Pub Date : 2024-02-15DOI: 10.1016/j.apal.2024.103422
Kentaro Sato
By combining tree representation of sets with the method introduced in the previous three papers I–III [39], [35], [37] in the series, we give a new -preserving interpretation of (Kripke–Platek set theory with the foundation schema restricted to , and augmented by θ) in for any sentence θ, where the language of second order arithmetic is considered as a sublanguage of that of set theory via the standard interpretation. Thus the addition of any theorem of does not increase the consistency strength of KPω. Among such theorems are several fixed point principles for positive arithmetical operators and ω-model reflection (the cofinal existence of coded ω-models) for theorems of BI. The reader's familiarity to the previous works I–III in the series might help, but is not necessary.
{"title":"A new model construction by making a detour via intuitionistic theories IV: A closer connection between KPω and BI","authors":"Kentaro Sato","doi":"10.1016/j.apal.2024.103422","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.apal.2024.103422","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>By combining tree representation of sets with the method introduced in the previous three papers I–III <span>[39]</span>, <span>[35]</span>, <span>[37]</span> in the series, we give a new <span><math><msubsup><mrow><mi>Π</mi></mrow><mrow><mn>2</mn></mrow><mrow><mn>1</mn></mrow></msubsup></math></span>-preserving interpretation of <span><math><mrow><mi>KP</mi></mrow><msub><mrow><mi>ω</mi></mrow><mrow><mi>r</mi></mrow></msub><mo>+</mo><mo>(</mo><msub><mrow><mi>Π</mi></mrow><mrow><mi>n</mi><mo>+</mo><mn>2</mn></mrow></msub><mtext>-</mtext><mrow><mi>Found</mi></mrow><mo>)</mo><mo>+</mo><mi>θ</mi></math></span> (Kripke–Platek set theory with the foundation schema restricted to <span><math><msub><mrow><mi>Π</mi></mrow><mrow><mi>n</mi><mo>+</mo><mn>2</mn></mrow></msub></math></span>, and augmented by <em>θ</em>) in <span><math><msubsup><mrow><mi>Σ</mi></mrow><mrow><mn>1</mn></mrow><mrow><mn>1</mn></mrow></msubsup><mtext>-</mtext><msub><mrow><mi>AC</mi></mrow><mrow><mn>0</mn></mrow></msub><mo>+</mo><mo>(</mo><msubsup><mrow><mi>Π</mi></mrow><mrow><mi>n</mi><mo>+</mo><mn>2</mn></mrow><mrow><mn>1</mn></mrow></msubsup><mtext>-</mtext><mrow><mi>TI</mi></mrow><mo>)</mo><mo>+</mo><mi>θ</mi></math></span> for any <span><math><msubsup><mrow><mi>Π</mi></mrow><mrow><mn>2</mn></mrow><mrow><mn>1</mn></mrow></msubsup></math></span> sentence <em>θ</em>, where the language of second order arithmetic is considered as a sublanguage of that of set theory via the standard interpretation. Thus the addition of any <span><math><msubsup><mrow><mi>Π</mi></mrow><mrow><mn>2</mn></mrow><mrow><mn>1</mn></mrow></msubsup></math></span> theorem of <span><math><mrow><mi>BI</mi></mrow><mo>≡</mo><msubsup><mrow><mi>Σ</mi></mrow><mrow><mn>1</mn></mrow><mrow><mn>1</mn></mrow></msubsup><mtext>-</mtext><msub><mrow><mi>AC</mi></mrow><mrow><mn>0</mn></mrow></msub><mo>+</mo><mo>(</mo><msubsup><mrow><mi>Π</mi></mrow><mrow><mo>∞</mo></mrow><mrow><mn>1</mn></mrow></msubsup><mtext>-</mtext><mrow><mi>TI</mi></mrow><mo>)</mo></math></span> does not increase the consistency strength of <strong>KP</strong><em>ω</em>. Among such <span><math><msubsup><mrow><mi>Π</mi></mrow><mrow><mn>2</mn></mrow><mrow><mn>1</mn></mrow></msubsup></math></span> theorems are several fixed point principles for positive arithmetical operators and <em>ω</em>-model reflection (the cofinal existence of coded <em>ω</em>-models) for theorems of <strong>BI</strong>. The reader's familiarity to the previous works I–III in the series might help, but is not necessary.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":50762,"journal":{"name":"Annals of Pure and Applied Logic","volume":"175 7","pages":"Article 103422"},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2024-02-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139811673","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"数学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2024-02-01DOI: 10.1016/j.apal.2024.103412
Aristotelis Panagiotopoulos , Assaf Shani
The algebraic dimension of a Polish permutation group is the size of the largest with the property that the orbit of every under the pointwise stabilizer of is infinite. We study the Bernoulli shift for various Polish permutation groups P and we provide criteria under which the P-shift is generically ergodic relative to the injective part of the Q-shift, when Q has algebraic dimension ≤n. We use this to show that the sequence of pairwise ⁎-reduction-incomparable equivalence relations defined in [18] is a strictly increasing sequence in the Borel reduction hierarchy. We also use our main theorem to exhibit an equivalence relation of pinned cardinal which strongly resembles the equivalence relation of pinned cardinal from [25], but which does not Borel reduce to the latter. It remains open whether they are actually incomparable under Borel reductions.
Our proofs rely on the study of symmetric models whose symmetries come from the group Q. We show that when Q is “locally finite”—e.g. when , where is the Fraïssé limit of a Fraïssé class satisfying the disjoint amalgamation property—the corresponding symmetric model admits a theory of supports which is analogous to that in the basic Cohen model.
{"title":"Strong ergodicity phenomena for Bernoulli shifts of bounded algebraic dimension","authors":"Aristotelis Panagiotopoulos , Assaf Shani","doi":"10.1016/j.apal.2024.103412","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.apal.2024.103412","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>The algebraic dimension of a Polish permutation group <span><math><mi>Q</mi><mo>≤</mo><mrow><mi>Sym</mi></mrow><mo>(</mo><mi>N</mi><mo>)</mo></math></span> is the size of the largest <span><math><mi>A</mi><mo>⊆</mo><mi>N</mi></math></span> with the property that the orbit of every <span><math><mi>a</mi><mo>∈</mo><mi>A</mi></math></span> under the pointwise stabilizer of <span><math><mi>A</mi><mo>∖</mo><mo>{</mo><mi>a</mi><mo>}</mo></math></span> is infinite. We study the Bernoulli shift <span><math><mi>P</mi><mo>↷</mo><msup><mrow><mi>R</mi></mrow><mrow><mi>N</mi></mrow></msup></math></span> for various Polish permutation groups <em>P</em> and we provide criteria under which the <em>P</em>-shift is generically ergodic relative to the injective part of the <em>Q</em>-shift, when <em>Q</em> has algebraic dimension ≤<em>n</em>. We use this to show that the sequence of pairwise ⁎-reduction-incomparable equivalence relations defined in <span>[18]</span> is a strictly increasing sequence in the Borel reduction hierarchy. We also use our main theorem to exhibit an equivalence relation of pinned cardinal <span><math><msubsup><mrow><mi>ℵ</mi></mrow><mrow><mn>1</mn></mrow><mrow><mo>+</mo></mrow></msubsup></math></span> which strongly resembles the equivalence relation of pinned cardinal <span><math><msubsup><mrow><mi>ℵ</mi></mrow><mrow><mn>1</mn></mrow><mrow><mo>+</mo></mrow></msubsup></math></span> from <span>[25]</span>, but which does not Borel reduce to the latter. It remains open whether they are actually incomparable under Borel reductions.</p><p>Our proofs rely on the study of symmetric models whose symmetries come from the group <em>Q</em>. We show that when <em>Q</em> is “locally finite”—e.g. when <span><math><mi>Q</mi><mo>=</mo><mrow><mi>Aut</mi></mrow><mo>(</mo><mi>M</mi><mo>)</mo></math></span>, where <span><math><mi>M</mi></math></span> is the Fraïssé limit of a Fraïssé class satisfying the disjoint amalgamation property—the corresponding symmetric model admits a theory of supports which is analogous to that in the basic Cohen model.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":50762,"journal":{"name":"Annals of Pure and Applied Logic","volume":"175 5","pages":"Article 103412"},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2024-02-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139657003","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"数学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2024-01-30DOI: 10.1016/j.apal.2024.103413
Emmanuel Gunther , Miguel Pagano , Pedro Sánchez Terraf , Matías Steinberg
We discuss some highlights of our computer-verified proof of the construction, given a countable transitive set-model M of ZFC, of generic extensions satisfying and . Moreover, let be the set of instances of the Axiom of Replacement. We isolated a 21-element subset and defined such that for every and M-generic G, implies , where ZC is Zermelo set theory with Choice.
To achieve this, we worked in the proof assistant Isabelle, basing our development on the Isabelle/ZF library by L. Paulson and others.
我们将讨论计算机验证证明的一些要点,即在给定 ZFC 的可数传递集合模型 M 的情况下,构造满足 ZFC+¬CH 和 ZFC+CH 的泛型扩展。此外,让 R 是替换公理的实例集。我们分离出一个 21 元子集 Ω⊆R,并定义了 F:R→R,使得对于每一个 Φ⊆R 和 M 泛函 G,M⊨ZC∪F "Φ∪Ω 意味着 M[G]⊨ZC∪Φ∪{¬CH},其中 ZC 是带选择的泽梅洛集合论。为了实现这一目标,我们使用了证明助手 Isabelle,以 L. Paulson 等人的 Isabelle/ZF 库为基础进行开发。
{"title":"The formal verification of the ctm approach to forcing","authors":"Emmanuel Gunther , Miguel Pagano , Pedro Sánchez Terraf , Matías Steinberg","doi":"10.1016/j.apal.2024.103413","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.apal.2024.103413","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>We discuss some highlights of our computer-verified proof of the construction, given a countable transitive set-model <em>M</em> of <em>ZFC</em>, of generic extensions satisfying <span><math><mrow><mi>ZFC</mi></mrow><mo>+</mo><mo>¬</mo><mrow><mi>CH</mi></mrow></math></span> and <span><math><mrow><mi>ZFC</mi></mrow><mo>+</mo><mrow><mi>CH</mi></mrow></math></span>. Moreover, let <span><math><mi>R</mi></math></span> be the set of instances of the Axiom of Replacement. We isolated a 21-element subset <span><math><mi>Ω</mi><mo>⊆</mo><mi>R</mi></math></span> and defined <span><math><mi>F</mi><mo>:</mo><mi>R</mi><mo>→</mo><mi>R</mi></math></span> such that for every <span><math><mi>Φ</mi><mo>⊆</mo><mi>R</mi></math></span> and <em>M</em>-generic <em>G</em>, <span><math><mi>M</mi><mo>⊨</mo><mrow><mi>ZC</mi></mrow><mo>∪</mo><mi>F</mi><mtext>“</mtext><mi>Φ</mi><mo>∪</mo><mi>Ω</mi></math></span> implies <span><math><mi>M</mi><mo>[</mo><mi>G</mi><mo>]</mo><mo>⊨</mo><mrow><mi>ZC</mi></mrow><mo>∪</mo><mi>Φ</mi><mo>∪</mo><mo>{</mo><mo>¬</mo><mrow><mi>CH</mi></mrow><mo>}</mo></math></span>, where <em>ZC</em> is Zermelo set theory with Choice.</p><p>To achieve this, we worked in the proof assistant <em>Isabelle</em>, basing our development on the Isabelle/ZF library by L. Paulson and others.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":50762,"journal":{"name":"Annals of Pure and Applied Logic","volume":"175 5","pages":"Article 103413"},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2024-01-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139649384","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"数学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2024-01-12DOI: 10.1016/j.apal.2024.103411
Miloš S. Kurilić
Matatyahu Rubin has shown that a sharp version of Vaught's conjecture, , holds for each complete theory of linear order . We show that the same is true for each complete theory of partial order having a model in the minimal class of partial orders containing the class of linear orders and which is closed under finite products and finite disjoint unions. The same holds for the extension of the class of rooted trees admitting a finite monomorphic decomposition, obtained in the same way. The sharp version of Vaught's conjecture also holds for the theories of trees which are infinite disjoint unions of linear orders.
马塔提胡-鲁宾(Matatyahu Rubin)已经证明,沃特猜想的一个尖锐版本 I(T,ω)∈{0,1,c} 对于线性阶 T 的每一个完整理论都成立。我们证明,对于在包含线性阶类的最小偏阶类中有一个模型并且在有限乘积和有限不相交联合下是封闭的偏阶类的每一个完整理论也是如此。用同样的方法得到的根树类的扩展也是如此,该类允许有限单态分解。沃特猜想的尖锐版本也适用于线性阶的无限不相交联合的树理论。
{"title":"Sharp Vaught's conjecture for some classes of partial orders","authors":"Miloš S. Kurilić","doi":"10.1016/j.apal.2024.103411","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.apal.2024.103411","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Matatyahu Rubin has shown that a sharp version of Vaught's conjecture, <span><math><mi>I</mi><mo>(</mo><mi>T</mi><mo>,</mo><mi>ω</mi><mo>)</mo><mo>∈</mo><mo>{</mo><mn>0</mn><mo>,</mo><mn>1</mn><mo>,</mo><mi>c</mi><mo>}</mo></math></span>, holds for each complete theory of linear order <span><math><mi>T</mi></math></span>. We show that the same is true for each complete theory of partial order having a model in the minimal class of partial orders containing the class of linear orders and which is closed under finite products and finite disjoint unions. The same holds for the extension of the class of rooted trees admitting a finite monomorphic decomposition, obtained in the same way. The sharp version of Vaught's conjecture also holds for the theories of trees which are infinite disjoint unions of linear orders.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":50762,"journal":{"name":"Annals of Pure and Applied Logic","volume":"175 4","pages":"Article 103411"},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2024-01-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139462598","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"数学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2024-01-05DOI: 10.1016/j.apal.2023.103403
Liling Ko
Given a finite lattice L that can be embedded in the recursively enumerable (r.e.) Turing degrees , it is not known how one can characterize the degrees below which L can be embedded. Two important characterizations are of the and lattices, where the lattices are embedded below d if and only if d contains sets of “fickleness” >ω and respectively. We work towards finding a lattice that characterizes the levels above , the first non-trivial level after ω. We considered lattices that are as “short” in height and “narrow” in width as and , but the lattices characterize also the >ω or levels, if the lattices are not already embeddable below all non-zero r.e. degrees. We also considered upper semilattices (USLs) by removing the bottom meet(s) of some previously considered lattices, but the removals did not change the levels characterized. We discovered three lattices besides that also characterize the -levels. Our search for -candidates can therefore be reduced to the lattice-theoretic problem of finding lattices that do not contain any of the four -lattices as sublattices.
{"title":"Towards characterizing the >ω2-fickle recursively enumerable Turing degrees","authors":"Liling Ko","doi":"10.1016/j.apal.2023.103403","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.apal.2023.103403","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p><span>Given a finite lattice </span><em>L</em><span> that can be embedded in the recursively enumerable (r.e.) Turing degrees </span><span><math><mo>〈</mo><msub><mrow><mi>R</mi></mrow><mrow><mi>T</mi></mrow></msub><mo>,</mo><msub><mrow><mo>≤</mo></mrow><mrow><mi>T</mi></mrow></msub><mo>〉</mo></math></span>, it is not known how one can characterize the degrees <span><math><mi>d</mi><mo>∈</mo><msub><mrow><mi>R</mi></mrow><mrow><mi>T</mi></mrow></msub></math></span> below which <em>L</em> can be embedded. Two important characterizations are of the <span><math><msub><mrow><mi>L</mi></mrow><mrow><mn>7</mn></mrow></msub></math></span> and <span><math><msub><mrow><mi>M</mi></mrow><mrow><mn>3</mn></mrow></msub></math></span> lattices, where the lattices are embedded below <strong>d</strong> if and only if <strong>d</strong> contains sets of “<em>fickleness</em>” ><em>ω</em> and <span><math><mo>≥</mo><msup><mrow><mi>ω</mi></mrow><mrow><mi>ω</mi></mrow></msup></math></span> respectively. We work towards finding a lattice that characterizes the levels above <span><math><msup><mrow><mi>ω</mi></mrow><mrow><mn>2</mn></mrow></msup></math></span>, the first non-trivial level after <em>ω</em>. We considered lattices that are as “short” in height and “narrow” in width as <span><math><msub><mrow><mi>L</mi></mrow><mrow><mn>7</mn></mrow></msub></math></span> and <span><math><msub><mrow><mi>M</mi></mrow><mrow><mn>3</mn></mrow></msub></math></span>, but the lattices characterize also the ><em>ω</em> or <span><math><mo>≥</mo><msup><mrow><mi>ω</mi></mrow><mrow><mi>ω</mi></mrow></msup></math></span> levels, if the lattices are not already embeddable below all non-zero r.e. degrees. We also considered upper semilattices (USLs) by removing the bottom meet(s) of some previously considered lattices, but the removals did not change the levels characterized. We discovered three lattices besides <span><math><msub><mrow><mi>M</mi></mrow><mrow><mn>3</mn></mrow></msub></math></span> that also characterize the <span><math><mo>≥</mo><msup><mrow><mi>ω</mi></mrow><mrow><mi>ω</mi></mrow></msup></math></span>-levels. Our search for <span><math><mo>></mo><msup><mrow><mi>ω</mi></mrow><mrow><mn>2</mn></mrow></msup></math></span>-candidates can therefore be reduced to the lattice-theoretic problem of finding lattices that do not contain any of the four <span><math><mo>≥</mo><msup><mrow><mi>ω</mi></mrow><mrow><mi>ω</mi></mrow></msup></math></span><span>-lattices as sublattices.</span></p></div>","PeriodicalId":50762,"journal":{"name":"Annals of Pure and Applied Logic","volume":"175 4","pages":"Article 103403"},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2024-01-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139104768","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"数学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2023-12-16DOI: 10.1016/j.apal.2023.103391
Paolo Aglianò , Sara Ugolini
In this work we study the notions of structural and universal completeness both from the algebraic and logical point of view. In particular, we provide new algebraic characterizations of quasivarieties that are actively and passively universally complete, and passively structurally complete. We apply these general results to varieties of bounded lattices and to quasivarieties related to substructural logics. In particular we show that a substructural logic satisfying weakening is passively structurally complete if and only if every classical contradiction is explosive in it. Moreover, we fully characterize the passively structurally complete varieties of -algebras, i.e., bounded commutative integral residuated lattices generated by chains.
{"title":"Structural and universal completeness in algebra and logic","authors":"Paolo Aglianò , Sara Ugolini","doi":"10.1016/j.apal.2023.103391","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.apal.2023.103391","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>In this work we study the notions of structural and universal completeness both from the algebraic and logical point of view. In particular, we provide new algebraic characterizations of quasivarieties that are actively and passively universally complete, and passively structurally complete. We apply these general results to varieties of bounded lattices and to quasivarieties related to substructural logics. In particular we show that a substructural logic satisfying weakening is passively structurally complete if and only if every classical contradiction is explosive in it. Moreover, we fully characterize the passively structurally complete varieties of <span><math><mi>MTL</mi></math></span>-algebras, i.e., bounded commutative integral residuated lattices generated by chains.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":50762,"journal":{"name":"Annals of Pure and Applied Logic","volume":"175 3","pages":"Article 103391"},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2023-12-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0168007223001483/pdfft?md5=566d39a3ec46ed86a39bb7490723fd1b&pid=1-s2.0-S0168007223001483-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"138683789","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"数学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2023-12-11DOI: 10.1016/j.apal.2023.103402
JinHoo Ahn , Joonhee Kim
In this paper, we study some tree properties and their related indiscernibilities. First, we prove that SOP2 can be witnessed by a formula with a tree of tuples holding ‘arbitrary homogeneous inconsistency’ (e.g., weak k-TP1 conditions or other possible inconsistency configurations).
And we introduce a notion of tree-indiscernibility, which preserves witnesses of SOP1, and by using this, we investigate the problem of (in)equality of SOP1 and SOP2.
Assuming the existence of a formula having SOP1 such that no finite conjunction of it has SOP2, we observe that the formula must witness some tree-property-like phenomenon, which we will call the antichain tree property (ATP, see Definition 4.1). We show that ATP implies SOP1 and TP2, but the converse of each implication does not hold. So the class of NATP theories (theories without ATP) contains the class of NSOP1 theories and the class of NTP2 theories.
At the end of the paper, we construct a structure whose theory has a formula having ATP, but any conjunction of the formula does not have SOP2. So this example shows that SOP1 and SOP2 are not the same at the level of formulas, i.e., there is a formula having SOP1, while any finite conjunction of it does not witness SOP2 (but a variation of the formula still has SOP2).
{"title":"SOP1, SOP2, and antichain tree property","authors":"JinHoo Ahn , Joonhee Kim","doi":"10.1016/j.apal.2023.103402","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.apal.2023.103402","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>In this paper, we study some tree properties and their related indiscernibilities. First, we prove that SOP<sub>2</sub> can be witnessed by a formula with a tree of tuples holding ‘arbitrary homogeneous inconsistency’ (e.g., weak <em>k</em>-TP<sub>1</sub> conditions or other possible inconsistency configurations).</p><p>And we introduce a notion of tree-indiscernibility, which preserves witnesses of SOP<sub>1</sub>, and by using this, we investigate the problem of (in)equality of SOP<sub>1</sub> and SOP<sub>2</sub>.</p><p>Assuming the existence of a formula having SOP<sub>1</sub> such that no finite conjunction of it has SOP<sub>2</sub><span>, we observe that the formula must witness some tree-property-like phenomenon, which we will call the antichain tree property (ATP, see </span><span>Definition 4.1</span>). We show that ATP implies SOP<sub>1</sub> and TP<sub>2</sub>, but the converse of each implication does not hold. So the class of NATP theories (theories without ATP) contains the class of NSOP<sub>1</sub> theories and the class of NTP<sub>2</sub> theories.</p><p>At the end of the paper, we construct a structure whose theory has a formula having ATP, but any conjunction of the formula does not have SOP<sub>2</sub>. So this example shows that SOP<sub>1</sub> and SOP<sub>2</sub> are not the same at the level of formulas, i.e., there is a formula having SOP<sub>1</sub>, while any finite conjunction of it does not witness SOP<sub>2</sub> (but a variation of the formula still has SOP<sub>2</sub>).</p></div>","PeriodicalId":50762,"journal":{"name":"Annals of Pure and Applied Logic","volume":"175 3","pages":"Article 103402"},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2023-12-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"138575042","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"数学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2023-12-07DOI: 10.1016/j.apal.2023.103392
Richard Matthews , Michael Rathjen
We study the properties of the constructible universe, L, over intuitionistic theories. We give an extended set of fundamental operations which is sufficient to generate the universe over Intuitionistic Kripke-Platek set theory without Infinity. Following this, we investigate when L can fail to be an inner model in the traditional sense. Namely, we show that over Constructive Zermelo-Fraenkel (even with the Power Set axiom) one cannot prove that the Axiom of Exponentiation holds in L.
我们研究直觉主义理论的可构造宇宙 L 的性质。我们给出了一个基本运算的扩展集,它足以在直观克里普克-普拉特克集合论上生成无穷大的宇宙。在此基础上,我们研究了什么情况下 L 不能成为传统意义上的内部模型。也就是说,我们证明在构造泽梅洛-弗兰克尔(即使有幂集公理)上,我们无法证明幂级数公理在 L 中成立。
{"title":"Constructing the constructible universe constructively","authors":"Richard Matthews , Michael Rathjen","doi":"10.1016/j.apal.2023.103392","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.apal.2023.103392","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>We study the properties of the constructible universe, L, over intuitionistic theories. We give an extended set of fundamental operations which is sufficient to generate the universe over Intuitionistic Kripke-Platek set theory without Infinity. Following this, we investigate when L can fail to be an inner model in the traditional sense. Namely, we show that over Constructive Zermelo-Fraenkel (even with the Power Set axiom) one cannot prove that the Axiom of Exponentiation holds in L.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":50762,"journal":{"name":"Annals of Pure and Applied Logic","volume":"175 3","pages":"Article 103392"},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2023-12-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"138548019","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"数学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2023-11-20DOI: 10.1016/j.apal.2023.103390
Samuele Maschio, Davide Trotta
Implicative algebras have been recently introduced by Miquel in order to provide a unifying notion of model, encompassing the most relevant and used ones, such as realizability (both classical and intuitionistic), and forcing. In this work, we initially approach implicative algebras as a generalization of locales, and we extend several topological-like concepts to the realm of implicative algebras, accompanied by various concrete examples. Then, we shift our focus to viewing implicative algebras as a generalization of partial combinatory algebras. We abstract the notion of a category of assemblies, partition assemblies, and modest sets to arbitrary implicative algebras, and thoroughly investigate their categorical properties and interrelationships.
{"title":"On categorical structures arising from implicative algebras: From topology to assemblies","authors":"Samuele Maschio, Davide Trotta","doi":"10.1016/j.apal.2023.103390","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1016/j.apal.2023.103390","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Implicative algebras have been recently introduced by Miquel in order to provide a unifying notion of model, encompassing the most relevant and used ones, such as realizability (both classical and intuitionistic), and forcing. In this work, we initially approach implicative algebras as a generalization of locales, and we extend several topological-like concepts to the realm of implicative algebras, accompanied by various concrete examples. Then, we shift our focus to viewing implicative algebras as a generalization of partial combinatory algebras. We abstract the notion of a category of assemblies, partition assemblies, and modest sets to arbitrary implicative algebras, and thoroughly investigate their categorical properties and interrelationships.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":50762,"journal":{"name":"Annals of Pure and Applied Logic","volume":"175 3","pages":"Article 103390"},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2023-11-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0168007223001471/pdfft?md5=e62dfd1384a82cf70c38bd805eb49847&pid=1-s2.0-S0168007223001471-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"138484884","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"数学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2023-11-14DOI: 10.1016/j.apal.2023.103389
Dragan Doder , Zoran Ognjanović
This work presents a proof-theoretical and model-theoretical approach to probabilistic temporal logic. We present two novel logics; each of them extends both the language of linear time logic (LTL) and the language of probabilistic logic with polynomial weight formulas. The first logic is designed for reasoning about probabilities of temporal events, allowing statements like “the probability that A will hold in next moment is at least the probability that B will always hold” and conditional probability statements like “probability that A will always hold, given that B holds, is at least one half”, where A and B are arbitrary statements. We axiomatize this logic, provide corresponding sigma additive semantics and prove that the axiomatization is sound and strongly complete. We show that the satisfiability problem for our logic is decidable, by presenting a procedure which runs in polynomial space. We also present a logic with much richer language, in which probabilities are not attached only to temporal events, but the language allows arbitrary nesting of probability and temporal operators, allowing statements like “probability that tomorrow the chance of rain will be less than 80% is at least a half”. For this logic we prove a decidability result.
这项研究提出了一种证明理论和模型理论方法来研究概率时态逻辑。我们提出了两个新颖的逻辑;每个逻辑都扩展了线性时间逻辑(LTL)语言和具有多项式权重公式的概率逻辑语言。第一种逻辑是为推理时间事件的概率而设计的,它允许 "A 在下一时刻成立的概率至少是 B 始终成立的概率 "这样的语句,以及 "A 始终成立的概率至少是 B 成立的二分之一 "这样的条件概率语句,其中 A 和 B 是任意语句。我们对这一逻辑进行了公理化,提供了相应的西格玛加法语义,并证明了公理化的合理性和强完备性。我们提出了一个在多项式空间内运行的过程,从而证明我们逻辑的可满足性问题是可解的。我们还提出了一种语言更为丰富的逻辑,在这种逻辑中,概率不仅与时间事件相关联,而且允许概率和时间运算符的任意嵌套,允许 "明天下雨的概率小于 80% 的概率至少是一半 "这样的语句。对于这种逻辑,我们证明了一个可解性结果。
{"title":"Probabilistic temporal logic with countably additive semantics","authors":"Dragan Doder , Zoran Ognjanović","doi":"10.1016/j.apal.2023.103389","DOIUrl":"10.1016/j.apal.2023.103389","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>This work presents a proof-theoretical and model-theoretical approach to probabilistic temporal logic. We present two novel logics; each of them extends both the language of linear time logic (LTL) and the language of probabilistic logic with polynomial weight formulas. The first logic is designed for reasoning about probabilities of temporal events, allowing statements like “the probability that A will hold in next moment is at least the probability that B will always hold” and conditional probability statements like “probability that A will always hold, given that B holds, is at least one half”, where A and B are arbitrary statements. We axiomatize this logic, provide corresponding sigma additive semantics and prove that the axiomatization is sound and strongly complete. We show that the satisfiability problem for our logic is decidable, by presenting a procedure which runs in polynomial space. We also present a logic with much richer language, in which probabilities are not attached only to temporal events, but the language allows arbitrary nesting of probability and temporal operators, allowing statements like “probability that tomorrow the chance of rain will be less than 80% is at least a half”. For this logic we prove a decidability result.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":50762,"journal":{"name":"Annals of Pure and Applied Logic","volume":"175 9","pages":"Article 103389"},"PeriodicalIF":0.8,"publicationDate":"2023-11-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S016800722300146X/pdfft?md5=b48bdc121fa115161627545db4c861fd&pid=1-s2.0-S016800722300146X-main.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135716247","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"数学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}