首页 > 最新文献

Rivista di Estetica最新文献

英文 中文
The Ontology of Landscapes 风景的本体论
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2020-12-01 DOI: 10.4000/ESTETICA.7426
A. Andrzejewski, M. Salwa
The paper aims at an analysis of the concept of landscape, offering an ontological approach. Our claim is that such a perspective is hardly ever assumed in philosophical aesthetics, even if theories of landscape appreciation are in fact based on tacit ontological assumptions. We argue that having an explicit ontology of landscapes is important, for aesthetic theories of their appreciation are often attacked in terms of the problems caused by their tacit ontologies. Therefore, we sketch an “Experience Ontology” that serves as an alternative to the ontologies implied in the two best known aesthetic approaches to landscapes. We contend that a landscape should not be conceived of as an object or view but as a way of experiencing one’s surroundings, and we argue that our theory is not only free from the shortcomings of the two dominant theories but that it also corresponds better to everyday intuitions.
本文旨在分析景观的概念,提供一种本体论的方法。我们的主张是,在哲学美学中,这种观点几乎从未被假设过,即使景观欣赏理论实际上是基于隐含的本体论假设。我们认为,拥有一个明确的景观本体论是很重要的,因为关于景观欣赏的美学理论经常受到攻击,因为它们的隐性本体论会带来问题。因此,我们绘制了一个“体验本体论”,作为两种最著名的景观美学方法中隐含的本体论的替代品。我们认为,景观不应被视为一种物体或景观,而应被视为由一种体验周围环境的方式。我们认为,我们的理论不仅没有这两种主流理论的缺点,而且更符合日常直觉。
{"title":"The Ontology of Landscapes","authors":"A. Andrzejewski, M. Salwa","doi":"10.4000/ESTETICA.7426","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/ESTETICA.7426","url":null,"abstract":"The paper aims at an analysis of the concept of landscape, offering an ontological approach. Our claim is that such a perspective is hardly ever assumed in philosophical aesthetics, even if theories of landscape appreciation are in fact based on tacit ontological assumptions. We argue that having an explicit ontology of landscapes is important, for aesthetic theories of their appreciation are often attacked in terms of the problems caused by their tacit ontologies. Therefore, we sketch an “Experience Ontology” that serves as an alternative to the ontologies implied in the two best known aesthetic approaches to landscapes. We contend that a landscape should not be conceived of as an object or view but as a way of experiencing one’s surroundings, and we argue that our theory is not only free from the shortcomings of the two dominant theories but that it also corresponds better to everyday intuitions.","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":"75 1","pages":"164-182"},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2020-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48732757","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Human Dignity: Final, Inherent, Absolute? 人的尊严:最终的、内在的、绝对的?
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2020-12-01 DOI: 10.4000/ESTETICA.7319
S. Muders
In the traditional understanding, human dignity is often portrayed as a «final», «inherent», and «absolute» value. If human dignity as the core of the status of a human being did indeed have thos characteristics, this would yield a severe limitation for obligations that stem from the moral status of non-human animals, plants, eco systems and other entities discussed in environmental ethics; for obligations that arise from human dignity standardly take priority over the duties toward entities with non-human moral status. Yet, many theorists of human dignity nowadays have given up the traditional picture in favour of a more «contingent» understanding of human dignity that abandons one or more of its traditional characteristics.In this paper, I argue that to the contrary, we have good reasons to think that the three characteristics of human dignity just mentioned can indeed be attributed to a value that deserves the name «human dignity». In a first part, I argue for a specific understanding of the three value characteristics under consideration. After these preliminaries, I show in a second part that given such an understanding, we have ample evidence that we can indeed say that human dignity is an inherent, absolute and final value; and also that these three characteristics are properties of a single value.
在传统的理解中,人的尊严往往被描绘成一种“最终”、“固有”和“绝对”的价值。如果作为人类地位核心的人类尊严确实具有这些特征,这将严重限制环境伦理学中讨论的非人类动物、植物、生态系统和其他实体的道德地位所产生的义务;对于产生于人类尊严的义务,标准上优先于对具有非人类道德地位的实体的义务。然而,如今许多人的尊严理论家已经放弃了传统的图景,转而对人的尊严进行更“偶然”的理解,放弃了其一个或多个传统特征。在本文中,我认为,恰恰相反,我们有充分的理由认为,刚才提到的人的尊严的三个特征确实可以归因于一种名副其实的价值观“人的尊严”。在第一部分中,我主张对所考虑的三个价值特征有一个具体的理解。在这些初步情况之后,我在第二部分表明,鉴于这样的理解,我们有充分的证据表明,我们确实可以说,人的尊严是一种固有的、绝对的和最终的价值;并且这三个特性是单个值的特性。
{"title":"Human Dignity: Final, Inherent, Absolute?","authors":"S. Muders","doi":"10.4000/ESTETICA.7319","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/ESTETICA.7319","url":null,"abstract":"In the traditional understanding, human dignity is often portrayed as a «final», «inherent», and «absolute» value. If human dignity as the core of the status of a human being did indeed have thos characteristics, this would yield a severe limitation for obligations that stem from the moral status of non-human animals, plants, eco systems and other entities discussed in environmental ethics; for obligations that arise from human dignity standardly take priority over the duties toward entities with non-human moral status. Yet, many theorists of human dignity nowadays have given up the traditional picture in favour of a more «contingent» understanding of human dignity that abandons one or more of its traditional characteristics.In this paper, I argue that to the contrary, we have good reasons to think that the three characteristics of human dignity just mentioned can indeed be attributed to a value that deserves the name «human dignity». In a first part, I argue for a specific understanding of the three value characteristics under consideration. After these preliminaries, I show in a second part that given such an understanding, we have ample evidence that we can indeed say that human dignity is an inherent, absolute and final value; and also that these three characteristics are properties of a single value.","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":"75 1","pages":"84-103"},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2020-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45311750","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Common-surrounding world and qualitative social ontology – phenomenological insights for the environment and its crisis 共同的周围世界和定性的社会本体论——对环境及其危机的现象学见解
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2020-12-01 DOI: 10.4000/ESTETICA.7221
F. Vecchi
I deal with the issue of the environmental crisis from the perspective of a phenomenologically embedded qualitative social ontology. The first point I make is that our environment is a «personal world», and not a «naturalistic world»: a world that is experienced in the «personalistic attitude» and as such is an ontologically qualitative world, in which both natural and social entities are given to us as essentially constituted by value-qualities and meanings, and not as merely material things. The second point I argue for is that our environment is also a «common-surrounding world» whose personal collectives are its essential correlate: «common-surrounding world» and personal collectives existentially depend on one another, and human persons, both individual and collective, are responsible for the existence of their environment and its entities. I apply the tools of phenomenological eidetics to the ideas of «personal world» and «common-surrounding world», and inquire into the ontologically qualitative implications that they have for our environment and its crisis.
我从现象学嵌入的定性社会本体论的角度来处理环境危机问题。我提出的第一点是,我们的环境是一个“个人世界”,而不是一个“自然主义世界”:一个以“个人态度”体验的世界,因此是一个本体论的定性世界,在这个世界中,自然和社会实体本质上都是由价值品质和意义构成的,而不仅仅是物质。我认为的第二点是,我们的环境也是一个“共同的周围世界”,其个人集体是其本质关联:“共同的周边世界”和个人集体在存在上相互依赖,人类,无论是个人还是集体,都对其环境及其实体的存在负责。我将现象学的工具应用于“个人世界”和“共同周围世界”的思想,并探讨它们对我们的环境及其危机的本体论定性影响。
{"title":"Common-surrounding world and qualitative social ontology – phenomenological insights for the environment and its crisis","authors":"F. Vecchi","doi":"10.4000/ESTETICA.7221","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/ESTETICA.7221","url":null,"abstract":"I deal with the issue of the environmental crisis from the perspective of a phenomenologically embedded qualitative social ontology. The first point I make is that our environment is a «personal world», and not a «naturalistic world»: a world that is experienced in the «personalistic attitude» and as such is an ontologically qualitative world, in which both natural and social entities are given to us as essentially constituted by value-qualities and meanings, and not as merely material things. The second point I argue for is that our environment is also a «common-surrounding world» whose personal collectives are its essential correlate: «common-surrounding world» and personal collectives existentially depend on one another, and human persons, both individual and collective, are responsible for the existence of their environment and its entities. I apply the tools of phenomenological eidetics to the ideas of «personal world» and «common-surrounding world», and inquire into the ontologically qualitative implications that they have for our environment and its crisis.","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":"75 1","pages":"33-51"},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2020-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44744973","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Schelling again
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2020-08-01 DOI: 10.4000/estetica.7036
E. Corriero
{"title":"Schelling again","authors":"E. Corriero","doi":"10.4000/estetica.7036","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/estetica.7036","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2020-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41376053","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Consciousness of the Real and the Reality of Consciousnes 现实的意识和意识的现实
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2020-08-01 DOI: 10.4000/ESTETICA.7073
Matteo Vincenzo d’Alfonso
With reference to Schelling’s Philosophy of Mythology (PoM) in my paper I will address three points, namely: To what extent Schelling’s PoM provides us with arguments in favour of 1. Realism, 2. Emergentism and 3. Documentality (Ferraris 2009). Accordingly, in the first section, Reality, I will present Schelling’s PoM as realism, arguing that in mythology Schelling finds the traces of the developing of consciousness, regarded as a real fact. But, as this latter can only be real if having a history, i.e. if emerging from a previous natural status, which is devoid of any consciousness, PoM should be regarded as strongly related with a sort of emergentism. This will thus be the object of the second section, where I will investigate the genetic interpretation of Schelling’s Weltalter proposed by Wolfram Hogrebe (Hogrebe 1989) and suggest that precisely this analysis of the Weltalter explains also why Schelling’s project couldn’t but fail. In fact, against its intention, the Weltalter, as it was trying to explain the rise of semantics together with it the true genesis of the our acknowledgment of the world, still remains affected by an idealistic stance and hence couldn’t succeed in becoming positive philosophy. Eventually, in the third section of this paper, Documentality, I argue, that a solution of the problems left open by Schelling’s Weltalter and positively addressed in the PoM is offered by the interpretation of this latter as a contribution to Documentality. Even if created before and apparently independently from the act writing, in fact mythology relies on the possibility of recording tales, hence it is made of and eventually ends up in a written corpus. This means that the consciousness mythology gives us an account of, is the one that for the first time is able to present itself in narrated tales. It is not the mere possibility of acknowledging something, but in fact the possibility of binding our will to a freely formulated law trough our memory, i.e. the birth of conscience upon consciousness, which is the real sense of religion. In this sense Ferraris’ concept of documentality provides us an important theoretical framework to understand the hidden presuppositions of Schelling’s PoM and to relate this latter to its realistic and emergentistic character.
关于谢林的神话哲学(PoM),我将在我的论文中阐述三点,即:谢林的神话哲学在多大程度上为我们提供了支持1的论据?现实主义,2。紧急情况和3。纪实性(法拉利2009)。因此,在第一节“现实”中,我将把谢林的诗歌作为现实主义呈现出来,认为谢林在神话中发现了意识发展的痕迹,意识被视为一个真实的事实。但是,由于后者只有在有历史的情况下,即从没有任何意识的以前的自然状态中产生出来,才可能是真实的,因此,PoM应该被认为是与一种突现主义密切相关的。因此,这将是第二部分的目标,在那里我将调查Wolfram Hogrebe (Hogrebe 1989)提出的谢林Weltalter的遗传解释,并提出正是这种对Weltalter的分析也解释了为什么谢林的项目不能不失败。事实上,与它的意图相反,当它试图解释语义学的兴起以及我们对世界认识的真正起源时,仍然受到唯心主义立场的影响,因此无法成功地成为实证哲学。最后,在本文的第三部分“文献性”中,我认为,谢林的《Weltalter》留下的、在PoM中得到积极解决的问题的解决方案,是通过对后者的解释作为对文献性的贡献而提供的。即使神话是在行为写作之前创造的,并且表面上独立于行为写作,但实际上神话依赖于记录故事的可能性,因此它是由书面语料库组成的,并最终以书面语料库结束。这意味着,意识神话给我们的描述,是第一次能够在叙述的故事中表现出来的。它不仅是承认某件事的可能性,而且实际上是通过我们的记忆把我们的意志束缚在自由制定的法则上的可能性,也就是说,良心在意识的基础上诞生,这就是真正意义上的宗教。在这个意义上,法拉利的文献性概念为我们提供了一个重要的理论框架来理解谢林PoM的隐含前提,并将后者与它的现实主义和突发性特征联系起来。
{"title":"The Consciousness of the Real and the Reality of Consciousnes","authors":"Matteo Vincenzo d’Alfonso","doi":"10.4000/ESTETICA.7073","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/ESTETICA.7073","url":null,"abstract":"With reference to Schelling’s Philosophy of Mythology (PoM) in my paper I will address three points, namely: To what extent Schelling’s PoM provides us with arguments in favour of 1. Realism, 2. Emergentism and 3. Documentality (Ferraris 2009). Accordingly, in the first section, Reality, I will present Schelling’s PoM as realism, arguing that in mythology Schelling finds the traces of the developing of consciousness, regarded as a real fact. But, as this latter can only be real if having a history, i.e. if emerging from a previous natural status, which is devoid of any consciousness, PoM should be regarded as strongly related with a sort of emergentism. This will thus be the object of the second section, where I will investigate the genetic interpretation of Schelling’s Weltalter proposed by Wolfram Hogrebe (Hogrebe 1989) and suggest that precisely this analysis of the Weltalter explains also why Schelling’s project couldn’t but fail. In fact, against its intention, the Weltalter, as it was trying to explain the rise of semantics together with it the true genesis of the our acknowledgment of the world, still remains affected by an idealistic stance and hence couldn’t succeed in becoming positive philosophy. Eventually, in the third section of this paper, Documentality, I argue, that a solution of the problems left open by Schelling’s Weltalter and positively addressed in the PoM is offered by the interpretation of this latter as a contribution to Documentality. Even if created before and apparently independently from the act writing, in fact mythology relies on the possibility of recording tales, hence it is made of and eventually ends up in a written corpus. This means that the consciousness mythology gives us an account of, is the one that for the first time is able to present itself in narrated tales. It is not the mere possibility of acknowledging something, but in fact the possibility of binding our will to a freely formulated law trough our memory, i.e. the birth of conscience upon consciousness, which is the real sense of religion. In this sense Ferraris’ concept of documentality provides us an important theoretical framework to understand the hidden presuppositions of Schelling’s PoM and to relate this latter to its realistic and emergentistic character.","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":"74 1","pages":"91-105"},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2020-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43911853","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Aesthetical Ontology, Ontological Aesthetics: Rethinking Art and Beauty through Speculative Realism 审美本体论、本体论美学:从思辨现实主义看艺术与美
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2020-08-01 DOI: 10.4000/ESTETICA.7115
Mario Ramirez
We thus propose to criticize the subjective-anthropological conception of beauty and to define the meaning of an ontological conception of the beautiful while at the same time inquiring into an aesthetic conception of ontology from the standpoint of speculative realism. We discuss first the general character of Kantian aesthetics, considered as the founding moment of modern aesthetic subjectivism. The first section reviews Gadamer’s criticisms of Kantianism before exposing, in the second section, the reinterpretation made by some neorealist thinkers (Shaviro, Harman) of the Kantian conception of art and beauty and, more generally, of the meaning of aesthetics at large. Through this line of inquiry the third section exposes an aesthetic interpretation of the ‘principle of unreason’ introduced by Quentin Meillassoux. By way of conclusion, the fourth section examines the philosophical meaning of art and the general aims of an ontological aesthetic.
因此,我们建议批判人类学的主观美观,界定美的本体论概念的含义,同时从思辨现实主义的角度探讨美的本体观。我们首先讨论了康德美学的一般特征,它被认为是现代美学主观主义的奠基时刻。第一节回顾了伽达默尔对康德主义的批评,然后在第二节中揭示了一些新现实主义思想家(沙维罗、哈曼)对康德艺术和美的概念以及更普遍的美学意义的重新解释。第三部分通过这一思路,揭示了昆汀·梅拉索对“非理性原则”的美学阐释。第四部分通过结语的方式,考察艺术的哲学意义和本体论美学的总体目标。
{"title":"Aesthetical Ontology, Ontological Aesthetics: Rethinking Art and Beauty through Speculative Realism","authors":"Mario Ramirez","doi":"10.4000/ESTETICA.7115","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/ESTETICA.7115","url":null,"abstract":"We thus propose to criticize the subjective-anthropological conception of beauty and to define the meaning of an ontological conception of the beautiful while at the same time inquiring into an aesthetic conception of ontology from the standpoint of speculative realism. We discuss first the general character of Kantian aesthetics, considered as the founding moment of modern aesthetic subjectivism. The first section reviews Gadamer’s criticisms of Kantianism before exposing, in the second section, the reinterpretation made by some neorealist thinkers (Shaviro, Harman) of the Kantian conception of art and beauty and, more generally, of the meaning of aesthetics at large. Through this line of inquiry the third section exposes an aesthetic interpretation of the ‘principle of unreason’ introduced by Quentin Meillassoux. By way of conclusion, the fourth section examines the philosophical meaning of art and the general aims of an ontological aesthetic.","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":"74 1","pages":"201-216"},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2020-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48775996","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Realism of Purposes: Schelling and Hegel on Kant’s Critique of Teleological Judgement 目的的实在论:谢林与黑格尔论康德的目的判断批判
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2020-08-01 DOI: 10.4000/ESTETICA.7080
Luca Illetterati, A. Gambarotto
The paper addresses Schelling’s and Hegel’s interpretation of Kant’s Critique of the Power of Judgement (1790), focusing especially on the so-called ‘problem of teleology.’ We reconstruct Schelling’s and Hegel’s reading of the second part of the Critique, dedicated to ‘teleological judgement’ and the question of natural purposiveness. We first propose a brief reconstruction of Kant’s argument about the possibility of using teleological judgment with reference to nature; we then show why Hegel and Schelling were unsatisfied with Kant’s argument; Finally, we argue that Schelling’s and Hegel’s dissatisfaction with the Kantian theory of teleological judgement led them to move beyond Kant, towards a different understanding of the relation between epistemology and ontology.
本文讨论了谢林和黑格尔对康德《判断力批判》(1790)的解释,特别关注所谓的“目的论问题”。我们重建谢林和黑格尔对《批判》第二部分的解读,致力于“目的论判断”和自然合意性的问题。我们首先对康德关于在自然中使用目的论判断的可能性的论证进行简要的重建;然后我们说明为什么黑格尔和谢林不满意康德的论点;最后,我们认为谢林和黑格尔对康德的目的论判断理论的不满导致他们超越康德,走向对认识论和本体论之间关系的不同理解。
{"title":"The Realism of Purposes: Schelling and Hegel on Kant’s Critique of Teleological Judgement","authors":"Luca Illetterati, A. Gambarotto","doi":"10.4000/ESTETICA.7080","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/ESTETICA.7080","url":null,"abstract":"The paper addresses Schelling’s and Hegel’s interpretation of Kant’s Critique of the Power of Judgement (1790), focusing especially on the so-called ‘problem of teleology.’ We reconstruct Schelling’s and Hegel’s reading of the second part of the Critique, dedicated to ‘teleological judgement’ and the question of natural purposiveness. We first propose a brief reconstruction of Kant’s argument about the possibility of using teleological judgment with reference to nature; we then show why Hegel and Schelling were unsatisfied with Kant’s argument; Finally, we argue that Schelling’s and Hegel’s dissatisfaction with the Kantian theory of teleological judgement led them to move beyond Kant, towards a different understanding of the relation between epistemology and ontology.","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":"74 1","pages":"106-118"},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2020-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"70154568","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
«All the principles of being and becoming»: Schelling’s ontogenetic hypothesis “存在与生成的所有原则”:谢林的个体发生假说
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2020-08-01 DOI: 10.4000/ESTETICA.7056
I. Grant
Schelling’s Naturphilosophie was, from the outset, more concerned with ontogeny than ontology, i.e. not on what nature is but on what it does: ubiquitous creation. Therefore, the processes articulated in the Philosophy of Mythology remain instances of a philosophy driven by what might be called a post-naturalist naturalism. The two aims of this paper are, firstly, to demonstrate this nature-philosophical continuity throughout Schelling’s so-called Protean philosophical projects in order, secondly, to re-prepare Schellingian themes for current debates concerning ontology. To this end, I draw on the worldmaking and abundance postulates of Goodman and Feyerabend, respectively, to demonstrate the persistence of Schellingian ontogenetic pathways for remodelling process metaphysics for contemporary philosophy. Finally, the paper argues that the logical form of the hypothesis (antecedent and consequent) is itself consequent upon the ontogeny it hypothesises.
谢林的自然哲学从一开始就更关注个体发生,而不是本体论,即不是关于自然是什么,而是关于它的作用:无处不在的创造。因此,神话哲学中阐述的过程仍然是由所谓的后自然主义驱动的哲学的实例。本文的两个目的是,首先,在谢林所谓的Protean哲学项目中展示这种性质的哲学连续性,以便为当前关于本体论的辩论重新准备谢林的主题。为此,我分别借鉴古德曼和费耶拉本德的造世界和富足假设,来证明舍林个体发生路径的持久性,以重塑当代哲学的过程形而上学。最后,本文认为,假设的逻辑形式(前提和后果)本身就是它所假设的个体发生的结果。
{"title":"«All the principles of being and becoming»: Schelling’s ontogenetic hypothesis","authors":"I. Grant","doi":"10.4000/ESTETICA.7056","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/ESTETICA.7056","url":null,"abstract":"Schelling’s Naturphilosophie was, from the outset, more concerned with ontogeny than ontology, i.e. not on what nature is but on what it does: ubiquitous creation. Therefore, the processes articulated in the Philosophy of Mythology remain instances of a philosophy driven by what might be called a post-naturalist naturalism. The two aims of this paper are, firstly, to demonstrate this nature-philosophical continuity throughout Schelling’s so-called Protean philosophical projects in order, secondly, to re-prepare Schellingian themes for current debates concerning ontology. To this end, I draw on the worldmaking and abundance postulates of Goodman and Feyerabend, respectively, to demonstrate the persistence of Schellingian ontogenetic pathways for remodelling process metaphysics for contemporary philosophy. Finally, the paper argues that the logical form of the hypothesis (antecedent and consequent) is itself consequent upon the ontogeny it hypothesises.","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":"74 1","pages":"22-38"},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2020-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45024053","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Preformation vs. Epigenesis: Inspiration and Haunting Within and Outside Contemporary Philosophy of Biology 预形成与后生:当代生物学哲学内外的启示与困扰
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2020-08-01 DOI: 10.4000/ESTETICA.7088
Elena Casetta
The 17th and 18th centuries were the theatre of the fight between two main theories concerning the development of organisms: preformationism (or preformism) and epigeneticism (or epigenesis). According to the first, the formation of new features during organisms’ development can be seen as the result of a mere unfolding of features that were preformed in the sperm, the egg, or the zygote. According to epigeneticism, there is no pre-existing form, and development is a process where genuinely new characters emerge from formless matter. The debate involved naturalists, anatomists, physiologists, microscopists, medical doctors, and philosophers as well. Current developmental biology is, according to some, still inspired (or haunted) by the age-old controversy. The aim of this contribution is twofold. First, to discuss in which guise, if any, the old controversy is still shaping the contemporary debate in biology and philosophy of biology; and, second, to sketch Schelling’s position on that debate, suggesting that it may contain some still valuable philosophical insight.
17世纪和18世纪是关于生物体发展的两种主要理论之间的斗争舞台:预形成论(或预形成论)和表观遗传学(或表观遗传学)。根据第一种观点,生物体发育过程中新特征的形成可以被视为精子、卵子或受精卵中预先形成的特征的展开结果。根据表观遗传学,不存在预先存在的形式,发展是一个从无形物质中产生真正新特征的过程。这场争论涉及博物学家、解剖学家、生理学家、显微镜学家、医生和哲学家。根据一些人的说法,目前的发育生物学仍然受到这一古老争议的启发(或困扰)。这一贡献的目的是双重的。首先,讨论旧的争论以何种形式(如果有的话)仍在塑造当代生物学和生物学哲学的争论;其次,勾勒出谢林对这场辩论的立场,表明它可能包含一些仍然有价值的哲学见解。
{"title":"Preformation vs. Epigenesis: Inspiration and Haunting Within and Outside Contemporary Philosophy of Biology","authors":"Elena Casetta","doi":"10.4000/ESTETICA.7088","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/ESTETICA.7088","url":null,"abstract":"The 17th and 18th centuries were the theatre of the fight between two main theories concerning the development of organisms: preformationism (or preformism) and epigeneticism (or epigenesis). According to the first, the formation of new features during organisms’ development can be seen as the result of a mere unfolding of features that were preformed in the sperm, the egg, or the zygote. According to epigeneticism, there is no pre-existing form, and development is a process where genuinely new characters emerge from formless matter. The debate involved naturalists, anatomists, physiologists, microscopists, medical doctors, and philosophers as well. Current developmental biology is, according to some, still inspired (or haunted) by the age-old controversy. The aim of this contribution is twofold. First, to discuss in which guise, if any, the old controversy is still shaping the contemporary debate in biology and philosophy of biology; and, second, to sketch Schelling’s position on that debate, suggesting that it may contain some still valuable philosophical insight.","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":"74 1","pages":"119-138"},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2020-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45194688","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Beyond the Process After Schelling. Freedom and Creativity 超越谢林之后的过程。自由与创造力
IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2020-08-01 DOI: 10.4000/ESTETICA.7066
E. Corriero
Schelling’s philosophy can be seen as a unitary project of dynamic philosophy in which the philosophy of nature is the theoretical core within a general frame of a philosophy of identity. According to this assumption, that is developed and argued in the first section, this essay shows moreover as Schelling’s philosophy is a sort of process philosophy capable of integrating the standard definition of it, given for example by Nicholas Rescher, introducing the ‘necessary’ ungroundedness of being which frees ‘actions’ and ‘creativity’ from the necessary chain of the process of nature. Thus described, the process indeed guaranties in particular that freedom that must be at the basis of moral action, seen by Schelling as that action capable of reactivating and freely reproducing that ‘love’ that guides Copula (the bond of the bonds) in its original and steady movement towards the concretedness of what exists.
谢林的哲学可以看作是动态哲学的一个统一项目,其中自然哲学是同一性哲学一般框架内的理论核心。根据这一假设,即在第一节中发展和论证的假设,本文进一步表明,谢林的哲学是一种过程哲学,能够整合尼古拉斯·雷舍尔(Nicholas Rescher)给出的标准定义,引入存在的“必要”无根据性,将“行动”和“创造力”从自然过程的必要链中解放出来。如此描述,这一过程确实特别保证了自由,这必须是道德行动的基础,被谢林视为能够重新激活和自由复制“爱”的行动,这种“爱”引导着Copula(纽带的纽带)在其原始和稳定的运动中走向存在的具体性。
{"title":"Beyond the Process After Schelling. Freedom and Creativity","authors":"E. Corriero","doi":"10.4000/ESTETICA.7066","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4000/ESTETICA.7066","url":null,"abstract":"Schelling’s philosophy can be seen as a unitary project of dynamic philosophy in which the philosophy of nature is the theoretical core within a general frame of a philosophy of identity. According to this assumption, that is developed and argued in the first section, this essay shows moreover as Schelling’s philosophy is a sort of process philosophy capable of integrating the standard definition of it, given for example by Nicholas Rescher, introducing the ‘necessary’ ungroundedness of being which frees ‘actions’ and ‘creativity’ from the necessary chain of the process of nature. Thus described, the process indeed guaranties in particular that freedom that must be at the basis of moral action, seen by Schelling as that action capable of reactivating and freely reproducing that ‘love’ that guides Copula (the bond of the bonds) in its original and steady movement towards the concretedness of what exists.","PeriodicalId":53954,"journal":{"name":"Rivista di Estetica","volume":"74 1","pages":"39-59"},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2020-08-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45199736","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Rivista di Estetica
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1