首页 > 最新文献

TheoLogica最新文献

英文 中文
Defining and Supplementing Conciliar Trinitarianism 界定和补充大公三位一体论
Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2020-07-30 DOI: 10.14428/thl.v4i2.55393
A. Torrance
This article constitutes a brief reply to Timothy Pawl's clear and insightful article on Conciliar Trinitarianism (defined as the Trinitarian theology of the Ecumenical Councils from Nicaea I to Nicaea II). The two basic arguments of that article (regarding the relationship between divine persons and divine nature and the debate over possible subordinationism) are celebrated rather than challenged. I instead offer three short comments. The first concerns the limited nature of the conciliar texts for the articulation of highly developed Trinitarian theology, and thus the question of methodology as it applies to Conciliar Trinitarianism. The second comment argues that the question of strict identity in the Godhead can be extended beyond the relationship of divine person and divine nature to the question of divine nature and divine power, will, and energy. The third comment argues that Pawl gives undue weight to a line from Cyril of Alexandria for a discussion of the Holy Spirt's mode of origination, and not enough weight to the clause related to the Holy Spirit articulated at the First Council of Constantinople, which recurs in one way or another at each of the subsequent Ecumenical Councils, up to and including Nicaea II. These three comments serve more as a supplement than a challenge to Pawl's original article, providing three further avenues for scholarly deliberation on the matter of Conciliar Trinitarianism.
这篇文章是对Timothy Pawl关于大公会议三位一体论(定义为从尼西亚第一届到尼西亚第二届大公会议的三位一体神学)的清晰而深刻的文章的简短回复。这篇文章的两个基本论点(关于神的位格和神的本质之间的关系以及关于可能的从属主义的辩论)是庆祝而不是挑战。相反,我提供了三条简短的评论。第一个问题是大公会议文本对高度发展的三位一体神学的表达的有限性,以及适用于大公会议三位一体论的方法论问题。第二个评论认为,神性的严格同一性问题可以延伸到神性与神性的关系之外,延伸到神性与神的力量、意志和能量的问题。第三条评论认为,保罗过分重视亚历山大的西里尔关于圣灵起源模式的论述,而对君士坦丁堡第一次大公会议中有关圣灵的条款重视不够,而这一条款在随后的每一次大公会议中都以这样或那样的方式出现,直到尼西亚二世。这三条评论更多的是作为对保罗原稿的补充而不是挑战,为大公会议三位一体论的学术讨论提供了三条进一步的途径。
{"title":"Defining and Supplementing Conciliar Trinitarianism","authors":"A. Torrance","doi":"10.14428/thl.v4i2.55393","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.14428/thl.v4i2.55393","url":null,"abstract":"This article constitutes a brief reply to Timothy Pawl's clear and insightful article on Conciliar Trinitarianism (defined as the Trinitarian theology of the Ecumenical Councils from Nicaea I to Nicaea II). The two basic arguments of that article (regarding the relationship between divine persons and divine nature and the debate over possible subordinationism) are celebrated rather than challenged. I instead offer three short comments. The first concerns the limited nature of the conciliar texts for the articulation of highly developed Trinitarian theology, and thus the question of methodology as it applies to Conciliar Trinitarianism. The second comment argues that the question of strict identity in the Godhead can be extended beyond the relationship of divine person and divine nature to the question of divine nature and divine power, will, and energy. The third comment argues that Pawl gives undue weight to a line from Cyril of Alexandria for a discussion of the Holy Spirt's mode of origination, and not enough weight to the clause related to the Holy Spirit articulated at the First Council of Constantinople, which recurs in one way or another at each of the subsequent Ecumenical Councils, up to and including Nicaea II. These three comments serve more as a supplement than a challenge to Pawl's original article, providing three further avenues for scholarly deliberation on the matter of Conciliar Trinitarianism.","PeriodicalId":52326,"journal":{"name":"TheoLogica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-07-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"85076425","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
La perichoresis e la grammatica teologica dei primi sette Concili ecumenici 前七次教会会议的《圣经》和神学语法
Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2020-04-30 DOI: 10.14428/thl.v4i2.22183
G. Maspero
The article analyzes the history of the term perichoresis in the space of time embraced by the first seven ecumenical councils. After the Christological debut of the terminology in the fourth century in the work of Gregory of Nazianzus to indicate the dynamism of the relationship of the two natures of Christ in the hypostatic union, the text shows how this theological transition was the basis of the development in Maximus the Confessor. In the seventh century he applied the theological gain of Gregory of Nazianzus to divinization, making explicit the Christological foundation of Christian salvation. The journey ends in the 8th century with John Damascene, who applies perichoresis to both Christology and divinization, as already seen before him, but extends the terminology to the Trinitarian dimension, thus sealing the parable of theological thought. This makes it possible to recognize a true theological grammar which, consistently with Timothy Pawl's studies, reveals the architectural value of a Conciliar Trinitarianism, as a Trinitarian epistemology based on a Trinitarian anthropology, in turn rooted in a Trinitarian ontology.  Abstract: L'articolo analizza la storia del termine perichoresis nello spazio di tempo abbracciato dai primi sette concili ecumenici. Dopo l'esordio cristologico nel IV secolo della terminologia nell'opera di Gregorio di Nazianzo per indicare la dinamicità del rapporto delle due nature del Cristo nell'unione ipostatica, si mostra come questo passo teologico sarà la base dello sviluppo in Massimo il Confessore. Questi nel VII seccolo applicherà il guadagno teologico del Nazianzeno alla divinizzazione, esplicitando il fondamento cristologico della salvezza cristiana. Il percorso si conclude nell'VIII secolo con Giovanni Damasceno, il quale applica perichoresis sia alla cristologia, sia alla divinizzazione, come già prima di lui, ma estende la terminologia anche alla dimensione trinitaria, sigillando così la parabola del pensiero teologico. Ciò permette di riconoscere una vera e propria grammatica teologica che, coerentemente con gli studi di Timothy Pawl, rivela il valore architettonico di un Conciliar Trinitarianism, come epistemologia trinitaria che si fonda su un'antropologia trinitaria, a sua volta radicata in una ontologia trinitaria. 
本文分析了“包涵性”一词在前七次大公会议中所包含的时间空间中的历史。公元四世纪,在格列高利的著作中,这个术语首次出现在基督论中,以表明基督的两种本质之间的动态关系,这篇文章展示了这种神学转变是如何成为《忏悔者马克西姆斯》发展的基础。在七世纪,他将纳齐安祖的格列高利的神学成果应用于神化,明确了基督教救赎的基督论基础。这段旅程在8世纪结束,约翰·大马士革,他在基督论和神化上都应用了包皮隐说,就像他之前看到的,但将术语扩展到三位一体的维度,从而密封了神学思想的寓言。这使我们有可能认识到一个真正的神学语法,它与Timothy Pawl的研究一致,揭示了大公会议三位一体论的建筑价值,作为基于三位一体人类学的三位一体认识论,反过来植根于三位一体的本体论。摘要:关节分析的目的是确定关节包膜运动的时间和速度,以确定关节包膜运动的时间和速度。在意大利,意大利人对基督教的信仰是虔诚的,意大利人对基督教的信仰是虔诚的,意大利人对基督教的信仰是虔诚的,意大利人对基督教的信仰是虔诚的,意大利人是虔诚的。问题七:科学应用领域:科学技术领域:科学技术领域:科学技术领域:科学技术领域:科学技术领域:科学技术领域:科学技术领域:科学技术领域:科学技术领域:科学技术领域Il percorso si结论nell'VIII secolo on Giovanni damasasceno, Il quale applied perichoresis sia alla cristologia, sia alla divinizazione, come gigioprima di lui, ma estende la terminologia andalla dimensionontritriia, sigillando così la parabola del pensiero tecologia。Ciò permette di riconoscere una vera propria grammatica teologicalche, coerentemente congli studi di Timothy Pawl, rivela il valvalore architettonico di unconciliar三位一体,come epistemologia trinitaria che si fonda su ununanthropologia trinitaria, a sua volta radicata in una ontology trinitaria。
{"title":"La perichoresis e la grammatica teologica dei primi sette Concili ecumenici","authors":"G. Maspero","doi":"10.14428/thl.v4i2.22183","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.14428/thl.v4i2.22183","url":null,"abstract":"The article analyzes the history of the term perichoresis in the space of time embraced by the first seven ecumenical councils. After the Christological debut of the terminology in the fourth century in the work of Gregory of Nazianzus to indicate the dynamism of the relationship of the two natures of Christ in the hypostatic union, the text shows how this theological transition was the basis of the development in Maximus the Confessor. In the seventh century he applied the theological gain of Gregory of Nazianzus to divinization, making explicit the Christological foundation of Christian salvation. The journey ends in the 8th century with John Damascene, who applies perichoresis to both Christology and divinization, as already seen before him, but extends the terminology to the Trinitarian dimension, thus sealing the parable of theological thought. This makes it possible to recognize a true theological grammar which, consistently with Timothy Pawl's studies, reveals the architectural value of a Conciliar Trinitarianism, as a Trinitarian epistemology based on a Trinitarian anthropology, in turn rooted in a Trinitarian ontology.  \u0000Abstract: L'articolo analizza la storia del termine perichoresis nello spazio di tempo abbracciato dai primi sette concili ecumenici. Dopo l'esordio cristologico nel IV secolo della terminologia nell'opera di Gregorio di Nazianzo per indicare la dinamicità del rapporto delle due nature del Cristo nell'unione ipostatica, si mostra come questo passo teologico sarà la base dello sviluppo in Massimo il Confessore. Questi nel VII seccolo applicherà il guadagno teologico del Nazianzeno alla divinizzazione, esplicitando il fondamento cristologico della salvezza cristiana. Il percorso si conclude nell'VIII secolo con Giovanni Damasceno, il quale applica perichoresis sia alla cristologia, sia alla divinizzazione, come già prima di lui, ma estende la terminologia anche alla dimensione trinitaria, sigillando così la parabola del pensiero teologico. Ciò permette di riconoscere una vera e propria grammatica teologica che, coerentemente con gli studi di Timothy Pawl, rivela il valore architettonico di un Conciliar Trinitarianism, come epistemologia trinitaria che si fonda su un'antropologia trinitaria, a sua volta radicata in una ontologia trinitaria. ","PeriodicalId":52326,"journal":{"name":"TheoLogica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-04-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"87777214","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
When and How in the History of Theology Did the Triune God Replace the Father as the Only True God? 在神学历史上,三位一体的神何时以及如何取代父神成为独一真神?
Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2020-04-01 DOI: 10.14428/thl.v4i2.23773
Dale Tuggy
A traditional view is that Christians have always believed that the one God is three Persons in one essence or being. Orthodox analytic theologian Beau Branson has recently argued that this is untrue, as earlier “fathers” taught that the one God just is the Father. He argues that this sensible Eastern view was misunderstood by Western sources, which is how the idea of the one God as tripersonal entered into mainstream Christian theologies. While I agree with Branson that in about the first three Christian centuries the teaching was that the one God just is the Father, I argue that his account about when and how the idea of a triune God comes in is mistaken, because we can see this new idea of a tripersonal God appearing in both Eastern and Western sources around the time of the council at Constantinople in 381, the surviving statement of which is the earliest “official” creed which assumes and implies that the one God is the Trinity, the tripersonal God.
传统的观点是,基督徒一直相信,一个上帝是三个人在一个本质或存在。正统分析神学家博·布兰森(Beau Branson)最近认为,这是不正确的,因为早期的“父亲”教导说,唯一的上帝是父亲。他认为,这种明智的东方观点被西方资源误解了,这就是为什么一个上帝是三人格的想法进入了主流基督教神学。虽然我同意布兰森的观点,在基督教最初的三个世纪里,人们的教导是唯一的上帝就是父亲,但我认为他关于三位一体的上帝是何时以及如何出现的说法是错误的,因为我们可以看到,在公元381年君士坦丁堡会议期间,东方和西方都出现了三位一体的上帝的新观点,现存的声明是最早的“官方”信条,它假设并暗示唯一的上帝是三位一体的上帝。
{"title":"When and How in the History of Theology Did the Triune God Replace the Father as the Only True God?","authors":"Dale Tuggy","doi":"10.14428/thl.v4i2.23773","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.14428/thl.v4i2.23773","url":null,"abstract":"A traditional view is that Christians have always believed that the one God is three Persons in one essence or being. Orthodox analytic theologian Beau Branson has recently argued that this is untrue, as earlier “fathers” taught that the one God just is the Father. He argues that this sensible Eastern view was misunderstood by Western sources, which is how the idea of the one God as tripersonal entered into mainstream Christian theologies. While I agree with Branson that in about the first three Christian centuries the teaching was that the one God just is the Father, I argue that his account about when and how the idea of a triune God comes in is mistaken, because we can see this new idea of a tripersonal God appearing in both Eastern and Western sources around the time of the council at Constantinople in 381, the surviving statement of which is the earliest “official” creed which assumes and implies that the one God is the Trinity, the tripersonal God.","PeriodicalId":52326,"journal":{"name":"TheoLogica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"83480017","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Is Subordinationism a Heresy? 从属主义是异端吗?
Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2020-02-05 DOI: 10.14428/thl.v4i2.23803
M. Edwards
The modern resurgence of orthodoxy in Anglican circles takes as its cardinal tenet the eternal coinherence of three persons in the one Godhead, equal in substance, rank and power. This is assumed to be the doctrine of the Nicene Council of 325, and the putative heresy that denies it is known by the term subordinationism. Although the ample lexicon of Greek heresiology supplies no clear antecedent for this term, the charge of subordinationism is thought to imperil any claim to be teaching in the catholic tradition, even if the teacher is Barth or Rahner. The confidence with which these accusations are levelled, however, seems to be in an inverse ratio to the accuser’s knowledge of history, for neither in New Testament scholarship nor at the cutting edge of the modern study of patristics will one find much evidence that subordinationism is even an anomaly, let alone an aberration from the biblical or conciliar norm. It is only in modern theology, not in the writings of empirical historians, that the Gorgon’s head of Arius is held up to those who question the strict equality of persons. At the same time, we must not forget that the systematician’s reading of Nicaea was until recently also that of the historian. No doubt the reason is partly that until the last half–century every historian was also a confessional theologian; but there is also a certain truth in the older approach so long as some pains are taken to define “subordination”.
现代复兴的正统在英国圣公会的圈子,作为其基本原则,永恒的内在的三个人在一个神,平等的物质,等级和权力。这被认为是325年尼西亚会议的教义,而否认这一教义的异端被称为从属主义。虽然希腊异端充足的词汇提供了这个词没有明确的先例,指控从属主义被认为危及任何声称是在天主教传统教学,即使教师是巴特或拉纳。然而,这些指控的信心似乎与原告的历史知识成反比,因为无论是在新约学术还是在现代教父研究的前沿,人们都找不到太多证据表明从属主义是一种反常现象,更不用说偏离圣经或大公会议规范了。只有在现代神学中,而不是在经验主义历史学家的著作中,才有人把蛇发女工阿里乌斯的头举到那些质疑人的严格平等的人面前。同时,我们不能忘记,直到最近,系统神学家对尼西亚的解读,也是历史学家的解读。毫无疑问,部分原因在于,直到上半个世纪,每一位历史学家同时也是认信派神学家;但是,只要花点功夫来定义“从属关系”,旧的方法也有一定的道理。
{"title":"Is Subordinationism a Heresy?","authors":"M. Edwards","doi":"10.14428/thl.v4i2.23803","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.14428/thl.v4i2.23803","url":null,"abstract":"The modern resurgence of orthodoxy in Anglican circles takes as its cardinal tenet the eternal coinherence of three persons in the one Godhead, equal in substance, rank and power. This is assumed to be the doctrine of the Nicene Council of 325, and the putative heresy that denies it is known by the term subordinationism. Although the ample lexicon of Greek heresiology supplies no clear antecedent for this term, the charge of subordinationism is thought to imperil any claim to be teaching in the catholic tradition, even if the teacher is Barth or Rahner. The confidence with which these accusations are levelled, however, seems to be in an inverse ratio to the accuser’s knowledge of history, for neither in New Testament scholarship nor at the cutting edge of the modern study of patristics will one find much evidence that subordinationism is even an anomaly, let alone an aberration from the biblical or conciliar norm. It is only in modern theology, not in the writings of empirical historians, that the Gorgon’s head of Arius is held up to those who question the strict equality of persons. At the same time, we must not forget that the systematician’s reading of Nicaea was until recently also that of the historian. No doubt the reason is partly that until the last half–century every historian was also a confessional theologian; but there is also a certain truth in the older approach so long as some pains are taken to define “subordination”.","PeriodicalId":52326,"journal":{"name":"TheoLogica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-02-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"90661517","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Truthmaker Trinitarianism Truthmaker三位一体论
Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-12-23 DOI: 10.14428/thl.v3i2.14693
Ryan Byerly
This paper employs recent developments in the theory of truthmakers to offer a novel solution to the most discussed philosophical challenge presented by the Christian doctrine of the Trinity. According to the view developed, the Father, Son, and Spirit each serve as the only substantial constituent of equally minimal truthmakers for claims about God. Because they do, there is a clear and robust sense in which each is a substance that “is” God as much as anything is, while the three remain distinct from each other. The view is shown to hold certain prima facie advantages over rival extant approaches.
本文采用真理制造者理论的最新发展,为基督教三位一体教义提出的最受讨论的哲学挑战提供了一个新颖的解决方案。根据发展出来的观点,圣父、圣子和圣灵各自作为唯一的实质性组成部分,为关于上帝的主张提供同等最低限度的真理制造者。因为他们这样做,有一种清晰而有力的感觉,其中每一个都是一个“是”上帝的物质,就像任何东西一样,而这三个仍然彼此不同。这种观点被证明比现存的竞争方法具有某些初步的优势。
{"title":"Truthmaker Trinitarianism","authors":"Ryan Byerly","doi":"10.14428/thl.v3i2.14693","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.14428/thl.v3i2.14693","url":null,"abstract":"This paper employs recent developments in the theory of truthmakers to offer a novel solution to the most discussed philosophical challenge presented by the Christian doctrine of the Trinity. According to the view developed, the Father, Son, and Spirit each serve as the only substantial constituent of equally minimal truthmakers for claims about God. Because they do, there is a clear and robust sense in which each is a substance that “is” God as much as anything is, while the three remain distinct from each other. The view is shown to hold certain prima facie advantages over rival extant approaches.","PeriodicalId":52326,"journal":{"name":"TheoLogica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-12-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"72796943","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
On Emily Paul on Brian Leftow 艾米丽·保罗和布莱恩·莱弗
Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-12-23 DOI: 10.14428/thl.v3i2.20543
Matthew James Collier
Emily Paul has recently argued that Brian Leftow’s account of why the import of God’s becoming Incarnate is not temporal but modal fails. She argues that Leftow’s required modal variation is not satisfied. That is, we do not have the required variation across logical space concerning the Incarnation. Paul examines her argument on two possible worlds theories: theistic ersatzism and (what I call) Lewisian theism. She thinks that both possible worlds theories face difficulties. I argue that Paul fails to provide a compelling argument against Leftow because, firstly, her defence of one her premises fails, and, secondly, she misjudges what is required for some of Leftow’s claims to be true. I also argue that some of the problematic consequences that Paul raises for theistic ersatzism and Lewisian theism either are not problematic or can be avoided.
艾米丽·保罗最近认为,布莱恩·厄夫关于上帝道成肉身的重要性不是暂时的,而是模式上的失败。她认为,厄弗莱夫所要求的模态变化并没有得到满足。也就是说,我们在关于化身的逻辑空间中没有必要的变异。保罗用两种可能的世界理论来检验她的论点:有神论的伪无神论和(我称之为)刘易斯的有神论。她认为两种可能世界理论都面临困难。我认为保罗没能提供一个令人信服的论据来反对奥莱弗,因为,首先,她对一个前提的辩护失败了,其次,她错误地判断了奥莱弗的一些主张为真所需要的条件。我还认为,保罗提出的,有神论的假无神论,和刘易斯的有神论的,一些有问题的后果,要么没有问题,要么可以避免。
{"title":"On Emily Paul on Brian Leftow","authors":"Matthew James Collier","doi":"10.14428/thl.v3i2.20543","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.14428/thl.v3i2.20543","url":null,"abstract":"Emily Paul has recently argued that Brian Leftow’s account of why the import of God’s becoming Incarnate is not temporal but modal fails. She argues that Leftow’s required modal variation is not satisfied. That is, we do not have the required variation across logical space concerning the Incarnation. Paul examines her argument on two possible worlds theories: theistic ersatzism and (what I call) Lewisian theism. She thinks that both possible worlds theories face difficulties. I argue that Paul fails to provide a compelling argument against Leftow because, firstly, her defence of one her premises fails, and, secondly, she misjudges what is required for some of Leftow’s claims to be true. I also argue that some of the problematic consequences that Paul raises for theistic ersatzism and Lewisian theism either are not problematic or can be avoided.","PeriodicalId":52326,"journal":{"name":"TheoLogica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-12-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"88438344","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Organic Unities 有机统一性
Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-12-23 DOI: 10.14428/thl.v3i1.15243
Graham Floyd
The principle of organic unities is a metaphysical claim regarding the nature of moral value.  It states that the value of the whole is not equal to the summation of its parts.  Even though this principle has a major impact on moral theory, it has been neglected in the consideration of the problem of God and evil.  I claim that the theist can utilize the principle of organic unities to undermine the problem of evil.  First, I explain the principle of organic unities and how it affects one’s understanding of moral value.  Next, I explicate the two major historical versions of the problem of evil: the logical argument from evil and the evidential argument from evil.  Lastly, I argue that the principle of organic unities demonstrates that God may logically co-exist with evil and that the atheologian lacks rational warrant appealing to gratuitous evil against God’s existence.  As a result, both problems fail.
有机统一性原则是关于道德价值本质的形而上学主张。它指出,整体的价值不等于其各部分的总和。尽管这一原则对道德理论有重大影响,但在考虑上帝与邪恶的问题时,它却被忽视了。我认为有神论者可以利用有机统一性原则来削弱邪恶的问题。首先,我解释了有机统一性原则以及它如何影响人们对道德价值的理解。接下来,我将阐述恶的问题的两个主要历史版本:从恶出发的逻辑论证和从恶出发的证据论证。最后,我认为,有机统一性的原则表明,上帝可能在逻辑上与邪恶共存,而神学家缺乏理性的理由,呼吁无端的邪恶反对上帝的存在。结果,两个问题都失败了。
{"title":"Organic Unities","authors":"Graham Floyd","doi":"10.14428/thl.v3i1.15243","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.14428/thl.v3i1.15243","url":null,"abstract":"The principle of organic unities is a metaphysical claim regarding the nature of moral value.  It states that the value of the whole is not equal to the summation of its parts.  Even though this principle has a major impact on moral theory, it has been neglected in the consideration of the problem of God and evil.  I claim that the theist can utilize the principle of organic unities to undermine the problem of evil.  First, I explain the principle of organic unities and how it affects one’s understanding of moral value.  Next, I explicate the two major historical versions of the problem of evil: the logical argument from evil and the evidential argument from evil.  Lastly, I argue that the principle of organic unities demonstrates that God may logically co-exist with evil and that the atheologian lacks rational warrant appealing to gratuitous evil against God’s existence.  As a result, both problems fail.","PeriodicalId":52326,"journal":{"name":"TheoLogica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-12-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"88233911","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Editorial: The Son of God 社论:上帝之子
Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-03-01 DOI: 10.14428/THL.V3I1.18423
Matthew Owen, Fred R. Sanders
For as long as the Christian church has been working out its understanding of the second person of the Trinity, it has employed analytic philosophical reflection to sharpen theological comprehension. In recent times, there has been a rekindled appreciation for the employment of analytic reflection in the service of theology. Analytic theology has established itself as a way of doing theology that employs analytic philosophical analysis in the project of faith in divinely revealed truths seeking understanding. In this issue, the fresh insights of analytic theology are applied to a theme most central to Christian theology—the Son of God.
自从基督教会建立起对三位一体中第二位格的理解以来,它就一直在运用分析性的哲学反思来提高神学理解。在最近的时代,有一个重新点燃的赞赏,为服务的神学分析反思的就业。分析神学已经确立了自己作为一种研究神学的方式,它运用分析哲学分析,在信仰项目中,在神启示的真理中寻求理解。在本期中,分析神学的新见解被应用于基督教神学最核心的主题——上帝之子。
{"title":"Editorial: The Son of God","authors":"Matthew Owen, Fred R. Sanders","doi":"10.14428/THL.V3I1.18423","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.14428/THL.V3I1.18423","url":null,"abstract":"For as long as the Christian church has been working out its understanding of the second person of the Trinity, it has employed analytic philosophical reflection to sharpen theological comprehension. In recent times, there has been a rekindled appreciation for the employment of analytic reflection in the service of theology. Analytic theology has established itself as a way of doing theology that employs analytic philosophical analysis in the project of faith in divinely revealed truths seeking understanding. In this issue, the fresh insights of analytic theology are applied to a theme most central to Christian theology—the Son of God.","PeriodicalId":52326,"journal":{"name":"TheoLogica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"90236841","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Son of God and Trinitarian Identity Statements 神的儿子和三位一体的身份声明
Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-03-01 DOI: 10.14428/THL.V2I3.18413
Matthew Owen, J. Dunne
Classical Trinitarians claim that Jesus—the Son of God—is truly God and that there is only one God and the Father is God, the Spirit is God, and the Father, Son, and Spirit are distinct. However, if the identity statement that ‘the Son is God’ is understood in the sense of numerical identity, logical incoherence seems immanent. Yet, if the identity statement is understood according to an ‘is’ of predication then it lacks accuracy and permits polytheism. Therefore, we argue that there is another sense of ‘is’ needed in trinitarian discourse that will allow the Christian to avoid logical incoherence while still fully affirming all that is meant to be affirmed in the confession ‘Jesus is God.’ We suggest a sense of ‘is’ that meets this need.
经典的三位一体论者声称耶稣——上帝的儿子——是真正的上帝,只有一位上帝,圣父是上帝,圣灵是上帝,圣父、圣子和圣灵是不同的。然而,如果把"圣子是上帝"的同一性表述理解为数字同一性的话,逻辑上的不连贯就显得是内在的了。然而,如果同一性陈述是根据一个“是”的预测来理解的,那么它就缺乏准确性,并允许多神教。因此,我们认为,在三位一体论的论述中,需要另一种意义上的“是”,这将允许基督徒避免逻辑上的不连贯,同时仍然完全肯定所有在“耶稣是上帝”的忏悔中应该被肯定的东西。我们建议使用“是”来满足这种需求。
{"title":"The Son of God and Trinitarian Identity Statements","authors":"Matthew Owen, J. Dunne","doi":"10.14428/THL.V2I3.18413","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.14428/THL.V2I3.18413","url":null,"abstract":"Classical Trinitarians claim that Jesus—the Son of God—is truly God and that there is only one God and the Father is God, the Spirit is God, and the Father, Son, and Spirit are distinct. However, if the identity statement that ‘the Son is God’ is understood in the sense of numerical identity, logical incoherence seems immanent. Yet, if the identity statement is understood according to an ‘is’ of predication then it lacks accuracy and permits polytheism. Therefore, we argue that there is another sense of ‘is’ needed in trinitarian discourse that will allow the Christian to avoid logical incoherence while still fully affirming all that is meant to be affirmed in the confession ‘Jesus is God.’ We suggest a sense of ‘is’ that meets this need.","PeriodicalId":52326,"journal":{"name":"TheoLogica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"79147285","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
On Thomas Aquinas's Rejection of an 'Incarnation Anyway' 论托马斯·阿奎那对“化身论”的否定
Q2 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2019-01-26 DOI: 10.14428/THL.V2I3.15373
Fellipe do Vale
In the recent literature on whether there would have been an incarnation if there had been no fall, Thomas Aquinas is often cited as arguing for a negative answer on the grounds that it is more fitting. Little attention, however, has been given to what fittingness amounts to for Thomas, or what relation this has to the primarily biblical reasons he gives for denying an incarnation without the fall. In this paper, I argue that the fittingness derives primarily from what kinds of conclusions can be drawn from the biblical text – fitting conclusions are those that, though short of necessary truths, nevertheless ought to be preferred over all of the possible alternatives because they best cohere with the nature of the scriptural canon. The answer to whether an incarnation would have occurred, for Thomas, is an example of one such biblical conclusion. I then place Thomas’ arguments in conversation with contemporary advocates in favor of an ‘Incarnation Anyway’ and show that their strategy of argumentation is actually accommodated by Thomas’ position, leaving it safe from criticism.
在最近的文献中,如果没有堕落,是否会有化身,托马斯·阿奎那经常被引用为否定的答案,理由是它更合适。然而,很少有人注意到,对于多马来说,什么是合适的,或者这与他给出的否认没有堕落的化身的主要圣经理由有什么关系。在本文中,我认为,适用性主要来自于从圣经文本中得出的结论——适用性的结论是那些尽管缺乏必要的真理,但应该优先于所有可能的选择,因为它们最符合圣经正典的本质。对于多马来说,关于化身是否会发生的答案,就是这样一个圣经结论的例子。然后,我将托马斯的论点与支持“无论如何化身”的当代倡导者进行对话,并表明他们的论证策略实际上与托马斯的立场相适应,使其免受批评。
{"title":"On Thomas Aquinas's Rejection of an 'Incarnation Anyway'","authors":"Fellipe do Vale","doi":"10.14428/THL.V2I3.15373","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.14428/THL.V2I3.15373","url":null,"abstract":"In the recent literature on whether there would have been an incarnation if there had been no fall, Thomas Aquinas is often cited as arguing for a negative answer on the grounds that it is more fitting. Little attention, however, has been given to what fittingness amounts to for Thomas, or what relation this has to the primarily biblical reasons he gives for denying an incarnation without the fall. In this paper, I argue that the fittingness derives primarily from what kinds of conclusions can be drawn from the biblical text – fitting conclusions are those that, though short of necessary truths, nevertheless ought to be preferred over all of the possible alternatives because they best cohere with the nature of the scriptural canon. The answer to whether an incarnation would have occurred, for Thomas, is an example of one such biblical conclusion. I then place Thomas’ arguments in conversation with contemporary advocates in favor of an ‘Incarnation Anyway’ and show that their strategy of argumentation is actually accommodated by Thomas’ position, leaving it safe from criticism.","PeriodicalId":52326,"journal":{"name":"TheoLogica","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2019-01-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"80275367","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
TheoLogica
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1