447","DOIUrl":"10.1162/ling_a_00447","url":null,"abstract":"This article is a study of the morphosyntax of the clausal periphery in Wolof, specifically the two layers commonly labeled CP and IP. It has long been noted that (a) C and I share a number of properties, and (b) languages differ in the amount of structure over which functional features are distributed. I propose a structure-building mechanism that can both explain the C-I relationship and derive the variation in the distribution of features over syntactic heads. I argue that features of C and I are bundled together and that this feature bundle can be divided into multiple heads via Head Splitting, which allows parts of feature bundles to reproject. The proposal is illustrated through a detailed exploration of the C-I domain in Wolof, which bundles C and I into one head in some structures and splits them in others.","PeriodicalId":48044,"journal":{"name":"Linguistic Inquiry","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.6,"publicationDate":"2022-12-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43660451","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
Reconciling “Heavy” and “Long”: The Typology of Lexical Geminates 调和“重”与“长”:词汇宝石的类型学
IF 1.6 1区 文学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-12-21 DOI: 10.1162/ling_a_00499
N. Topintzi, Eva Zimmermann
After decades of research, opinions are still split as to whether geminates should be represented as long or as heavy. In this paper, we attempt to resolve this issue by entertaining a model that rests on the assumption that all underlying geminates are moraic consonants but they might not emerge as such on the surface. We argue that this intuition—due to Davis (2011)—can be formalized in a theoretical model where 1) different degrees of prosodic integration are possible and 2) phonetic interpretation can refer to the difference between epenthetic and underlying elements. This model predicts that the questions of whether a mora has an effect for segmental length and whether it has an effect for syllabic weight are independent from each other. We show that this representational consequence correctly predicts the typology of attested combinations of geminates in different positions and singleton coda consonants in the languages of the world.
经过几十年的研究,对于双生染色体是否应该长或重的观点仍然存在分歧。在本文中,我们试图通过一个模型来解决这个问题,该模型基于所有潜在的双生音都是韵律辅音的假设,但它们可能不会在表面上出现。我们认为这种直觉——由于Davis(2011)——可以在一个理论模型中形式化,其中1)不同程度的韵律整合是可能的,2)语音解释可以参考外在元素和潜在元素之间的差异。该模型预测,动词是否对音段长度有影响,是否对音节重有影响,这两个问题是相互独立的。我们证明,这一表征结果正确地预测了世界语言中不同位置的双生组合和单尾辅音的类型学。
{"title":"Reconciling “Heavy” and “Long”: The Typology of Lexical Geminates","authors":"N. Topintzi, Eva Zimmermann","doi":"10.1162/ling_a_00499","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1162/ling_a_00499","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 After decades of research, opinions are still split as to whether geminates should be represented as long or as heavy. In this paper, we attempt to resolve this issue by entertaining a model that rests on the assumption that all underlying geminates are moraic consonants but they might not emerge as such on the surface. We argue that this intuition—due to Davis (2011)—can be formalized in a theoretical model where 1) different degrees of prosodic integration are possible and 2) phonetic interpretation can refer to the difference between epenthetic and underlying elements. This model predicts that the questions of whether a mora has an effect for segmental length and whether it has an effect for syllabic weight are independent from each other. We show that this representational consequence correctly predicts the typology of attested combinations of geminates in different positions and singleton coda consonants in the languages of the world.","PeriodicalId":48044,"journal":{"name":"Linguistic Inquiry","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.6,"publicationDate":"2022-12-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48404793","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Communicative Stability and the Typology of Logical Operators 通信稳定性与逻辑算子的类型学
IF 1.6 1区 文学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-12-21 DOI: 10.1162/ling_a_00497
Moshe E. Bar-Lev, Roni Katzir
The typology of the logical vocabulary in natural language is highly skewed. In the domain of logical connectives, AND and OR are often lexicalized, lexicalizations of NOR are less common and tend to be structurally complex, and no other logical connective is ever lexicalized. Existing accounts fail to fully derive this major crosslinguistic pattern, and moreover resort to otherwise unwarranted assumptions. The goal of this paper is to provide an account which is less stipulative and has wider empirical coverage than previous accounts, based on a novel notion of communicative stability. Using a model of a rational speaker we observe that attested languages are stable languages, i.e., languages in which the optimal message for a speaker to choose when they want to convey a particular state they are in is not affected by which states they take to be more likely and which ones less. We argue that Stability can account both for why AND and OR are the only simple connectives lexicalized and for why NOR is the only complex connective lexicalized.
自然语言中逻辑词汇的类型学是高度倾斜的。在逻辑连接词领域,AND和OR经常被词汇化,NOR的词汇化不太常见,而且往往结构复杂,其他逻辑连接词从未被词汇化。现有的研究并没有完全推导出这种主要的跨语言模式,而且还采用了一些毫无根据的假设。本文的目标是基于一种新的交流稳定性概念,提供一种比以前的账户更少的规定和更广泛的经验覆盖的账户。使用一个理性说话者的模型,我们观察到被证明的语言是稳定的语言,也就是说,当说话者想要传达他们所处的特定状态时,他们选择的最佳信息不受他们认为哪种状态更可能出现、哪种状态更不可能出现的影响。我们认为稳定性可以解释为什么AND和OR是唯一被词汇化的简单连接词,为什么NOR是唯一被词汇化的复杂连接词。
{"title":"Communicative Stability and the Typology of Logical Operators","authors":"Moshe E. Bar-Lev, Roni Katzir","doi":"10.1162/ling_a_00497","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1162/ling_a_00497","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 The typology of the logical vocabulary in natural language is highly skewed. In the domain of logical connectives, AND and OR are often lexicalized, lexicalizations of NOR are less common and tend to be structurally complex, and no other logical connective is ever lexicalized. Existing accounts fail to fully derive this major crosslinguistic pattern, and moreover resort to otherwise unwarranted assumptions. The goal of this paper is to provide an account which is less stipulative and has wider empirical coverage than previous accounts, based on a novel notion of communicative stability. Using a model of a rational speaker we observe that attested languages are stable languages, i.e., languages in which the optimal message for a speaker to choose when they want to convey a particular state they are in is not affected by which states they take to be more likely and which ones less. We argue that Stability can account both for why AND and OR are the only simple connectives lexicalized and for why NOR is the only complex connective lexicalized.","PeriodicalId":48044,"journal":{"name":"Linguistic Inquiry","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.6,"publicationDate":"2022-12-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42238668","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Binding and Anti-Cataphora in Mayan 玛雅语中的束缚与反Cataphora
IF 1.6 1区 文学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2022-12-21 DOI: 10.1162/ling_a_00498
Justin Royer
This paper examines a puzzle pertaining to the distribution of covalued nominal expressions in two understudied Mayan languages, Chuj and Ch’ol. While Ch’ol behaves entirely as expected with regards to the binding conditions, Chuj appears to consistently tolerate violations of Condition C, often privileging linear precedence as the determining factor in the distribution of R-expressions and pronouns. The Chuj data therefore initially seem to cast doubt on a long tradition to treat the binding conditions as universal (e.g., Grodzinsky and Reinhart 1993, Reuland 2010, 2011). I argue that the difference between Chuj and Ch’ol can be largely explained if, contrary to Ch’ol, Chuj exhibits ‘high-absolutive’ syntax, independently proposed to account for a number of morphosyntactic phenomena in a subset of Mayan languages (Coon et al. 2014; Coon et al. 2021). High-absolutive syntax creates configurations in which the internal argument asymmetrically c-commands the external argument, bleeding otherwise expected binding relations from the external argument into the internal argument. The violations of Condition C in Chuj are thus only apparent. I further argue (i) that linear precedence effects in Chuj are a reflex of a more general anti-cataphora constraint on free nominals, which can also be shown to apply to Ch’ol, and (ii) that there are corners of Chuj where the binding conditions do apply, and that in such cases linear precedence is irrelevant for the distribution of covalued nominals. This means that the binding conditions are active in Chuj, even though idiosyncratic syntactic properties of the language often render their application impossible. The general lesson is that despite initial evidence to doubt the universality of the binding conditions, a universalist approach not only can be maintained, but is supported by the Chuj data.
本文研究了两种研究不足的玛雅语言Chuj和Ch'ol中共值名词表达式的分布问题。虽然Ch'ol在约束条件方面的表现完全符合预期,但Chuj似乎一贯容忍违反条件C的行为,经常将线性优先权作为R-表达和代词分布的决定因素。因此,Chuj数据最初似乎对将约束条件视为普遍条件的长期传统表示怀疑(例如,Grodzinsky和Reinhart 1993,Reuland 20102011)。我认为,如果与Ch'ol相反,Chuj表现出“高度绝对性”语法,独立提出解释玛雅语言子集中的许多形态句法现象,那么Chuj和Ch'ol之间的差异可以在很大程度上得到解释(Coon等人,2014;Coon等人2021)。高度绝对语法创建了内部自变量不对称地c命令外部自变量的配置,将原本期望的绑定关系从外部自变量渗透到内部自变量中。因此,Chuj违反条件C的行为是显而易见的。我进一步认为(I)Chuj中的线性优先效应是自由名词上更普遍的反cataphora约束的反射,这也可以证明适用于Ch’ol,以及(ii)Chuj的某些角落确实适用约束条件,在这种情况下,线性优先与共值名词的分布无关。这意味着绑定条件在Chuj中是活跃的,尽管语言的特殊句法特性往往使其无法应用。一般的教训是,尽管有初步证据怀疑约束条件的普遍性,但普遍主义方法不仅可以维持,而且得到了Chuj数据的支持。
{"title":"Binding and Anti-Cataphora in Mayan","authors":"Justin Royer","doi":"10.1162/ling_a_00498","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1162/ling_a_00498","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 This paper examines a puzzle pertaining to the distribution of covalued nominal expressions in two understudied Mayan languages, Chuj and Ch’ol. While Ch’ol behaves entirely as expected with regards to the binding conditions, Chuj appears to consistently tolerate violations of Condition C, often privileging linear precedence as the determining factor in the distribution of R-expressions and pronouns. The Chuj data therefore initially seem to cast doubt on a long tradition to treat the binding conditions as universal (e.g., Grodzinsky and Reinhart 1993, Reuland 2010, 2011). I argue that the difference between Chuj and Ch’ol can be largely explained if, contrary to Ch’ol, Chuj exhibits ‘high-absolutive’ syntax, independently proposed to account for a number of morphosyntactic phenomena in a subset of Mayan languages (Coon et al. 2014; Coon et al. 2021). High-absolutive syntax creates configurations in which the internal argument asymmetrically c-commands the external argument, bleeding otherwise expected binding relations from the external argument into the internal argument. The violations of Condition C in Chuj are thus only apparent. I further argue (i) that linear precedence effects in Chuj are a reflex of a more general anti-cataphora constraint on free nominals, which can also be shown to apply to Ch’ol, and (ii) that there are corners of Chuj where the binding conditions do apply, and that in such cases linear precedence is irrelevant for the distribution of covalued nominals. This means that the binding conditions are active in Chuj, even though idiosyncratic syntactic properties of the language often render their application impossible. The general lesson is that despite initial evidence to doubt the universality of the binding conditions, a universalist approach not only can be maintained, but is supported by the Chuj data.","PeriodicalId":48044,"journal":{"name":"Linguistic Inquiry","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.6,"publicationDate":"2022-12-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49587237","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
期刊
Linguistic Inquiry
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1