首页 > 最新文献

Harvard Law Review最新文献

英文 中文
Adjudication Outside Article III 第三条之外的裁决
IF 3.4 2区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2020-03-10 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.3194945
William Baude
Article III requires federal courts that exercise federal jurisdiction to be given life tenure and undiminished compensation, limiting Congress’s ability to influence the judiciary. But from the beginning, we have accepted certain forms of adjudication outside Article III – state courts, most obviously, but also territorial courts, administrative adjudication of public rights, and military tribunals. The question is why. This Article attempts to provide an answer. It argues that it is a mistake to focus on the act of adjudication itself; adversary presentation about the application of law to fact is simply a procedure, and not a procedure uniquely limited to Article III courts. Instead, the constitutional question is one of government power. What kind of power has the tribunal been vested with, and what it is trying to do with that power? With this framework in view, the structure and scope of non-Article-III adjudication becomes clearer. Some courts exercise the judicial power of some other government. This is why territorial courts and state courts are constitutional. Some bodies exercise executive power, subject to the constraints reflected by the Due Process Clause. This is why administrative adjudication of public rights and military trials are constitutional. Some exercise no governmental power, and can proceed only as an adjunct to another entity, or on the basis of consent. This is the only basis on which magistrate judges and bankruptcy judges can proceed and may render some of their current behavior unconstitutional.
第三条要求行使联邦管辖权的联邦法院终身任职,赔偿不减,限制了国会影响司法机构的能力。但从一开始,我们就接受了第三条之外的某些形式的裁决——最明显的是州法院,但也接受了地区法院、公共权利行政裁决和军事法庭。问题是为什么。本文试图提供一个答案。它认为,把注意力集中在裁决行为本身是错误的;关于法律适用于事实的对抗性陈述只是一种程序,而不是仅限于第三条法院的程序。相反,宪法问题是政府权力问题。法庭被赋予了什么样的权力,它试图用这种权力做什么?有了这一框架,非第三条裁决的结构和范围变得更加明确。一些法院行使其他政府的司法权。这就是为什么领土法院和州法院是符合宪法的。一些机构行使行政权力,但受正当程序条款所反映的限制。这就是为什么对公共权利的行政裁决和军事审判符合宪法的原因。有些人不行使政府权力,只能作为另一个实体的附属机构或在征得同意的基础上进行。这是地方法官和破产法官可以进行诉讼的唯一依据,可能会使他们目前的一些行为违宪。
{"title":"Adjudication Outside Article III","authors":"William Baude","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.3194945","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.3194945","url":null,"abstract":"Article III requires federal courts that exercise federal jurisdiction to be given life tenure and undiminished compensation, limiting Congress’s ability to influence the judiciary. But from the beginning, we have accepted certain forms of adjudication outside Article III – state courts, most obviously, but also territorial courts, administrative adjudication of public rights, and military tribunals. The question is why. \u0000 \u0000This Article attempts to provide an answer. It argues that it is a mistake to focus on the act of adjudication itself; adversary presentation about the application of law to fact is simply a procedure, and not a procedure uniquely limited to Article III courts. Instead, the constitutional question is one of government power. What kind of power has the tribunal been vested with, and what it is trying to do with that power? \u0000 \u0000With this framework in view, the structure and scope of non-Article-III adjudication becomes clearer. Some courts exercise the judicial power of some other government. This is why territorial courts and state courts are constitutional. Some bodies exercise executive power, subject to the constraints reflected by the Due Process Clause. This is why administrative adjudication of public rights and military trials are constitutional. Some exercise no governmental power, and can proceed only as an adjunct to another entity, or on the basis of consent. This is the only basis on which magistrate judges and bankruptcy judges can proceed and may render some of their current behavior unconstitutional.","PeriodicalId":48320,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":3.4,"publicationDate":"2020-03-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46649458","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Freedom 自由
IF 3.4 2区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2019-12-12 DOI: 10.4324/9780429029202
Peter Rohs
{"title":"Freedom","authors":"Peter Rohs","doi":"10.4324/9780429029202","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4324/9780429029202","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":48320,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":3.4,"publicationDate":"2019-12-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"70610785","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 15
Dormant Commerce Clause--Extraterritoriality Doctrine--Fourth Circuit Invalidates Maryland Statute Regulating Price Gouging in the Sale Of Generic Drugs.--Association for Accessible Medicines v. Frosh, 887 F.3d 664 (4th Cir. 2018). 休眠期商业条款——治外法权原则——第四巡回法院裁定马里兰州仿制药销售价格欺诈法规无效。——无障碍药品协会诉Frosh, 887 F.3d 664(2018年第4期)。
IF 3.4 2区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2019-04-01
{"title":"Dormant Commerce Clause--Extraterritoriality Doctrine--Fourth Circuit Invalidates Maryland Statute Regulating Price Gouging in the Sale Of Generic Drugs.--Association for Accessible Medicines v. Frosh, 887 F.3d 664 (4th Cir. 2018).","authors":"","doi":"","DOIUrl":"","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":48320,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":3.4,"publicationDate":"2019-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"37163701","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Faithful Execution and Article II 忠实履行和第二条
IF 3.4 2区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2018-10-04 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.3260593
A. Kent, E. Leib, J. Shugerman
Article II of the U.S. Constitution twice imposes a duty of “faithful execution” on the President, who must “take Care that the Laws be faithfully executed,” and take an oath or affirmation to “faithfully execute the Office of President.” These clauses are cited often, but their background and original meaning have never been fully explored. Courts, the executive branch, and many scholars rely on one or both clauses as support for expansive views of presidential power, for example, to go beyond standing law to defend the nation in emergencies; to withhold documents from Congress or the courts; or to refuse to fully execute statutes on grounds of unconstitutionality or for policy reasons. This Article is the first to explore the textual roots of these clauses from the time of Magna Carta and medieval England, through colonial America, and up to the original meaning in the Philadelphia Convention and ratification debates. We find that the language of “faithful execution” was for centuries before 1787 very commonly associated with the performance of public and private offices—especially those in which the officer had some control over the public fisc. “Faithful execution” language applied not only to senior government officials but also to a vast number of more ministerial officers, too. We contend that it imposed three core requirements on officeholders: (1) diligent, careful, good faith, and impartial execution of law or office; (2) a duty not to misuse an office’s funds and or take unauthorized profits; and (3) a duty not to act ultra vires, beyond the scope of one’s office. These three duties of fidelity look a lot like fiduciary duties in modern private law. This “fiduciary” reading of the original meaning of the Faithful Execution Clauses might have important implications in modern constitutional law. Our history supports readings of Article II of the Constitution, for example, that limit presidents to exercise their power in good faith, for the public interest, and not for reasons of self-dealing, self-protection, or other bad faith, personal reasons. So understood, Article II may thus place some limits on the pardon and removal authority. The history we present also supports readings of Article II that tend to subordinate presidential power to congressional direction, limiting presidential non-enforcement of statutes, and perhaps constraining agencies’ interpretation of statutes to pursue Congress’s objectives. Our conclusions undermine imperial and prerogative claims for the presidency, claims that are sometimes, in our estimation, improperly traced to dimensions of the clauses requiring the President's faithful execution.
美国宪法第二条两次规定总统有“忠实执行”的义务,总统必须“注意法律的忠实执行”,并宣誓或肯定“忠实执行总统职务”。这些条款经常被引用,但其背景和原意从未得到充分探讨。法院、行政部门和许多学者依靠一个或两个条款来支持对总统权力的广泛看法,例如,超越常规法在紧急情况下保卫国家;扣留国会或法院的文件;或以违宪或政策原因为由拒绝全面执行法规。本文首次探讨了这些条款的文本根源,从《大宪章》时代和中世纪的英格兰,到殖民地时期的美国,再到《费城公约》和批准辩论中的原意。我们发现,在1787年之前的几个世纪里,“忠实执行”的语言通常与公共和私人办公室的表现联系在一起,尤其是那些官员对公共财政有一定控制权的办公室。“忠实执行”的措辞不仅适用于高级政府官员,也适用于大量部长级官员。我们认为,它对官员提出了三个核心要求:(1)勤勉、谨慎、诚信和公正地执行法律或职务;(2) 不滥用办公室资金和/或获取未经授权的利润的义务;以及(3)不越权行事的义务。这三项忠实义务看起来很像现代私法中的信托义务。这种对忠实执行条款原意的“信托”解读可能对现代宪法产生重要影响。例如,我们的历史支持对宪法第二条的解读,该条限制总统出于公众利益善意行使权力,而不是出于自我交易、自我保护或其他不诚实的个人原因。因此,第二条可以对赦免和罢免权作出一些限制。我们介绍的历史也支持对第二条的解读,该条倾向于将总统权力置于国会指示之下,限制总统不执行法规,并可能限制各机构对法规的解释,以实现国会的目标。我们的结论破坏了对总统的帝国主义和特权主张,据我们估计,这些主张有时被不恰当地追溯到要求总统忠实执行的条款的各个方面。
{"title":"Faithful Execution and Article II","authors":"A. Kent, E. Leib, J. Shugerman","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.3260593","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.3260593","url":null,"abstract":"Article II of the U.S. Constitution twice imposes a duty of “faithful execution” on the President, who must “take Care that the Laws be faithfully executed,” and take an oath or affirmation to “faithfully execute the Office of President.” These clauses are cited often, but their background and original meaning have never been fully explored. Courts, the executive branch, and many scholars rely on one or both clauses as support for expansive views of presidential power, for example, to go beyond standing law to defend the nation in emergencies; to withhold documents from Congress or the courts; or to refuse to fully execute statutes on grounds of unconstitutionality or for policy reasons. \u0000 \u0000This Article is the first to explore the textual roots of these clauses from the time of Magna Carta and medieval England, through colonial America, and up to the original meaning in the Philadelphia Convention and ratification debates. We find that the language of “faithful execution” was for centuries before 1787 very commonly associated with the performance of public and private offices—especially those in which the officer had some control over the public fisc. “Faithful execution” language applied not only to senior government officials but also to a vast number of more ministerial officers, too. We contend that it imposed three core requirements on officeholders: \u0000 \u0000(1) diligent, careful, good faith, and impartial execution of law or office; \u0000 \u0000(2) a duty not to misuse an office’s funds and or take unauthorized profits; and \u0000 \u0000(3) a duty not to act ultra vires, beyond the scope of one’s office. \u0000 \u0000These three duties of fidelity look a lot like fiduciary duties in modern private law. This “fiduciary” reading of the original meaning of the Faithful Execution Clauses might have important implications in modern constitutional law. Our history supports readings of Article II of the Constitution, for example, that limit presidents to exercise their power in good faith, for the public interest, and not for reasons of self-dealing, self-protection, or other bad faith, personal reasons. So understood, Article II may thus place some limits on the pardon and removal authority. The history we present also supports readings of Article II that tend to subordinate presidential power to congressional direction, limiting presidential non-enforcement of statutes, and perhaps constraining agencies’ interpretation of statutes to pursue Congress’s objectives. Our conclusions undermine imperial and prerogative claims for the presidency, claims that are sometimes, in our estimation, improperly traced to dimensions of the clauses requiring the President's faithful execution.","PeriodicalId":48320,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":3.4,"publicationDate":"2018-10-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43260536","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 5
The "Guarantee" Clause “担保”条款
IF 3.4 2区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2018-03-28 DOI: 10.4135/9781483302799.n170
Ryan C. Williams
Article IV’s command that the “United States shall guarantee to every State in this Union a Republican Form of Government” stands as one of the few remaining lacunae in the judicially enforced Constitution. For well over a century, federal courts have viewed the provision — traditionally known as the Guarantee Clause but now referred to by some as the “Republican Form of Government” Clause — as a paradigmatic example of a nonjusticiable political question. In recent years, however, both the Supreme Court and lower federal courts have signaled a new willingness to reconsider this much-criticized jurisdictional barrier in an appropriate case, leading many to predict that its eventual demise is only a matter of time. The interpretive possibilities inherent in a judicially enforceable Guarantee Clause have tantalized generations of constitutional theorists, leading to a significant body of research attempting to uncover what was meant by the provision’s oblique reference to “a Republican Form of Government.” But this research has almost completely ignored a separate inquiry that is equally critical to understanding the provision’s meaning and significance — namely, what it means for the United States to “guarantee” such republican government to the states. This Article seeks to shed new light on the original meaning of the term “guarantee” in the Guarantee Clause, by looking to an unexpected source — namely, eighteenth century treaty practice. The language of the Guarantee Clause closely parallels language that was frequently used in seventeenth and eighteenth-century treaties. The interpretation of such treaty provisions was informed by well-settled background principles of international law, which attached particular legal significance to the term “guarantee.” As used in eighteenth-century treaties, the term “guarantee” signified a diplomatic commitment whereby one nation pledged its support to the protection of some preexisting right or entitlement possessed by another sovereign. Importantly, however, such provisions were deemed to exist solely for the benefit of the guaranteed sovereign and conferred no separate rights or entitlements on the nation pledging the guarantee. Viewing the Guarantee Clause through the lens of eighteenth-century treaty practice casts significant doubt on claims by modern scholars that the provision should be understood as a repository of judicially enforceable individual rights. Rather, both the text of the provision and contextual evidence regarding its original understanding strongly suggest that the provision more likely reflected a quasi-diplomatic, treaty-like commitment on the part of the federal government to its quasi-sovereign component states. This evidence lends new, and heretofore unappreciated support, to the Supreme Court’s longstanding practice of treating Guarantee Clause claims as beyond the scope of judicial cognizance.
第四条关于“美国应保证本联邦每个州都有共和党政府形式”的命令是司法执行的宪法中为数不多的空白之一。一个多世纪以来,联邦法院一直将该条款视为不可审理政治问题的典型例子。该条款传统上被称为“保证条款”,但现在被一些人称为“共和党政府形式”条款。然而,近年来,最高法院和下级联邦法院都表示愿意在适当的案件中重新考虑这一备受批评的管辖权障碍,这让许多人预测,它的最终消亡只是时间问题。司法强制执行的保证条款所固有的解释可能性吸引了几代宪法理论家,导致大量研究试图揭示该条款间接提及“共和党政府形式”的含义。“但这项研究几乎完全忽略了一项单独的调查,该调查对理解该条款的含义和意义同样至关重要,即美国向各州“保证”这样的共和党政府意味着什么。本条试图通过寻找一个意想不到的来源,即十八世纪的条约惯例,重新阐明担保条款中“担保”一词的原意。担保条款的语言与17世纪和18世纪条约中经常使用的语言非常相似。对这类条约条款的解释是根据既定的国际法背景原则作出的,这些原则对“保证”一词具有特别的法律意义,“保证”一词表示一种外交承诺,即一个国家承诺支持保护另一个主权国家所拥有的某些预先存在的权利或权利。然而,重要的是,这些条款被视为仅为被担保主权国家的利益而存在,并没有赋予承诺担保的国家单独的权利或权利。从18世纪条约实践的角度来看《保证条款》,现代学者认为该条款应被理解为司法上可强制执行的个人权利的储存库,这一说法引起了极大的怀疑。相反,该条款的文本和关于其最初理解的上下文证据都强烈表明,该条款更有可能反映出联邦政府对其准主权组成国的准外交、条约式承诺。这一证据为最高法院长期以来将担保条款索赔视为超出司法审理范围的做法提供了新的、迄今为止未得到认可的支持。
{"title":"The \"Guarantee\" Clause","authors":"Ryan C. Williams","doi":"10.4135/9781483302799.n170","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4135/9781483302799.n170","url":null,"abstract":"Article IV’s command that the “United States shall guarantee to every State in this Union a Republican Form of Government” stands as one of the few remaining lacunae in the judicially enforced Constitution. For well over a century, federal courts have viewed the provision — traditionally known as the Guarantee Clause but now referred to by some as the “Republican Form of Government” Clause — as a paradigmatic example of a nonjusticiable political question. In recent years, however, both the Supreme Court and lower federal courts have signaled a new willingness to reconsider this much-criticized jurisdictional barrier in an appropriate case, leading many to predict that its eventual demise is only a matter of time. The interpretive possibilities inherent in a judicially enforceable Guarantee Clause have tantalized generations of constitutional theorists, leading to a significant body of research attempting to uncover what was meant by the provision’s oblique reference to “a Republican Form of Government.” But this research has almost completely ignored a separate inquiry that is equally critical to understanding the provision’s meaning and significance — namely, what it means for the United States to “guarantee” such republican government to the states. \u0000This Article seeks to shed new light on the original meaning of the term “guarantee” in the Guarantee Clause, by looking to an unexpected source — namely, eighteenth century treaty practice. The language of the Guarantee Clause closely parallels language that was frequently used in seventeenth and eighteenth-century treaties. The interpretation of such treaty provisions was informed by well-settled background principles of international law, which attached particular legal significance to the term “guarantee.” As used in eighteenth-century treaties, the term “guarantee” signified a diplomatic commitment whereby one nation pledged its support to the protection of some preexisting right or entitlement possessed by another sovereign. Importantly, however, such provisions were deemed to exist solely for the benefit of the guaranteed sovereign and conferred no separate rights or entitlements on the nation pledging the guarantee. \u0000Viewing the Guarantee Clause through the lens of eighteenth-century treaty practice casts significant doubt on claims by modern scholars that the provision should be understood as a repository of judicially enforceable individual rights. Rather, both the text of the provision and contextual evidence regarding its original understanding strongly suggest that the provision more likely reflected a quasi-diplomatic, treaty-like commitment on the part of the federal government to its quasi-sovereign component states. This evidence lends new, and heretofore unappreciated support, to the Supreme Court’s longstanding practice of treating Guarantee Clause claims as beyond the scope of judicial cognizance.","PeriodicalId":48320,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":3.4,"publicationDate":"2018-03-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41527964","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Statutory Interpretation on the Bench: A Survey of Forty-Two Judges on the Federal Courts of Appeals 法官席上的法定解释:对联邦上诉法院42名法官的调查
IF 3.4 2区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2018-03-09 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.3138249
Abbe R. Gluck, R. Posner
This Article reports the results of a survey of a diverse group of forty-two federal appellate judges concerning their approaches to statutory interpretation. The study reveals important differences between their approaches and the approach that the Supreme Court purports to take. It also helps to substantiate the irrelevance of the enduring, but now-boring, textualism-versus-purposivism debate. None of the judges we interviewed was willing to associate himself or herself with “textualism” without qualification. All consult legislative history. Most eschew dictionaries. All utilize at least some canons of construction, but for reasons that range from “window dressing,” to the use of canons to assist in opinion writing, to a view that they are useful decision tools. Most of the judges we interviewed are not fans of Chevron, except for the judges on the D.C. Circuit, which hears the bulk of Chevron cases. Some of the judges interviewed believe that understanding Congress is important to a judge’s work, while others do not see how judges can use such understanding to decide cases. Most express doubt that the Supreme Court’s interpretive methodology binds the lower courts. The younger judges, who attended law school and practiced during the ascendance of textualism, are generally more formalist and accepting of the canons of construction, regardless of political affiliation. The older judges are less focused on canons, take a broader view of their delegated authority, and appear to grapple more with questions of judicial legitimacy. The approach that emerged most clearly from our interviews might be described as intentional eclecticism. Most of the judges we spoke to are willing to consider many different kinds of argument and evidence, and defend that approach as the only democratically legitimate one. Yet at the same time many observe a gap between how they actually decide cases and how they write opinions, a gap they attribute to the disconnect between the expectations of the public and the realities of judicial decisionmaking.
本文报告了一项对42名联邦上诉法官的调查结果,调查内容涉及他们对法律解释的态度。这项研究揭示了他们的方法与最高法院声称采取的方法之间的重要差异。它还有助于证实持久的,但现在无聊的,文本主义与目的主义之争的无关性。我们采访的所有法官都不愿意毫无条件地将自己与“文本主义”联系在一起。所有这些都参考了立法历史。大多数人都避开字典。所有人都至少使用了一些结构标准,但出于各种原因,从“粉饰门面”到使用标准来协助撰写意见,再到认为它们是有用的决策工具。我们采访的大多数法官都不是雪佛龙的粉丝,除了华盛顿特区巡回法院的法官,他们审理了雪佛龙的大部分案件。一些接受采访的法官认为,了解国会对法官的工作很重要,而另一些人则不明白法官如何利用这种了解来裁决案件。大多数人对最高法院的解释方法是否对下级法院具有约束力表示怀疑。在文本主义盛行时期就读法学院并从事司法工作的年轻法官,通常更倾向于形式主义,无论政治派别如何,他们都接受建构法则。年长的法官不太关注法律,对他们的授权有更广泛的看法,似乎更多地在司法合法性问题上挣扎。在我们的采访中,最明显的方法可以被描述为有意的折衷主义。我们采访过的大多数法官都愿意考虑各种不同的论点和证据,并将这种方法视为唯一民主合法的方法。然而,与此同时,许多人注意到他们在实际判决案件的方式与撰写意见书的方式之间存在差距,他们将这种差距归因于公众的期望与司法决策的现实之间的脱节。
{"title":"Statutory Interpretation on the Bench: A Survey of Forty-Two Judges on the Federal Courts of Appeals","authors":"Abbe R. Gluck, R. Posner","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.3138249","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.3138249","url":null,"abstract":"This Article reports the results of a survey of a diverse group of forty-two federal appellate judges concerning their approaches to statutory interpretation. The study reveals important differences between their approaches and the approach that the Supreme Court purports to take. It also helps to substantiate the irrelevance of the enduring, but now-boring, textualism-versus-purposivism debate. None of the judges we interviewed was willing to associate himself or herself with “textualism” without qualification. All consult legislative history. Most eschew dictionaries. All utilize at least some canons of construction, but for reasons that range from “window dressing,” to the use of canons to assist in opinion writing, to a view that they are useful decision tools. Most of the judges we interviewed are not fans of Chevron, except for the judges on the D.C. Circuit, which hears the bulk of Chevron cases. Some of the judges interviewed believe that understanding Congress is important to a judge’s work, while others do not see how judges can use such understanding to decide cases. Most express doubt that the Supreme Court’s interpretive methodology binds the lower courts. The younger judges, who attended law school and practiced during the ascendance of textualism, are generally more formalist and accepting of the canons of construction, regardless of political affiliation. The older judges are less focused on canons, take a broader view of their delegated authority, and appear to grapple more with questions of judicial legitimacy. The approach that emerged most clearly from our interviews might be described as intentional eclecticism. Most of the judges we spoke to are willing to consider many different kinds of argument and evidence, and defend that approach as the only democratically legitimate one. Yet at the same time many observe a gap between how they actually decide cases and how they write opinions, a gap they attribute to the disconnect between the expectations of the public and the realities of judicial decisionmaking.","PeriodicalId":48320,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":3.4,"publicationDate":"2018-03-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43678161","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Civil Rights--Eighth Amendment--Third Circuit Holds Parents of Mentally Ill Young Man Held in Solitary Confinement Stated Claims of Cruel and Unusual Punishment.--Palakovic v. Wetzel, 854 F.3d 209 (3d Cir. 2017). 公民权利——第八修正案——第三巡回法院裁定被单独监禁的精神病青年的父母声称受到残酷和不寻常的惩罚。——Palakovic诉Wetzel, 854 F.3d 209 (3d Cir. 2017)。
IF 3.4 2区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2018-03-01
{"title":"Civil Rights--Eighth Amendment--Third Circuit Holds Parents of Mentally Ill Young Man Held in Solitary Confinement Stated Claims of Cruel and Unusual Punishment.--Palakovic v. Wetzel, 854 F.3d 209 (3d Cir. 2017).","authors":"","doi":"","DOIUrl":"","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":48320,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":3.4,"publicationDate":"2018-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"36300598","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Pseudo-Contract and Shared Meaning Analysis 伪契约与共享意义分析
IF 3.4 2区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2018-02-14 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.3124018
R. Kar, M. Radin
Over the last several decades, courts and legal scholars have struggled with whether or when to consider boilerplate text as contract. Recent attempts to draw all boilerplate text into “contract” seek to end that struggle but have shifted contract law away from its traditional focus on enforcing parties’ actual agreements and common understandings. This has required a series of ad hoc “fixes” to contract law reminiscent of the medieval use of “epicycles” to try to square geocentric theories of planetary motion with recalcitrant observations of a nongeocentric universe. This shift has been transforming the meanings of contract law’s central concepts. We view the shift as an undiagnosed paradigm slip, resulting in a generalized theory of “contract” as a mere assumption of risk that allows private obligations to be created unilaterally without reaching the actual agreements required by core contract law principles. Some now call this new sort of obligation “contract.” But it is pseudo-contract, resembling contract without fulfilling its necessary conditions of validity.The recent paradigm slip into pseudo-contract raises a complex blend of linguistic, factual, conceptual, practical, normative, and doctrinal problems. Under the mantle of “contract,” the problems of pseudo-contract have remained largely hidden. In this Article we expose these problems and develop a more nuanced and coherent method of analysis — shared meaning analysis — that courts and other legal analysts can use to determine when any particular piece of boilerplate text does, or does not, contribute an actual term to a contract. Because facts about language have received insufficient attention in discussions of how boilerplate text may (or may not) contribute to contract meaning, we launch our analysis by developing several seminal insights into the dependence of meaning on social cooperation from the language philosopher Paul Grice. Drawing on his insights into language, we develop a contemporary definition of the shared meaning of a contract (or the “common meaning of the parties”) as that meaning that is most consistent with the presupposition that both parties were using language cooperatively to contract. We then offer a simple conceptual test that courts can use to discern this shared meaning, distinguish contractual from noncontractual uses of boilerplate text, and prevent contract from slipping into pseudo-contract. We pay particular attention to diagnosing deceptive or misleading uses of boilerplate text. Using examples ranging widely from clickwrap consumer contracts to high-end boilerplate contracts between sophisticated parties, we show how shared meaning analysis applies generally to many varieties of contract.
在过去的几十年里,法院和法律学者一直在纠结是否或何时将样板文本视为合同。最近试图将所有样板文本纳入“合同”,试图结束这场斗争,但已经将合同法从传统的重点转移到执行各方的实际协议和共同谅解上。这就需要对合同法进行一系列临时的“修正”,让人想起中世纪使用“周转”来试图将行星运动的地心理论与对非地心宇宙的顽固观测相一致。这种转变改变了合同法核心概念的含义。我们认为这种转变是一种未经诊断的范式失误,导致“合同”的广义理论仅仅是一种风险假设,允许在没有达成核心合同法原则所要求的实际协议的情况下单方面设定私人义务。有些人现在把这种新的义务称为“合同”。但它是伪合同,类似于没有满足其必要的有效条件的合同。最近进入伪契约的范式引发了语言、事实、概念、实践、规范和理论问题的复杂混合。在“契约”的外衣下,伪契约的问题在很大程度上一直隐藏着。在这篇文章中,我们揭露了这些问题,并开发了一种更细致、更连贯的分析方法——共有含义分析——法院和其他法律分析师可以用它来确定任何特定的样板文本何时对合同有实际条款的贡献。由于在讨论样板文本如何(或不)有助于契约意义的讨论中,有关语言的事实没有得到足够的关注,我们通过从语言哲学家保罗·格里斯那里对意义对社会合作的依赖性提出了一些开创性的见解来启动我们的分析。根据他对语言的见解,我们对合同的共同含义(或“双方的共同含义”)进行了当代定义,即最符合双方合作使用语言订立合同的前提的含义。然后,我们提供了一个简单的概念测试,法院可以用来辨别这种共同的含义,区分样板文本的合同和非合同使用,并防止合同滑向伪合同。我们特别注意诊断样板文本的欺骗性或误导性使用。通过使用从点击包装消费者合同到复杂各方之间的高端样板合同等广泛的例子,我们展示了共享含义分析如何普遍应用于多种合同。
{"title":"Pseudo-Contract and Shared Meaning Analysis","authors":"R. Kar, M. Radin","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.3124018","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.3124018","url":null,"abstract":"Over the last several decades, courts and legal scholars have struggled with whether or when to consider boilerplate text as contract. Recent attempts to draw all boilerplate text into “contract” seek to end that struggle but have shifted contract law away from its traditional focus on enforcing parties’ actual agreements and common understandings. This has required a series of ad hoc “fixes” to contract law reminiscent of the medieval use of “epicycles” to try to square geocentric theories of planetary motion with recalcitrant observations of a nongeocentric universe. This shift has been transforming the meanings of contract law’s central concepts. We view the shift as an undiagnosed paradigm slip, resulting in a generalized theory of “contract” as a mere assumption of risk that allows private obligations to be created unilaterally without reaching the actual agreements required by core contract law principles. Some now call this new sort of obligation “contract.” But it is pseudo-contract, resembling contract without fulfilling its necessary conditions of validity.The recent paradigm slip into pseudo-contract raises a complex blend of linguistic, factual, conceptual, practical, normative, and doctrinal problems. Under the mantle of “contract,” the problems of pseudo-contract have remained largely hidden. In this Article we expose these problems and develop a more nuanced and coherent method of analysis — shared meaning analysis — that courts and other legal analysts can use to determine when any particular piece of boilerplate text does, or does not, contribute an actual term to a contract. Because facts about language have received insufficient attention in discussions of how boilerplate text may (or may not) contribute to contract meaning, we launch our analysis by developing several seminal insights into the dependence of meaning on social cooperation from the language philosopher Paul Grice. Drawing on his insights into language, we develop a contemporary definition of the shared meaning of a contract (or the “common meaning of the parties”) as that meaning that is most consistent with the presupposition that both parties were using language cooperatively to contract. We then offer a simple conceptual test that courts can use to discern this shared meaning, distinguish contractual from noncontractual uses of boilerplate text, and prevent contract from slipping into pseudo-contract. We pay particular attention to diagnosing deceptive or misleading uses of boilerplate text. Using examples ranging widely from clickwrap consumer contracts to high-end boilerplate contracts between sophisticated parties, we show how shared meaning analysis applies generally to many varieties of contract.","PeriodicalId":48320,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":3.4,"publicationDate":"2018-02-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47453665","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 13
The Endgame of Administrative Law: Governmental Disobedience and the Judicial Contempt Power 行政法的终结:政府的不服从与司法的蔑视
IF 3.4 2区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2018-01-12 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2907797
N. Parrillo
Scholars of administrative law focus overwhelmingly on lawsuits to review federal government action while assuming that, if plaintiffs win such lawsuits, the government will do what the court says. But in fact, the federal government’s compliance with court orders is imperfect and fraught, especially with orders compelling the government to act affirmatively. Such orders can strain a federal agency’s resources, interfere with its other legally-required tasks, and force it to make decisions on little information. An agency hit with such an order will often warn the judge that it badly needs more latitude and more time to comply. Judges relent, cutting slack and extending deadlines. The plaintiff who has “won” the suit finds that victory was merely the start of a tough negotiation that can drag on for years. These compliance negotiations are little understood. Basic questions about them are unexplored, including the most fundamental: What is the endgame? That is, if the judge concludes that the agency has delayed too long and demanded too much, is there anything she can do, at long last, to make the agency comply? What the judge can do, ultimately, is the same thing as for any disobedient litigant: find the agency (and its high officials) in contempt. But do judges actually make such contempt findings? If so, can judges couple those findings with the sanctions of fine and imprisonment that give contempt its potency against private parties? If not, what use is contempt? The literature is silent on these questions, and conventional research methods, confined to appellate case law, are hopeless for addressing it. There are no opinions of the Supreme Court on the subject, and while the courts of appeals have handled the problem many times, they have dealt with it in a manner calculated to avoid setting clear and general precedent. Through an examination of thousands of opinions (especially of district courts), docket sheets, briefs, and other filings, plus archival research and interviews, this Article provides the first general assessment of how federal courts handle the federal government’s disobedience. It makes four conclusions. First, the federal judiciary is willing to issue contempt findings against agencies and officials. Second, while several federal judges believe they can (and have tried to) attach sanctions to these findings, the higher courts have exhibited a virtually complete unwillingness to allow sanctions, at times swooping down at the eleventh hour to rescue an agency from incurring a budget-straining fine or its top official from being thrown in jail. Third, the higher courts, even as they unfailingly thwart sanctions in all but a few minor instances, have bent over backward to avoid making pronouncements that sanctions are categorically unavailable, deliberately keeping the sanctions issue in a state of low salience and at least nominal legal uncertainty. Fourth, even though contempt findings are practically devoid of sanctions, th
行政法学者主要关注审查联邦政府行动的诉讼,同时假设,如果原告赢得此类诉讼,政府将按照法院的指示行事。但事实上,联邦政府对法院命令的遵守是不完美和令人担忧的,尤其是在命令迫使政府采取积极行动的情况下。这样的命令可能会使联邦机构的资源紧张,干扰其其他法律要求的任务,并迫使其在几乎没有信息的情况下做出决定。受到此类命令打击的机构通常会警告法官,它迫切需要更多的自由度和时间来遵守。法官们态度缓和,放松态度,延长最后期限。“赢得”诉讼的原告发现,这场胜利只是一场艰难谈判的开始,这场谈判可能会拖上数年。这些合规谈判鲜为人知。关于它们的基本问题尚未探索,包括最基本的问题:结局是什么?也就是说,如果法官得出结论,认为该机构拖延太久,要求太多,她最终能做些什么让该机构遵守吗?最终,法官能做的和对待任何不听话的诉讼当事人一样:认定该机构(及其高级官员)藐视法庭。但法官真的会做出这样的藐视法庭的裁决吗?如果是这样的话,法官能否将这些调查结果与罚款和监禁的制裁结合起来,使藐视法庭行为对私人当事人具有效力?如果没有,蔑视有什么用?文献对这些问题保持沉默,仅限于上诉判例法的传统研究方法无法解决这个问题。最高法院对这个问题没有意见,尽管上诉法院已经多次处理这个问题,但他们处理这个问题的方式是有意避免开立明确和普遍的先例。通过对数千份意见(尤其是地区法院的意见)、案卷、案情摘要和其他文件的审查,再加上档案研究和采访,本文首次对联邦法院如何处理联邦政府的抗命行为进行了全面评估。它得出了四个结论。首先,联邦司法机构愿意发布针对机构和官员的藐视法庭调查结果。其次,尽管几名联邦法官认为他们可以(并试图)对这些调查结果进行制裁,但高等法院几乎完全不愿意允许制裁,有时会在最后一刻采取行动,挽救一个机构免于遭受预算紧张的罚款或其高级官员免于入狱。第三,尽管高等法院在除少数小案件外的所有案件中都坚决阻挠制裁,但它们还是竭尽全力避免宣布制裁是绝对不可用的,故意使制裁问题处于不突出的状态,至少在名义上具有法律不确定性。第四,尽管藐视法庭的调查结果实际上没有制裁,但它们具有羞辱作用,即使威慑力不完善,也会带来实质性的威慑力。针对各机构的诉讼的效力取决于一种普遍的看法,即联邦官员根本不会违反法院命令,以及一种将任何违规行为认定为越轨行为的相应规范。蔑视调查结果,无论制裁如何,都是将该机构和官员指定为违规者并使其蒙羞,从而将这一规范武器化的一种手段。但是,如果法官做出了太多这样的调查结果,尤其是如果他们实施(不可避免地会引起公众关注)制裁,他们可能会破坏人们对官员总是遵守的看法,从而破坏他们这样做的规范。因此,司法机构有时可能会采取行动,以维护其拥有的实质性但有限的基于规范的权力。
{"title":"The Endgame of Administrative Law: Governmental Disobedience and the Judicial Contempt Power","authors":"N. Parrillo","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2907797","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2907797","url":null,"abstract":"Scholars of administrative law focus overwhelmingly on lawsuits to review federal government action while assuming that, if plaintiffs win such lawsuits, the government will do what the court says. But in fact, the federal government’s compliance with court orders is imperfect and fraught, especially with orders compelling the government to act affirmatively. Such orders can strain a federal agency’s resources, interfere with its other legally-required tasks, and force it to make decisions on little information. An agency hit with such an order will often warn the judge that it badly needs more latitude and more time to comply. Judges relent, cutting slack and extending deadlines. The plaintiff who has “won” the suit finds that victory was merely the start of a tough negotiation that can drag on for years. These compliance negotiations are little understood. Basic questions about them are unexplored, including the most fundamental: What is the endgame? That is, if the judge concludes that the agency has delayed too long and demanded too much, is there anything she can do, at long last, to make the agency comply? What the judge can do, ultimately, is the same thing as for any disobedient litigant: find the agency (and its high officials) in contempt. But do judges actually make such contempt findings? If so, can judges couple those findings with the sanctions of fine and imprisonment that give contempt its potency against private parties? If not, what use is contempt? The literature is silent on these questions, and conventional research methods, confined to appellate case law, are hopeless for addressing it. There are no opinions of the Supreme Court on the subject, and while the courts of appeals have handled the problem many times, they have dealt with it in a manner calculated to avoid setting clear and general precedent. Through an examination of thousands of opinions (especially of district courts), docket sheets, briefs, and other filings, plus archival research and interviews, this Article provides the first general assessment of how federal courts handle the federal government’s disobedience. It makes four conclusions. First, the federal judiciary is willing to issue contempt findings against agencies and officials. Second, while several federal judges believe they can (and have tried to) attach sanctions to these findings, the higher courts have exhibited a virtually complete unwillingness to allow sanctions, at times swooping down at the eleventh hour to rescue an agency from incurring a budget-straining fine or its top official from being thrown in jail. Third, the higher courts, even as they unfailingly thwart sanctions in all but a few minor instances, have bent over backward to avoid making pronouncements that sanctions are categorically unavailable, deliberately keeping the sanctions issue in a state of low salience and at least nominal legal uncertainty. Fourth, even though contempt findings are practically devoid of sanctions, th","PeriodicalId":48320,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":3.4,"publicationDate":"2018-01-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.2907797","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41592021","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 16
Multiple Chancellors: Reforming the National Injunction 多位校长:改革国家禁令
IF 3.4 2区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2017-12-08 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2864175
Samuel L. Bray
In several recent high-profile cases, federal district judges have issued injunctions that apply across the nation, controlling the defendants’ behavior with respect to non-parties. This Article offers a new analysis of the scope of injunctions to restrain the enforcement of a federal statute or regulation. It makes two contributions.First, it shows the causes of the current problem. The national injunction is a recent development in the history of equity, traceable to the second half of the twentieth century. But the forum-shopping and other problems associated with the national injunction depend on something older and more structural: the shift from one chancellor in England to many “chancellors” in the federal courts.Second, this Article proposes a single clear principle for the scope of injunctions against federal defendants. A federal court should give what might be called a “plaintiff-protective injunction,” enjoining the defendant’s conduct only with respect to the plaintiff. No matter how important the question and no matter how important the value of uniformity, a federal court should not award a national injunction. The basis for this principle is traditional equity, in line with the rule that the federal courts must trace their equitable doctrines to that source. To put this principle into practice, several specific reforms are suggested, ones that the Supreme Court could adopt through an exercise of its supervisory jurisdiction.
在最近几起备受关注的案件中,联邦地区法官发布了适用于全国各地的禁令,控制了被告对非当事人的行为。本条对限制联邦法规执行的禁令范围进行了新的分析。它有两个贡献。首先,它显示了当前问题的原因。国家禁令是公平史上的一个最新发展,可以追溯到20世纪下半叶。但与国家禁令相关的论坛购物和其他问题取决于更古老、更结构性的东西:从英格兰的一位财政大臣转变为联邦法院的许多“财政大臣”。第二,本条提出了针对联邦被告的禁令范围的单一明确原则。联邦法院应该发布所谓的“原告保护性禁令”,禁止被告仅针对原告的行为。无论这个问题多么重要,无论统一性的价值多么重要,联邦法院都不应该授予国家禁令。这一原则的基础是传统的公平,符合联邦法院必须追溯其公平原则的规则。为了将这一原则付诸实践,建议进行几项具体改革,最高法院可以通过行使其监督管辖权来采取这些改革。
{"title":"Multiple Chancellors: Reforming the National Injunction","authors":"Samuel L. Bray","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2864175","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2864175","url":null,"abstract":"In several recent high-profile cases, federal district judges have issued injunctions that apply across the nation, controlling the defendants’ behavior with respect to non-parties. This Article offers a new analysis of the scope of injunctions to restrain the enforcement of a federal statute or regulation. It makes two contributions.First, it shows the causes of the current problem. The national injunction is a recent development in the history of equity, traceable to the second half of the twentieth century. But the forum-shopping and other problems associated with the national injunction depend on something older and more structural: the shift from one chancellor in England to many “chancellors” in the federal courts.Second, this Article proposes a single clear principle for the scope of injunctions against federal defendants. A federal court should give what might be called a “plaintiff-protective injunction,” enjoining the defendant’s conduct only with respect to the plaintiff. No matter how important the question and no matter how important the value of uniformity, a federal court should not award a national injunction. The basis for this principle is traditional equity, in line with the rule that the federal courts must trace their equitable doctrines to that source. To put this principle into practice, several specific reforms are suggested, ones that the Supreme Court could adopt through an exercise of its supervisory jurisdiction.","PeriodicalId":48320,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":3.4,"publicationDate":"2017-12-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43707377","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 33
期刊
Harvard Law Review
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1