首页 > 最新文献

Harvard Law Review最新文献

英文 中文
The Cost of Accidents 事故的代价
IF 3.4 2区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2017-12-06 DOI: 10.12987/9780300157970
G. Calabresi
Medicine and Ethics. Problems encountered as science makes genetic control of man a real possibility. Includes discussions of asexual reproduction of men, frozen semen banks, breeding human beings for special purposes.
{"title":"The Cost of Accidents","authors":"G. Calabresi","doi":"10.12987/9780300157970","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.12987/9780300157970","url":null,"abstract":"Medicine and Ethics. Problems encountered as science makes genetic control of man a real possibility. Includes discussions of asexual reproduction of men, frozen semen banks, breeding human beings for special purposes.","PeriodicalId":48320,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":3.4,"publicationDate":"2017-12-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"66375670","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 491
Tort Law--Expert Testimony in Asbestos Litigation--District of South Carolina Holds the Every Exposure Theory Insufficient to Demonstrate Specific Causation Even If Legal Conclusions are Scientifically Sound.--Haskins v. 3m Co., Nos. 2:15-cv-02086, 3:15-cv-02123, 2017 WL 3118017 (D.S.C. July 21, 2017). 侵权法——石棉诉讼中的专家证言——南卡罗莱纳地区法院认为,即使法律结论在科学上是合理的,每次暴露理论也不足以证明具体的因果关系。——Haskins诉3m Co., no . 2:15-cv-02086, 3:15-cv-02123, 2017 WL 3118017 (dsc, 2017年7月21日)。
IF 3.4 2区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2017-12-01
{"title":"Tort Law--Expert Testimony in Asbestos Litigation--District of South Carolina Holds the Every Exposure Theory Insufficient to Demonstrate Specific Causation Even If Legal Conclusions are Scientifically Sound.--Haskins v. 3m Co., Nos. 2:15-cv-02086, 3:15-cv-02123, 2017 WL 3118017 (D.S.C. July 21, 2017).","authors":"","doi":"","DOIUrl":"","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":48320,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":3.4,"publicationDate":"2017-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"35656076","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Without the Pretense of Legislative Intent 没有立法意图的伪装
IF 3.4 2区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2017-10-27 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.3347325
J. Manning
{"title":"Without the Pretense of Legislative Intent","authors":"J. Manning","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.3347325","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.3347325","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":48320,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":3.4,"publicationDate":"2017-10-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44073129","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 6
Unprecedented? Judicial Confirmation Battles and the Search for a Usable Past 前所未有的司法确认之争与寻找可利用的过去
IF 3.4 2区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2017-07-21 DOI: 10.31228/osf.io/7wnqe
Josh Chafetz
"Unprecedented" is a dirty word--at least in the context of constitutional politics. The claim that some behavior is unprecedented carries with it a distinct whiff of impermissibility: if it's never been done before, then at the very least the burden is on those who would want to do it to show that it is permissible. (1) A thumb is very firmly placed on the scale against constitutional novelty. The claim that some activity is constitutionally novel is therefore a politically potent one. Of course, to call one act a "precedent" for another is not to state a fact about the relationship between them but rather to engage in a creative act of interpretation. Precedential relationships are made, not found, (2) and therefore charges of unprecedentedness represent a political judgment--but one that comes in the guise of a discovery of a fact about the world. In recent years, perhaps nowhere has unprecedented behavior been "discovered" with more abandon than in the context of judicial appointments. Part I of this Essay describes recent events in this domain, beginning in the George W. Bush Administration and culminating with the 2017 elimination of the filibuster for all nominees. In particular, it focuses on the discourse surrounding these reforms, noting that at every turn, accusations of "unprecedented" behavior have flown in all directions and have served as justifications for countermeasures, which are in turn characterized as unprecedented. Part II then reconstructs two pasts--two precedential pathways--for recent * rofessor of Law, Cornell Law School. I am grateful to Will Baude, Mike Dorf, Joey Fishkin, Randy Kozel, Marin Levy, David Pozen, Aziz Rana, Catherine Roach, and Justin Zaremby for helpful and thought-provoking comments on earlier drafts. The research and writing of this Essay were funded in part by a gift from the Charles Adelman Fund at Cornell Law School. I gratefully acknowledge the generosity of Charles Adelman and the support his gift provides to legal scholarship. Any remaining errors or infelicities are, of course, my own. events, one drawing on the history of legislative obstruction and the other on the history of confirmation politics. The purpose of these historical narratives is not to adjudicate particular claims of unprecedentedness but rather to highlight the ways in which any claim of (un)precedentedness involves particular, contestable constructions of the past. The Essay concludes with some thoughts about why we might prefer some avail-able pasts to others. I. The Present By the middle of 2004, Republicans were furious. Three years into George W. Bush's presidency, they were having at best very limited success in stocking the federal courts, and especially the circuit courts, with their preferred personnel. Democrats had held the Senate majority for most of the 107th Congress (2001-2003), (3) and they had used their power to good effect, confirming only 52% of Bush's (4) nominees to the courts of appeals. (5) But Republi
“史无前例”是一个肮脏的词——至少在宪政的背景下是这样。声称某些行为是前所未有的,带有明显的不被允许的意味:如果以前从未有人做过,那么至少那些想要做这件事的人有责任证明它是被允许的。(1)在反对宪法新颖性的天平上,大拇指是非常牢固的。因此,声称某些活动在宪法上是新颖的,在政治上是强有力的。当然,将一个行为称为另一个行为的“先例”并不是陈述它们之间关系的事实,而是参与一种创造性的解释行为。先例关系是建立的,而不是发现的,因此,对史无前例的指责代表了一种政治判断——但它是以发现世界事实的名义出现的。近年来,在司法任命的背景下,可能没有什么地方比任何地方更能“发现”前所未有的行为了。本文的第一部分描述了这一领域最近发生的事件,从乔治·w·布什政府开始,到2017年取消对所有提名者的阻挠议事。报告特别关注围绕这些改革的讨论,指出在每一个转折点,对“前所未有”行为的指责都向四面八方飞来,并成为反制措施的理由,而反制措施又被描述为前所未有。第二部分为康奈尔大学法学院(Cornell Law School)最近的法学教授重建了两个过去——两个先例路径。我很感谢Will Baude, Mike Dorf, Joey Fishkin, Randy Kozel, Marin Levy, David Pozen, Aziz Rana, Catherine Roach和Justin Zaremby对早期草稿的有益和发人深省的评论。本文的研究和写作部分由康奈尔大学法学院查尔斯·阿德尔曼基金的捐赠资助。我非常感谢查尔斯·阿德尔曼的慷慨和他的捐赠对法律学术的支持。当然,任何剩下的错误或缺点都是我自己的。事件,一个借鉴立法阻挠的历史,另一个借鉴确认政治的历史。这些历史叙述的目的并不是对史无前例的特定主张进行评判,而是强调任何(非)史无前例的主张都涉及对过去的特定的、有争议的建构。这篇文章总结了一些关于为什么我们可能更喜欢一些可用的过去而不是其他人的想法。到2004年中期,共和党人怒不可遏。在乔治·w·布什(George W. Bush)担任总统三年后,他们在为联邦法院,尤其是巡回法院配备他们喜欢的人员方面,最多只取得了非常有限的成功。民主党在第107届国会(2001-2003)的大部分时间里都占据着参议院的多数席位,他们很好地利用了自己的权力,布什提名的上诉法院大法官中只有52%得到了确认。但是,共和党人在2002年中期选举中重新夺回了参议院,并显然期望任命的步伐加快。成为司法委员会主席的奥林·哈奇宣布,他将减少对家乡参议员的传统尊重,甚至对两个家乡参议员都反对的提名人举行听证会和投票。(6)在那届国会中,有7名上诉法院提名人没有得到两个州参议员的批准,其中5人被选出了委员会。(7)司法委员会的资深民主党人帕特里克·莱希(Patrick Leahy)庄严地表示,这一举动将“在参议院和我们委员会的史册上永远被铭记,因为它开创了先例(不顾两个州参议员的反对,就一名被提名人举行听证会),因为它背后的傲慢和它所设定的无耻的双重标准”(8)多数党领袖比尔·弗里斯特(Bill Frist)不为所动;当被提名者上台时,他拒绝尊重他们的等待要求。...
{"title":"Unprecedented? Judicial Confirmation Battles and the Search for a Usable Past","authors":"Josh Chafetz","doi":"10.31228/osf.io/7wnqe","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.31228/osf.io/7wnqe","url":null,"abstract":"\"Unprecedented\" is a dirty word--at least in the context of constitutional politics. The claim that some behavior is unprecedented carries with it a distinct whiff of impermissibility: if it's never been done before, then at the very least the burden is on those who would want to do it to show that it is permissible. (1) A thumb is very firmly placed on the scale against constitutional novelty. The claim that some activity is constitutionally novel is therefore a politically potent one. Of course, to call one act a \"precedent\" for another is not to state a fact about the relationship between them but rather to engage in a creative act of interpretation. Precedential relationships are made, not found, (2) and therefore charges of unprecedentedness represent a political judgment--but one that comes in the guise of a discovery of a fact about the world. In recent years, perhaps nowhere has unprecedented behavior been \"discovered\" with more abandon than in the context of judicial appointments. Part I of this Essay describes recent events in this domain, beginning in the George W. Bush Administration and culminating with the 2017 elimination of the filibuster for all nominees. In particular, it focuses on the discourse surrounding these reforms, noting that at every turn, accusations of \"unprecedented\" behavior have flown in all directions and have served as justifications for countermeasures, which are in turn characterized as unprecedented. Part II then reconstructs two pasts--two precedential pathways--for recent * rofessor of Law, Cornell Law School. I am grateful to Will Baude, Mike Dorf, Joey Fishkin, Randy Kozel, Marin Levy, David Pozen, Aziz Rana, Catherine Roach, and Justin Zaremby for helpful and thought-provoking comments on earlier drafts. The research and writing of this Essay were funded in part by a gift from the Charles Adelman Fund at Cornell Law School. I gratefully acknowledge the generosity of Charles Adelman and the support his gift provides to legal scholarship. Any remaining errors or infelicities are, of course, my own. events, one drawing on the history of legislative obstruction and the other on the history of confirmation politics. The purpose of these historical narratives is not to adjudicate particular claims of unprecedentedness but rather to highlight the ways in which any claim of (un)precedentedness involves particular, contestable constructions of the past. The Essay concludes with some thoughts about why we might prefer some avail-able pasts to others. I. The Present By the middle of 2004, Republicans were furious. Three years into George W. Bush's presidency, they were having at best very limited success in stocking the federal courts, and especially the circuit courts, with their preferred personnel. Democrats had held the Senate majority for most of the 107th Congress (2001-2003), (3) and they had used their power to good effect, confirming only 52% of Bush's (4) nominees to the courts of appeals. (5) But Republi","PeriodicalId":48320,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":3.4,"publicationDate":"2017-07-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44349288","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
The Debate That Never Was 从未有过的辩论
IF 3.4 2区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2017-05-22 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2972256
N. Stavropoulos
In September 1994, Professor Ronald Dworkin presented a new paper at the NYU Colloquium in Legal, Political, and Social Philosophy. Earlier that year, the second edition of Professor H.L.A. Hart's The Concept of Law had appeared, which now included as a postscript an edited version of an unfinished manuscript that Hart had left at his death. (1) Hart's Postscript (as it came to be known) was Hart's response to Dworkin's work. In part, the Postscript addressed Dworkin's arguments from the late 1960s and early 1970s that had directly discussed Hart's claims in the book. (2) But it also addressed Dworkin's own theory of law, developed in the 1970s and early 1980s and, most fully and systematically, in Law's Empire, which appeared in 1986. (3) The paper that Dworkin presented at the Colloquium, entitled Hart's Posthumous Reply, (4) was a rebuttal of Hart's claims in the Postscript. This was an exciting development: Dworkin's manuscript circulated rapidly and widely, in spite of the fact that, back then, dissemination of manuscripts relied on photocopier and postal service, or even fax. I. DWORKIN AND HIS CRITICS To understand why this was exciting requires some background. The publication in 1967 of Dworkin's The Model of Rules had set off a fierce debate between Dworkin and a large number of critics. Dworkin's target in that paper was legal positivism, which he defined as a family of theories that purport to explain obligation in law by appeal to the existence of a set of special standards that meet a social test of pedigree: for example, that they have been endorsed by some institution. (5) Dworkin contended that such theories cannot adequately account for the role that certain unenacted moral principles play in grounding legal rights and obligations. (6) This failure, he argued, led the theories to conflate the use of moral judgment in judicial reasoning (a core judicial duty, given the role of principles) with judicial creation of new legal rights and duties to which litigants are retroactively held (which would be a gross violation of that duty). (7) In part, Dworkin framed the discussion as an attack on Hart's theory, which he considered the strongest version of positivism then available. (8) Dworkin's critics from that period sought to defend positivism. They, too, often focused on Hart, framing their arguments as a defence of Hart's (or a Hartian) theory, either by developing responses that they claimed to be available to Hart or by suggesting modifications to Hart's theory that they claimed to be capable of preserving the general positivist outlook that Hart championed and of making the modified theory immune to Dworkin's criticism. (9) Because of its framing, the relevant scholarship came to be known as the "Hart-Dworkin debate," though of course it was in fact a debate between Dworkin and his numerous critics, since Hart did not reply to Dworkin at that time. Following the early pair of articles that sparked the debate, Dworkin embarked on
1994年9月,罗纳德·德沃金教授在纽约大学法律、政治和社会哲学学术讨论会上发表了一篇新论文。同年早些时候,H.L.A.Hart教授的《法律的概念》第二版出版了,其中包括哈特去世时留下的一份未完成手稿的编辑版本作为后记。(1) 哈特的后记是哈特对德沃金作品的回应。在某种程度上,后记阐述了德沃金在20世纪60年代末和70年代初的论点,这些论点直接讨论了哈特在书中的主张。(2) 但它也谈到了德沃金自己的法律理论,该理论发展于20世纪70年代和80年代初,最全面、系统地出现在1986年出现的《法律帝国》中。(3) 德沃金在学术讨论会上发表的题为《哈特的事后答辩》的论文(4)是对哈特在后记中的主张的反驳。这是一个令人兴奋的发展:德沃金的手稿迅速而广泛地传播,尽管当时手稿的传播依赖于复印机和邮政服务,甚至传真。I.德沃金和他的批评要理解为什么这件事令人兴奋,需要一些背景知识。1967年,德沃金的《规则的模型》出版,引发了德沃金与众多评论家之间的激烈争论。德沃金在那篇论文中的目标是法律实证主义,他将其定义为一系列理论,旨在通过呼吁存在一套符合谱系社会测试的特殊标准来解释法律义务:例如,这些标准得到了一些机构的认可。(5) 德沃金认为,这些理论不能充分解释某些未被执行的道德原则在奠定法律权利和义务方面所起的作用。(6) 他认为,这一失败导致理论将在司法推理中使用道德判断(考虑到原则的作用,这是一项核心的司法义务)与司法创造新的法律权利和义务混为一谈,诉讼当事人对这些权利和义务具有追溯力(这将严重违反这一义务)。(7) 在某种程度上,德沃金将这场讨论视为对哈特理论的攻击,他认为哈特理论是当时最有力的实证主义版本。(8) 德沃金在那个时期的批评者试图为实证主义辩护。他们也经常关注哈特,将他们的论点框定为哈特(或哈特派)理论的辩护,要么发展他们声称对哈特可用的回应,要么建议对哈特的理论进行修改,他们声称能够保留哈特所倡导的一般实证主义观,并使修改后的理论免受德沃金的批评。(9) 由于其框架,相关学术被称为“哈特-德沃金辩论”,尽管事实上这是德沃金和他的众多批评者之间的辩论,因为哈特当时没有回复德沃金。在最初引发争论的两篇文章之后,德沃金开始发展一种新颖的法律概念,即后来被称为解释主义。德沃金的新作品吸引了人们的极大兴趣,每一本新出版物都会受到一系列新的评论和批评。然而,辩论的基调现在发生了变化。德沃金的新作品很少提及哈特,它引发的反应也是如此。(11) 相反,讨论现在被德沃金独特的主题所主导:解释的理念和以此为基础的法律概念,原则一致性的价值,德沃金的各种新颖的分析手段,包括识别法律权利和义务的解释前和解释后阶段,一个成功的解释必须满足的测试的适合性和正当性的维度,他的模范法官赫拉克勒斯和法律的确定性,等等。(12)批评者试图用通常的哲学工具直接破坏新理论:提出关于概念最初的合理性、解释力、内部一致性的问题,或其含义的成立性…
{"title":"The Debate That Never Was","authors":"N. Stavropoulos","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2972256","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2972256","url":null,"abstract":"In September 1994, Professor Ronald Dworkin presented a new paper at the NYU Colloquium in Legal, Political, and Social Philosophy. Earlier that year, the second edition of Professor H.L.A. Hart's The Concept of Law had appeared, which now included as a postscript an edited version of an unfinished manuscript that Hart had left at his death. (1) Hart's Postscript (as it came to be known) was Hart's response to Dworkin's work. In part, the Postscript addressed Dworkin's arguments from the late 1960s and early 1970s that had directly discussed Hart's claims in the book. (2) But it also addressed Dworkin's own theory of law, developed in the 1970s and early 1980s and, most fully and systematically, in Law's Empire, which appeared in 1986. (3) The paper that Dworkin presented at the Colloquium, entitled Hart's Posthumous Reply, (4) was a rebuttal of Hart's claims in the Postscript. This was an exciting development: Dworkin's manuscript circulated rapidly and widely, in spite of the fact that, back then, dissemination of manuscripts relied on photocopier and postal service, or even fax. I. DWORKIN AND HIS CRITICS To understand why this was exciting requires some background. The publication in 1967 of Dworkin's The Model of Rules had set off a fierce debate between Dworkin and a large number of critics. Dworkin's target in that paper was legal positivism, which he defined as a family of theories that purport to explain obligation in law by appeal to the existence of a set of special standards that meet a social test of pedigree: for example, that they have been endorsed by some institution. (5) Dworkin contended that such theories cannot adequately account for the role that certain unenacted moral principles play in grounding legal rights and obligations. (6) This failure, he argued, led the theories to conflate the use of moral judgment in judicial reasoning (a core judicial duty, given the role of principles) with judicial creation of new legal rights and duties to which litigants are retroactively held (which would be a gross violation of that duty). (7) In part, Dworkin framed the discussion as an attack on Hart's theory, which he considered the strongest version of positivism then available. (8) Dworkin's critics from that period sought to defend positivism. They, too, often focused on Hart, framing their arguments as a defence of Hart's (or a Hartian) theory, either by developing responses that they claimed to be available to Hart or by suggesting modifications to Hart's theory that they claimed to be capable of preserving the general positivist outlook that Hart championed and of making the modified theory immune to Dworkin's criticism. (9) Because of its framing, the relevant scholarship came to be known as the \"Hart-Dworkin debate,\" though of course it was in fact a debate between Dworkin and his numerous critics, since Hart did not reply to Dworkin at that time. Following the early pair of articles that sparked the debate, Dworkin embarked on","PeriodicalId":48320,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":3.4,"publicationDate":"2017-05-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.2972256","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41633276","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
Antitrust Law--Hospital Mergers--Third Circuit Clarifies Geographic Market Definition and Raises Bar for Efficiencies Defense. 反垄断法-医院合并-第三巡回法院澄清地域市场定义并提高效率辩护的门槛。
IF 3.4 2区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2017-04-01
{"title":"Antitrust Law--Hospital Mergers--Third Circuit Clarifies Geographic Market Definition and Raises Bar for Efficiencies Defense.","authors":"","doi":"","DOIUrl":"","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":48320,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":3.4,"publicationDate":"2017-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"34929234","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Preemption — ERISA Preemption — Sixth Circuit Holds That ERISA Does Not Preempt Michigan Medicaid Tax Law. 优先权- ERISA优先权-第六巡回法院认为ERISA不优先于密歇根医疗补助税法。
IF 3.4 2区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2017-03-01
{"title":"Preemption — ERISA Preemption — Sixth Circuit Holds That ERISA Does Not Preempt Michigan Medicaid Tax Law.","authors":"","doi":"","DOIUrl":"","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":48320,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":3.4,"publicationDate":"2017-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"34884464","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Bureaucracy and Distrust: Landis, Jaffe and Kagan on the Administrative State 官僚主义与不信任:兰迪斯、贾菲和卡根论行政国家
IF 3.4 2区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2016-11-02 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2863112
Adrian Vermeule
What, if anything, legitimates the administrative state? In this Essay, for the Harvard Law Review’s special issue celebrating the bicentennial of Harvard Law School, I examine three attempts to solve the administrative state’s legitimation problem, offered respectively by James Landis, by Louis Jaffe, and by Elena Kagan. The solutions have a common theme and a common structure: each appeals more or less explicitly to “independence.” Each attempts to find a remedy for distrust of unchecked administrative power, and each attempts to do so by identifying “independent” institutions that will monitor and oversee the bureaucracy. However, each compromises their claims in institutional circumstances where the force of competing values becomes particularly strong. The result is that each theorist ends up adopting a kind of roughly optimizing pluralism of values for the administrative state, a pluralism in which “independence” falls out of the picture as such, and in which the benefits of expertise, political accountability, and legalism all have some claims. Happily, this pluralist, rough, and imperfectly-optimizing approach seems adequate to legitimate the administrative state, at least in the sociological sense of legitimation as public acceptance.
如果有的话,是什么使行政国家合法化?在这篇为《哈佛法律评论》庆祝哈佛法学院200周年特刊撰写的文章中,我考察了詹姆斯·兰迪斯、路易斯·贾菲和埃琳娜·卡根分别提出的解决行政国家合法性问题的三种尝试。这些解决方案有一个共同的主题和一个共同的结构:每个都或多或少地明确地呼吁“独立性”。两者都试图找到一种补救方法,以消除对不受制约的行政权力的不信任,并且都试图通过确定“独立”的机构来监督和监督官僚机构。然而,在价值观竞争的力量变得特别强大的制度环境中,每一方都妥协了自己的主张。其结果是,每一位理论家最终都采用了一种大致优化的行政国家价值多元化,在这种多元化中,“独立”从图景中消失,专业知识、政治问责制和法律主义的好处都有一些主张。令人高兴的是,这种多元的、粗糙的、不完美的优化方法似乎足以使行政国家合法化,至少在作为公众接受的合法性的社会学意义上是这样。
{"title":"Bureaucracy and Distrust: Landis, Jaffe and Kagan on the Administrative State","authors":"Adrian Vermeule","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2863112","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2863112","url":null,"abstract":"What, if anything, legitimates the administrative state? In this Essay, for the Harvard Law Review’s special issue celebrating the bicentennial of Harvard Law School, I examine three attempts to solve the administrative state’s legitimation problem, offered respectively by James Landis, by Louis Jaffe, and by Elena Kagan. The solutions have a common theme and a common structure: each appeals more or less explicitly to “independence.” Each attempts to find a remedy for distrust of unchecked administrative power, and each attempts to do so by identifying “independent” institutions that will monitor and oversee the bureaucracy. However, each compromises their claims in institutional circumstances where the force of competing values becomes particularly strong. The result is that each theorist ends up adopting a kind of roughly optimizing pluralism of values for the administrative state, a pluralism in which “independence” falls out of the picture as such, and in which the benefits of expertise, political accountability, and legalism all have some claims. Happily, this pluralist, rough, and imperfectly-optimizing approach seems adequate to legitimate the administrative state, at least in the sociological sense of legitimation as public acceptance.","PeriodicalId":48320,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":3.4,"publicationDate":"2016-11-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68398935","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
How Private Insurers Regulate Public Police 私营保险公司如何监管公共警察
IF 3.4 2区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2016-02-15 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2733783
John Rappaport
A string of deadly police-citizen encounters, made public on an unprecedented scale, has thrust American policing into the crucible of political conflict. New social movements have taken to the streets, while legislators have introduced a wide array of reform proposals. Optimism is elusive, though, as the police are notoriously difficult to change. One powerful policy lever, however, has been overlooked: police liability insurance. Based on primary sources new to legal literature and interviews with nearly thirty insurance industry representatives, civil rights litigators, municipal attorneys, and consultants, this Article shows how liability insurers are capable of effecting meaningful change within the agencies they insure — a majority of police agencies nationwide. The Article is the first to describe and assess the contemporary market for liability insurance in the policing context; in particular, the effects of insurance on police behavior. While not ignoring the familiar (and potentially serious) problem of moral hazard, the Article focuses on the ways in which insurers perform a traditionally governmental “regulatory” role as they work to manage risk. Insurers get police agencies to adopt or amend written departmental policies on subjects like the use of force and strip searches, to change the way they train their officers, and even to fire problem officers, from the beat up to the chief. One implication of these findings is that the state might regulate the police by regulating insurers. In this spirit, the Article considers several unconventional legal reforms that could reduce police misconduct, including a mandate that all municipalities purchase insurance coverage, a ban on “first-dollar” (no-deductible) policies that may reduce municipal care, and a requirement that small municipalities pool their risks and resources before buying insurance on the commercial market. At bottom, the Article establishes that liability insurance has profound significance to any comprehensive program of police reform. The Article also makes three important theoretical contributions to legal scholarship. First, it inverts the ordinary model of governance as public regulation of private action, observing that here, private insurers regulate public police. Second, it illustrates how insurers not only enforce the Constitution, but also construct its meaning. Among other things, in the hands of insurers, liability for constitutional violations and other police misconduct becomes “loss” to the police agency, which must be “controlled.” Perhaps surprisingly, by denaturing the law in this way and stripping it of its moral valence, insurers may actually advance the law’s aims. Finally, the Article helps to pry open the black box of deterrence. In fact, given widespread indemnification of both individual and entity liability for constitutional torts committed by police, an understanding of how insurers manage police risk is essential to any persuasive theory of civ
一系列警察与公民之间的致命冲突,以前所未有的规模被公开,将美国警察推入了政治冲突的熔炉。新的社会运动已经走上街头,而立法者则提出了一系列广泛的改革建议。然而乐观是难以捉摸的,因为警察是出了名的难以改变。然而,一个强有力的政策杠杆却被忽视了:警察责任保险。本文基于法律文献的第一手资料和对近30位保险业代表、民权诉讼律师、市政律师和顾问的采访,展示了责任保险公司如何能够在其承保的机构(全国大多数警察机构)内实现有意义的变革。本文首次对警务背景下的当代责任保险市场进行了描述和评估;特别是保险对警察行为的影响。虽然没有忽视熟悉的(潜在严重的)道德风险问题,但文章重点关注保险公司在管理风险时扮演传统政府“监管”角色的方式。保险公司要求警察机构采纳或修改有关使用武力和脱衣搜查等问题的书面部门政策,改变他们培训警官的方式,甚至解雇问题警官,从殴打到局长。这些发现的一个暗示是,国家可能通过监管保险公司来监管警察。本着这一精神,本文考虑了几项可以减少警察不当行为的非常规法律改革,包括要求所有市政当局购买保险,禁止可能减少市政保健的“第一美元”(无免赔额)政策,以及要求小市政当局在商业市场上购买保险之前集中风险和资源。文章最后指出,责任保险对于任何一项综合性的公安改革方案都具有深远的意义。本文还对法学研究做出了三个重要的理论贡献。首先,它将普通的治理模式颠倒为公共对私人行为的监管,观察到在这里,私人保险公司监管公共警察。其次,它说明了保险公司不仅如何执行宪法,而且如何构建宪法的含义。除此之外,在保险公司手中,违反宪法和其他警察不当行为的责任成为警察机构的“损失”,必须“控制”。也许令人惊讶的是,通过以这种方式改变法律并剥离其道德价值,保险公司实际上可能会推进法律的目标。最后,本文有助于撬开威慑的黑盒子。事实上,鉴于对警察犯下的宪法侵权行为的个人和实体责任的广泛赔偿,了解保险公司如何管理警察风险对于任何有说服力的警察不当行为民事威慑理论都是至关重要的。
{"title":"How Private Insurers Regulate Public Police","authors":"John Rappaport","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2733783","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2733783","url":null,"abstract":"A string of deadly police-citizen encounters, made public on an unprecedented scale, has thrust American policing into the crucible of political conflict. New social movements have taken to the streets, while legislators have introduced a wide array of reform proposals. Optimism is elusive, though, as the police are notoriously difficult to change. One powerful policy lever, however, has been overlooked: police liability insurance. Based on primary sources new to legal literature and interviews with nearly thirty insurance industry representatives, civil rights litigators, municipal attorneys, and consultants, this Article shows how liability insurers are capable of effecting meaningful change within the agencies they insure — a majority of police agencies nationwide. The Article is the first to describe and assess the contemporary market for liability insurance in the policing context; in particular, the effects of insurance on police behavior. While not ignoring the familiar (and potentially serious) problem of moral hazard, the Article focuses on the ways in which insurers perform a traditionally governmental “regulatory” role as they work to manage risk. Insurers get police agencies to adopt or amend written departmental policies on subjects like the use of force and strip searches, to change the way they train their officers, and even to fire problem officers, from the beat up to the chief. One implication of these findings is that the state might regulate the police by regulating insurers. In this spirit, the Article considers several unconventional legal reforms that could reduce police misconduct, including a mandate that all municipalities purchase insurance coverage, a ban on “first-dollar” (no-deductible) policies that may reduce municipal care, and a requirement that small municipalities pool their risks and resources before buying insurance on the commercial market. At bottom, the Article establishes that liability insurance has profound significance to any comprehensive program of police reform. The Article also makes three important theoretical contributions to legal scholarship. First, it inverts the ordinary model of governance as public regulation of private action, observing that here, private insurers regulate public police. Second, it illustrates how insurers not only enforce the Constitution, but also construct its meaning. Among other things, in the hands of insurers, liability for constitutional violations and other police misconduct becomes “loss” to the police agency, which must be “controlled.” Perhaps surprisingly, by denaturing the law in this way and stripping it of its moral valence, insurers may actually advance the law’s aims. Finally, the Article helps to pry open the black box of deterrence. In fact, given widespread indemnification of both individual and entity liability for constitutional torts committed by police, an understanding of how insurers manage police risk is essential to any persuasive theory of civ","PeriodicalId":48320,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":3.4,"publicationDate":"2016-02-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.2733783","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68279607","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 28
How Much Does Speech Matter 语言有多重要
IF 3.4 2区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2016-01-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2724040
Leslie Kendrick
In Speech Matters (Princeton 2014), Seana Shiffrin explains why lying is wrong, why freedom of speech is right, and why those two views are compatible. This review lauds Shiffrin’s book for its creative and powerful coherence of vision. It lays its claims about both lying and free speech on the same foundation: on a view of sincere communication as a prerequisite for moral agency and moral progress. In this regard, Shiffrin’s book stands in sharp rebuke to the current trend, in the Supreme Court and elsewhere, of assuming that the freedom of speech must include a right to lie. Instead, Shiffrin argues, the reasons that we have freedom of speech are the same reasons that lying is rarely morally permissible. At the same time, the coherence of Shiffrin’s view also reveals a certain symmetry between Kantian accounts of lying and predominant views of free speech, one that not everyone will find salutary. In both, the importance of communication seems to override other interests, even other moral commitments. While Shiffrin articulates a compelling view of why free and authentic communication serves a distinct, indeed a singular, role in moral identity, the question remains whether that role requires quite so much protection, either against lying or in favor of free speech. Nevertheless, Shiffrin’s book puts forth an original and authoritative view on these questions, one that will challenge and instruct anyone interested in lying, free speech, or the communicative responsibilities we owe to ourselves and others.
在Speech Matters (Princeton, 2014)一书中,Seana Shiffrin解释了为什么说谎是错误的,为什么言论自由是正确的,以及为什么这两种观点是相容的。这篇评论称赞了Shiffrin的书的创造性和强大的连贯性。它将谎言和言论自由的主张建立在同一个基础上:真诚的交流是道德能动性和道德进步的先决条件。在这方面,Shiffrin的书对目前最高法院和其他地方认为言论自由必须包括撒谎权利的趋势提出了尖锐的指责。相反,Shiffrin认为,我们拥有言论自由的原因与说谎在道德上很少被允许的原因是一样的。与此同时,Shiffrin观点的一致性也揭示了康德对谎言的描述与对言论自由的主流观点之间的某种对称性,这种对称性并不是每个人都觉得有益。在这两种情况下,沟通的重要性似乎都超过了其他利益,甚至其他道德承诺。虽然Shiffrin阐述了一个令人信服的观点,即为什么自由和真实的交流在道德认同中发挥着独特的作用,实际上是一种独特的作用,但问题仍然是,这种作用是否需要如此多的保护,无论是反对谎言还是支持言论自由。尽管如此,Shiffrin的书对这些问题提出了一个原创和权威的观点,它将挑战和指导任何对说谎、言论自由或我们对自己和他人的沟通责任感兴趣的人。
{"title":"How Much Does Speech Matter","authors":"Leslie Kendrick","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2724040","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2724040","url":null,"abstract":"In Speech Matters (Princeton 2014), Seana Shiffrin explains why lying is wrong, why freedom of speech is right, and why those two views are compatible. This review lauds Shiffrin’s book for its creative and powerful coherence of vision. It lays its claims about both lying and free speech on the same foundation: on a view of sincere communication as a prerequisite for moral agency and moral progress. In this regard, Shiffrin’s book stands in sharp rebuke to the current trend, in the Supreme Court and elsewhere, of assuming that the freedom of speech must include a right to lie. Instead, Shiffrin argues, the reasons that we have freedom of speech are the same reasons that lying is rarely morally permissible. At the same time, the coherence of Shiffrin’s view also reveals a certain symmetry between Kantian accounts of lying and predominant views of free speech, one that not everyone will find salutary. In both, the importance of communication seems to override other interests, even other moral commitments. While Shiffrin articulates a compelling view of why free and authentic communication serves a distinct, indeed a singular, role in moral identity, the question remains whether that role requires quite so much protection, either against lying or in favor of free speech. Nevertheless, Shiffrin’s book puts forth an original and authoritative view on these questions, one that will challenge and instruct anyone interested in lying, free speech, or the communicative responsibilities we owe to ourselves and others.","PeriodicalId":48320,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":3.4,"publicationDate":"2016-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68274641","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Harvard Law Review
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1