首页 > 最新文献

Philosophia (Ramat-Gan, Israel)最新文献

英文 中文
Sufficient Reasons to Act Wrongly: Making Parfit's Kantian Contractualist Formula Consistent with Reasons. 错误行为的充分理由:使帕菲特的康德契约主义公式与理由一致。
Pub Date : 2017-01-01 Epub Date: 2016-09-23 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-016-9766-z
Mattias Gunnemyr

In On What Matters (2011) Derek Parfit advocates the Kantian Contractualist Formula as one of three supreme moral principles. In important cases, this formula entails that it is wrong for an agent to act in a way that would be partially best. In contrast, Parfit's wide value-based objective view of reasons entails that the agent often have sufficient reasons to perform such acts. It seems then that agents might have sufficient reasons to act wrongly. In this paper I will argue that such reasons are a symptom of a fundamental inconsistency between the Kantian Contractualist Formula and Parfit's view of reasons. The formula requires that we consider what everyone could rationally will, while a wide value-based objective view requires that we consider only what the agent has sufficient reasons for doing. The same inconsistency is particularly obvious in Parfit's version of the Consent Principle, which share important features with the Kantian Contractualist Formula. Parfit accepts that moral principles might entail that we sometimes have sufficient reasons to act wrongly. However, to accept that supreme moral principles have such implications is objectionable if you, like Parfit, also hold that principles with such implications should be rejected or revised. I suggest that we could abandon the requirement that we have to consider the reasons of everyone. This would make the Kantian Contractualist Formula consistent with Parfit's view of reasons, at least in this respect. I also argue that we can keep most implications of the Kantian Contractualist Formula that Parfit finds attractive.

在《论何为重要》(2011)一书中,德里克·帕菲特(Derek Parfit)主张康德契约主义公式是三大最高道德原则之一。在一些重要的情况下,这个公式意味着,一个行为人以部分最佳的方式行事是错误的。相比之下,帕菲特宽泛的基于价值的客观理性观点要求行为人通常有足够的理由来实施此类行为。这样看来,代理人可能有足够的理由做出错误的行为。在本文中,我将论证,这些理由是康德契约主义公式与帕菲特的理由观之间根本不一致的症状。这个公式要求我们考虑每个人的理性意愿,而基于广泛价值的客观观点则要求我们只考虑行为人有充分理由去做的事情。同样的不一致在帕菲特版本的同意原则中尤为明显,它与康德的契约主义公式具有重要的特征。帕菲特承认,道德原则可能意味着我们有时有足够的理由做出错误的行为。然而,如果你像帕菲特一样,也认为具有这种含义的原则应该被拒绝或修改,那么接受最高道德原则具有这种含义是令人反感的。我建议我们可以放弃我们必须考虑每个人的理由的要求。这将使康德的契约主义公式与帕菲特的理性观点相一致,至少在这方面是这样。我还认为,我们可以保留帕菲特认为有吸引力的康德契约主义公式的大部分含义。
{"title":"Sufficient Reasons to Act Wrongly: Making Parfit's Kantian Contractualist Formula Consistent with Reasons.","authors":"Mattias Gunnemyr","doi":"10.1007/s11406-016-9766-z","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-016-9766-z","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>In <i>On What Matters</i> (2011) Derek Parfit advocates the Kantian Contractualist Formula as one of three supreme moral principles. In important cases, this formula entails that it is wrong for an agent to act in a way that would be partially best. In contrast, Parfit's wide value-based objective view of reasons entails that the agent often have sufficient reasons to perform such acts. It seems then that agents might have sufficient reasons to act wrongly. In this paper I will argue that such reasons are a symptom of a fundamental inconsistency between the Kantian Contractualist Formula and Parfit's view of reasons. The formula requires that we consider what <i>everyone</i> could rationally will, while a wide value-based objective view requires that we consider only what <i>the agent</i> has sufficient reasons for doing. The same inconsistency is particularly obvious in Parfit's version of the Consent Principle, which share important features with the Kantian Contractualist Formula. Parfit accepts that moral principles might entail that we sometimes have sufficient reasons to act wrongly. However, to accept that supreme moral principles have such implications is objectionable if you, like Parfit, also hold that principles with such implications should be rejected or revised. I suggest that we could abandon the requirement that we have to consider the reasons of everyone. This would make the Kantian Contractualist Formula consistent with Parfit's view of reasons, at least in this respect. I also argue that we can keep most implications of the Kantian Contractualist Formula that Parfit finds attractive.</p>","PeriodicalId":74436,"journal":{"name":"Philosophia (Ramat-Gan, Israel)","volume":"45 1","pages":"227-246"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s11406-016-9766-z","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"36429112","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Sensitivity has Multiple Heterogeneity Problems: a Reply to Wallbridge. 敏感性具有多重异质性问题:对Wallbridge的回应。
Pub Date : 2017-01-01 Epub Date: 2017-07-11 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-017-9873-5
Guido Melchior

In this paper, I defend the heterogeneity problem for sensitivity accounts of knowledge against an objection that has been recently proposed by Wallbridge in Philosophia (2016b). I argue in (Melchior in Episteme, 12(4), 479-496, 2015) that sensitivity accounts of knowledge face a heterogeneity problem when it comes to higher-level knowledge about the truth of one's own beliefs. Beliefs in weaker higher-level propositions are insensitive, but beliefs in stronger higher-level propositions are sensitive. The resulting picture that we can know the stronger propositions without being in a position to know the weaker propositions is too heterogeneous to be plausible. Wallbridge objects that there is no heterogeneity problem because beliefs in the weaker higher-level propositions are also sensitive. I argue against Wallbridge that the heterogeneity problem is not solved but only displaced. Only some beliefs in the weaker higher-level propositions are sensitive. I conclude that the heterogeneity problem is one of a family of instability problems that sensitivity accounts of knowledge face and that Wallbridge's account raises a further problem of this kind.

在这篇论文中,我为知识敏感性解释的异质性问题辩护,反对Wallbridge最近在《哲学》(2016b)中提出的反对意见。我在(Melchior in Episteme,12(4),479-4962015)中认为,当涉及到关于自己信仰真理的更高层次知识时,知识的敏感性账户面临着异质性问题。对较弱的更高层次命题的信念是不敏感的,但对较强的更高层级命题的信念则是敏感的。由此产生的画面是,我们可以知道更强的命题,而不必知道较弱的命题,这太不均匀了,不可能是可信的。Wallbridge反对不存在异质性问题,因为对较弱的高级命题的信念也是敏感的。我反对Wallbridge的观点,即异质性问题没有得到解决,只是被取代了。只有在较弱的更高层次命题中的一些信念是敏感的。我的结论是,异质性问题是知识的敏感性账户所面临的一系列不稳定问题之一,而Wallbridge的账户提出了另一个此类问题。
{"title":"Sensitivity has Multiple Heterogeneity Problems: a Reply to Wallbridge.","authors":"Guido Melchior","doi":"10.1007/s11406-017-9873-5","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s11406-017-9873-5","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>In this paper, I defend the heterogeneity problem for sensitivity accounts of knowledge against an objection that has been recently proposed by Wallbridge in <i>Philosophia</i> (2016b). I argue in (Melchior in <i>Episteme</i>, <i>12</i>(4), 479-496, 2015) that sensitivity accounts of knowledge face a heterogeneity problem when it comes to higher-level knowledge about the truth of one's own beliefs. Beliefs in weaker higher-level propositions are insensitive, but beliefs in stronger higher-level propositions are sensitive. The resulting picture that we can know the stronger propositions without being in a position to know the weaker propositions is too heterogeneous to be plausible. Wallbridge objects that there is no heterogeneity problem because beliefs in the weaker higher-level propositions are also sensitive. I argue against Wallbridge that the heterogeneity problem is not solved but only displaced. Only some beliefs in the weaker higher-level propositions are sensitive. I conclude that the heterogeneity problem is one of a family of instability problems that sensitivity accounts of knowledge face and that Wallbridge's account raises a further problem of this kind.</p>","PeriodicalId":74436,"journal":{"name":"Philosophia (Ramat-Gan, Israel)","volume":"45 4","pages":"1741-1747"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s11406-017-9873-5","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"36431382","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 7
A Short Comment on Michael Slote, "The Many Faces of Empathy". 对Michael Slote的《移情的多重面》的简短评论。
Pub Date : 2017-01-01 Epub Date: 2016-04-30 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-016-9717-8
R Zaborowski

ᅟThe comment discusses M. Slote's view on empathy as presented in his paper "The Many Faces of Empathy". It is asked whether three forms of empathy he portrays are three separable concepts or three variants of the same concept of empathy.

ᅟ评论讨论了M. Slote在他的论文“The Many Faces of empathy”中提出的关于同理心的观点。他所描述的三种共情形式是三个可分离的概念,还是同一个共情概念的三个变体。
{"title":"A Short Comment on Michael Slote, \"The Many Faces of Empathy\".","authors":"R Zaborowski","doi":"10.1007/s11406-016-9717-8","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-016-9717-8","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>ᅟThe comment discusses M. Slote's view on empathy as presented in his paper \"The Many Faces of Empathy\". It is asked whether three forms of empathy he portrays are three separable concepts or three variants of the same concept of empathy.</p>","PeriodicalId":74436,"journal":{"name":"Philosophia (Ramat-Gan, Israel)","volume":"45 3","pages":"857-859"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s11406-016-9717-8","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"36432028","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Intuition-Talk: Virus or Virtue? 直觉对话:病毒还是美德?
Pub Date : 2017-01-01 Epub Date: 2017-01-22 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-016-9796-6
James Andow

The word 'intuition' is used frequently both in philosophy and in discussions about philosophical methods. It has been argued that this intuition-talk makes no (clear) semantic contribution and that intuition-talk is thus a bad habit that ought to be abandoned. I urge caution in making this inference. There are many pragmatic roles intuition-talk might play. Moreover, according to one plausible story (for which there is some empirical support), there is reason to think intuition-talk is actually a good habit for philosophers to have.

“直觉”这个词在哲学和关于哲学方法的讨论中都经常使用。有人认为,这种直觉对话没有(明确的)语义贡献,因此直觉对话是一种应该放弃的坏习惯。我敦促大家在作出这种推论时要谨慎。直觉对话可能扮演许多实用主义角色。此外,根据一个貌似合理的故事(有一些经验支持),有理由认为直觉对话实际上是哲学家的一个好习惯。
{"title":"Intuition-Talk: Virus or Virtue?","authors":"James Andow","doi":"10.1007/s11406-016-9796-6","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-016-9796-6","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>The word 'intuition' is used frequently both in philosophy and in discussions about philosophical methods. It has been argued that this intuition-talk makes no (clear) semantic contribution and that intuition-talk is thus a bad habit that ought to be abandoned. I urge caution in making this inference. There are many pragmatic roles intuition-talk might play. Moreover, according to one plausible story (for which there is some empirical support), there is reason to think intuition-talk is actually a good habit for philosophers to have.</p>","PeriodicalId":74436,"journal":{"name":"Philosophia (Ramat-Gan, Israel)","volume":"45 2","pages":"523-531"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s11406-016-9796-6","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"36431583","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Transgressions Are Equal, and Right Actions Are Equal: some Philosophical Reflections on Paradox III in Cicero's Paradoxa Stoicorum. 越界是平等的,正确的行为是平等的:对西塞罗《斯多葛论》悖论三的哲学思考。
Pub Date : 2017-01-01 Epub Date: 2016-10-05 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-016-9761-4
Daniel Rönnedal

In Paradoxa Stoicorum, the Roman philosopher Cicero defends six important Stoic theses. Since these theses seem counterintuitive, and it is not likely that the average person would agree with them, they were generally called "paradoxes". According to the third paradox, (P3), (all) transgressions (wrong actions) are equal and (all) right actions are equal. According to one interpretation of this principle, which I will call (P3'), it means that if it is forbidden that A and it is forbidden that B, then not-A is as good as not-B; and if it is permitted that A and it is permitted that B, then A is as good as B. In this paper, I show how it is possible to prove this thesis in dyadic deontic logic. I also try to defend (P3') against some philosophical counterarguments. Furthermore, I address the claim that (P3') is not a correct interpretation of Cicero's third paradox and the assertion that it does not matter whether (P3') is true or not. I argue that it does matter whether (P3') is true or not, but acknowledge that (P3') is perhaps a slightly different principle than Cicero's thesis. The upshot is that (P3') seems to be a plausible principle, and that at least one part of paradox III in Cicero's Paradoxa Stoicorum appears to be defensible.

在《斯多葛的悖论》一书中,罗马哲学家西塞罗为斯多葛学派的六个重要论点进行了辩护。由于这些论点似乎违反直觉,而且一般人也不太可能同意,因此它们通常被称为“悖论”。根据第三个悖论(P3),(所有)违法行为(错误行为)是平等的,(所有)正确行为是平等的。根据对这一原则的一种解释,我称之为P3',它意味着如果A和B都被禁止,那么非A和非B一样好;如果允许A和允许B,那么A就和B一样好。在本文中,我展示了如何在二进道义逻辑中证明这个命题。我也试图为(P3)辩护,反对一些哲学上的反驳。此外,我提出(P3')不是对西塞罗第三个悖论的正确解释,以及(P3')是否为真无关紧要的主张。我认为(P3')是否正确很重要,但我承认,(P3')的原则可能与西塞罗的论点略有不同。结论是(P3')似乎是一个合理的原则,至少西塞罗的悖论III的一部分似乎是可以辩护的。
{"title":"Transgressions Are Equal, and Right Actions Are Equal: some Philosophical Reflections on Paradox III in Cicero's <i>Paradoxa Stoicorum</i>.","authors":"Daniel Rönnedal","doi":"10.1007/s11406-016-9761-4","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-016-9761-4","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>In <i>Paradoxa Stoicorum</i>, the Roman philosopher Cicero defends six important Stoic theses. Since these theses seem counterintuitive, and it is not likely that the average person would agree with them, they were generally called \"paradoxes\". According to the third paradox, (P3), (all) transgressions (wrong actions) are equal and (all) right actions are equal. According to one interpretation of this principle, which I will call (P3'), it means that if it is forbidden that A and it is forbidden that B, then not-A is as good as not-B; and if it is permitted that A and it is permitted that B, then A is as good as B. In this paper, I show how it is possible to prove this thesis in dyadic deontic logic. I also try to defend (P3') against some philosophical counterarguments. Furthermore, I address the claim that (P3') is not a correct interpretation of Cicero's third paradox and the assertion that it does not matter whether (P3') is true or not. I argue that it does matter whether (P3') is true or not, but acknowledge that (P3') is perhaps a slightly different principle than Cicero's thesis. The upshot is that (P3') seems to be a plausible principle, and that at least one part of paradox III in Cicero's <i>Paradoxa Stoicorum</i> appears to be defensible.</p>","PeriodicalId":74436,"journal":{"name":"Philosophia (Ramat-Gan, Israel)","volume":"45 1","pages":"317-334"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s11406-016-9761-4","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"36429113","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Why bad Moods Matter. William James on Melancholy, Mystic Emotion, and the Meaning of Life. 为什么坏心情很重要。威廉·詹姆斯论忧郁、神秘的情感和生命的意义。
Pub Date : 2017-01-01 Epub Date: 2017-05-09 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-017-9842-z
Heleen Pott

William James's reputation in the field of emotion research is based on his early psychological writings where he defines emotions as 'feelings of bodily changes'. In his later work, particularly in his study of mystic emotion (1902), James comes up with what looks like a completely different approach. Here his focus is on positive feelings of inspiration and joy, but also on downbeat moods like melancholy and depression. He examines how these feeling states give meaning to an individual's life. Theorists often speculate about a gap between James's early writings and his later work, and assume that the later James turned from an evolutionary-minded natural scientist into a metaphysical philosopher. In my paper, I follow Ratcliffe (2008) in his view that a sharply drawn line between the early and the late work is implausible and that James's later study of mysticism fits nicely with his early psychology. Drawing on James (1902), I show how in his later work, James develops a theory of embodied emotions that anticipates the role ascribed by twentieth century phenomenology to anxiety and other 'bad moods', as possibilities for philosophical reflection and self-understanding.

威廉·詹姆斯在情感研究领域的声誉是基于他早期的心理学著作,他将情感定义为“身体变化的感觉”。在他后来的作品中,特别是在他对神秘情感的研究中(1902),詹姆斯提出了一种看起来完全不同的方法。在这本书中,他关注的是鼓舞和喜悦的积极情绪,但也关注忧郁和抑郁等悲观情绪。他研究了这些情感状态是如何赋予个人生活意义的。理论家们经常推测詹姆斯的早期作品和后期作品之间存在差距,并假设詹姆斯从一个有进化论思想的自然科学家变成了一个形而上学的哲学家。在我的论文中,我遵循拉特克利夫(2008)的观点,即在早期和晚期作品之间划清界限是不可信的,詹姆斯后来对神秘主义的研究与他早期的心理学非常吻合。在詹姆斯(1902)的基础上,我展示了詹姆斯如何在他的后期作品中发展了一种具身情绪理论,该理论预测了20世纪现象学所赋予的焦虑和其他“坏情绪”的角色,作为哲学反思和自我理解的可能性。
{"title":"Why bad Moods Matter. William James on Melancholy, Mystic Emotion, and the Meaning of Life.","authors":"Heleen Pott","doi":"10.1007/s11406-017-9842-z","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-017-9842-z","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>William James's reputation in the field of emotion research is based on his early psychological writings where he defines emotions as 'feelings of bodily changes'. In his later work, particularly in his study of mystic emotion (1902), James comes up with what looks like a completely different approach. Here his focus is on positive feelings of inspiration and joy, but also on downbeat moods like melancholy and depression. He examines how these feeling states give meaning to an individual's life. Theorists often speculate about a gap between James's early writings and his later work, and assume that the later James turned from an evolutionary-minded natural scientist into a metaphysical philosopher. In my paper, I follow Ratcliffe (2008) in his view that a sharply drawn line between the early and the late work is implausible and that James's later study of mysticism fits nicely with his early psychology. Drawing on James (1902), I show how in his later work, James develops a theory of embodied emotions that anticipates the role ascribed by twentieth century phenomenology to anxiety and other 'bad moods', as possibilities for philosophical reflection and self-understanding.</p>","PeriodicalId":74436,"journal":{"name":"Philosophia (Ramat-Gan, Israel)","volume":"45 4","pages":"1635-1645"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s11406-017-9842-z","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"36430936","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Toleration and Pragmatism: Themes from The Work of John Horton. 宽容与实用主义:约翰·霍顿作品的主题。
Pub Date : 2017-01-01 Epub Date: 2016-11-05 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-016-9767-y
Sorin Baiasu

John Horton's work has been particularly influential in debates on specific topics related to toleration, political obligation, modus vivendi and political realism. More recently, he has synthesised these views in the form of a distinctive position in political philosophy, a position that has the potential to question much of the received wisdom in the field. The papers of this special issue engage with some of the most fundamental issues of Horton's account, more exactly, the related issues of toleration and modus vivendi, Horton's account of associative obligations, with a focus on the methodological assumptions which underpin his position more generally, and the metaphysical presuppositions of his account, in particular, the presupposition of contingency. I offer brief presentations of the papers in the special issue and of the ways they link with each other. In the discussion of the papers by Forst, Newey, Jones, Weale and Mendus, the emphasis will be on those arguments which question Horton's position. Horton's paper will then be presented with a focus on possible responses to these challenges. I will conclude with several remarks on an unexpected continuity between Horton's realist view and a view realists usually criticise as idealising, namely, John Rawls's theory of justice as fairness.

约翰·霍顿的著作在与宽容、政治义务、权宜之计和政治现实主义有关的特定主题的辩论中尤其有影响力。最近,他以一种独特的政治哲学立场的形式综合了这些观点,这种立场有可能对该领域的许多公认智慧提出质疑。本期特刊的论文涉及了霍顿论述中一些最基本的问题,更确切地说,是与宽容和暂时方式相关的问题,霍顿对联想义务的论述,重点关注支撑他的立场的方法论假设,以及他的论述的形而上学前提,特别是偶然性的前提。我将简要介绍特刊上的论文以及它们相互联系的方式。在对福斯特、纽维、琼斯、威尔和门杜斯的论文的讨论中,重点将放在那些质疑霍顿立场的论点上。然后,霍顿的论文将重点介绍应对这些挑战的可能方法。最后,我将对霍顿的现实主义观点和现实主义者通常批评为理想化的观点,即约翰·罗尔斯的正义作为公平的理论之间意想不到的连续性进行评论。
{"title":"Toleration and Pragmatism: Themes from The Work of John Horton.","authors":"Sorin Baiasu","doi":"10.1007/s11406-016-9767-y","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-016-9767-y","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>John Horton's work has been particularly influential in debates on specific topics related to toleration, political obligation, modus vivendi and political realism. More recently, he has synthesised these views in the form of a distinctive position in political philosophy, a position that has the potential to question much of the received wisdom in the field. The papers of this special issue engage with some of the most fundamental issues of Horton's account, more exactly, the related issues of toleration and modus vivendi, Horton's account of associative obligations, with a focus on the methodological assumptions which underpin his position more generally, and the metaphysical presuppositions of his account, in particular, the presupposition of contingency. I offer brief presentations of the papers in the special issue and of the ways they link with each other. In the discussion of the papers by Forst, Newey, Jones, Weale and Mendus, the emphasis will be on those arguments which question Horton's position. Horton's paper will then be presented with a focus on possible responses to these challenges. I will conclude with several remarks on an unexpected continuity between Horton's realist view and a view realists usually criticise as idealising, namely, John Rawls's theory of justice as fairness.</p>","PeriodicalId":74436,"journal":{"name":"Philosophia (Ramat-Gan, Israel)","volume":"45 2","pages":"397-413"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s11406-016-9767-y","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"36431577","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Sensitivity hasn't got a Heterogeneity Problem - a Reply to Melchior. 敏感性没有异质性问题——对Melchior的回复。
Pub Date : 2017-01-01 Epub Date: 2016-11-14 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-016-9782-z
Kevin Wallbridge

In a recent paper, Melchior pursues a novel argumentative strategy against the sensitivity condition. His claim is that sensitivity suffers from a 'heterogeneity problem:' although some higher-order beliefs are knowable, other, very similar, higher-order beliefs are insensitive and so not knowable. Similarly, the conclusions of some bootstrapping arguments are insensitive, but others are not (and since one motivation for endorsing the sensitivity condition was to provide an explanation of what goes wrong in bootstrapping arguments, this motivation is undermined). In reply, I show that sensitivity does not treat different higher-order beliefs differently in the way that Melchior states and that while genuine bootstrapping arguments have insensitive conclusions, the cases that Melchior describes as sensitive 'bootstrapping' arguments don't deserve the name, since they are a perfectly good way of getting to know their conclusions. In sum, sensitivity doesn't have a heterogeneity problem.

在最近的一篇论文中,Melchior针对敏感性条件提出了一种新的论证策略。他的观点是,敏感性受到“异质性问题”的影响:尽管一些高阶信念是可知的,但其他非常相似的高阶信念是不敏感的,因此是不可知的。类似地,一些引导参数的结论是不敏感的,而另一些则不是(由于支持敏感性条件的一个动机是解释引导参数中出现的问题,因此这个动机被破坏了)。作为回答,我表明敏感性并没有像Melchior所说的那样以不同的方式对待不同的高阶信念,而且尽管真正的自举论证有不敏感的结论,但Melchior描述为敏感的“自举”论证的情况并不值得使用这个名字,因为它们是了解其结论的完美方式。总之,灵敏度不存在异质性问题。
{"title":"Sensitivity hasn't got a Heterogeneity Problem - a Reply to Melchior.","authors":"Kevin Wallbridge","doi":"10.1007/s11406-016-9782-z","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-016-9782-z","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>In a recent paper, Melchior pursues a novel argumentative strategy against the sensitivity condition. His claim is that sensitivity suffers from a 'heterogeneity problem:' although some higher-order beliefs are knowable, other, very similar, higher-order beliefs are insensitive and so not knowable. Similarly, the conclusions of some bootstrapping arguments are insensitive, but others are not (and since one motivation for endorsing the sensitivity condition was to provide an explanation of what goes wrong in bootstrapping arguments, this motivation is undermined). In reply, I show that sensitivity does not treat different higher-order beliefs differently in the way that Melchior states and that while genuine bootstrapping arguments have insensitive conclusions, the cases that Melchior describes as sensitive 'bootstrapping' arguments don't deserve the name, since they are a perfectly good way of getting to know their conclusions. In sum, sensitivity doesn't have a heterogeneity problem.</p>","PeriodicalId":74436,"journal":{"name":"Philosophia (Ramat-Gan, Israel)","volume":"45 2","pages":"835-841"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s11406-016-9782-z","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"36432027","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 10
Balancing Freedom of Expression and Social Responsibility on the Internet. 平衡互联网上的言论自由和社会责任。
Pub Date : 2017-01-01 Epub Date: 2017-06-06 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-017-9856-6
Raphael Cohen-Almagor

This paper reflects on the articles submitted for the Symposium Confronting the Internet's Dark Side. I discuss some of the criticisms of the book's theory and my treatment of hate speech. The responsibilities of Internet Service Providers (ISPs) and Web-Hosting Services (WHSs) are in the fore, arguing that as they are the gatekeepers, they need to be proactive far more than they are now. This paper, like my book, strives to suggest an approach that harnesses the strengths and capabilities of the public and the private sectors in offering practical solutions to pressing problems.

本文对“面对互联网的阴暗面”研讨会提交的文章进行了反思。我讨论了对该书理论的一些批评,以及我对仇恨言论的处理。互联网服务提供商(ISPs)和网络托管服务提供商(WHSs)的责任是最重要的,他们认为,由于他们是看门人,他们需要比现在更积极主动。本文和我的书一样,努力提出一种方法,利用公共和私营部门的优势和能力,为紧迫问题提供切实可行的解决方案。
{"title":"Balancing Freedom of Expression and Social Responsibility on the Internet.","authors":"Raphael Cohen-Almagor","doi":"10.1007/s11406-017-9856-6","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-017-9856-6","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>This paper reflects on the articles submitted for the Symposium <i>Confronting the Internet's Dark Side.</i> I discuss some of the criticisms of the book's theory and my treatment of hate speech. The responsibilities of Internet Service Providers (ISPs) and Web-Hosting Services (WHSs) are in the fore, arguing that as they are the gatekeepers, they need to be proactive far more than they are now. This paper, like my book, strives to suggest an approach that harnesses the strengths and capabilities of the public and the private sectors in offering practical solutions to pressing problems.</p>","PeriodicalId":74436,"journal":{"name":"Philosophia (Ramat-Gan, Israel)","volume":"45 3","pages":"973-985"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s11406-017-9856-6","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"36432030","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
A Response to Coren's Objections to the Principle of Alternate Possibilities as Sufficient but not Necessary for Moral Responsibility. 对科恩反对替代可能性原则的回应,替代可能性原则是道德责任的充分而非必要。
Pub Date : 2017-01-01 Epub Date: 2017-05-25 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-017-9819-y
Garry Young

In this paper I respond to Coren's argument against my 2016 paper in which I present a case for the principle of alternate possibilities as sufficient but not necessary for the ascription of moral responsibility (PAP(S)). I concede that Coren has identified aspects of my original position that are vulnerable to counter-examples. Nevertheless, through a simple amendment to my original argument I am able to respond to these counter-examples without undermining the foundations on which my 2016 paper was built. Moreover, it is my contention that the main challenge Coren presents to my original paper involves making explicit that which is already implied within PAP(S). Therefore, while I acknowledge that my argument for PAP(S) requires further clarification, this can be achieved (as I demonstrate here) without undermining my original position.

在这篇论文中,我回应了Coren反对我2016年论文的论点,在该论文中,我们提出了一个替代可能性原则的案例,认为这对于道德责任的归属是充分的,但不是必要的(PAP(s))。我承认,Coren已经确定了我最初立场中容易受到反例影响的方面。尽管如此,通过对我最初论点的简单修正,我能够在不破坏我2016年论文基础的情况下回应这些反例。此外,我的论点是,Coren对我的原始论文提出的主要挑战涉及明确PAP(S)中已经隐含的内容。因此,尽管我承认我对PAP(S)的论点需要进一步澄清,但这是可以实现的(正如我在这里所展示的),而不会破坏我最初的立场。
{"title":"A Response to Coren's Objections to the Principle of Alternate Possibilities as Sufficient but not Necessary for Moral Responsibility.","authors":"Garry Young","doi":"10.1007/s11406-017-9819-y","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s11406-017-9819-y","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>In this paper I respond to Coren's argument against my 2016 paper in which I present a case for the principle of alternate possibilities as sufficient but not necessary for the ascription of moral responsibility (PAP<sub>(S)</sub>). I concede that Coren has identified aspects of my original position that are vulnerable to counter-examples. Nevertheless, through a simple amendment to my original argument I am able to respond to these counter-examples without undermining the foundations on which my 2016 paper was built. Moreover, it is my contention that the main challenge Coren presents to my original paper involves making explicit that which is already implied within PAP<sub>(S)</sub>. Therefore, while I acknowledge that my argument for PAP<sub>(S)</sub> requires further clarification, this can be achieved (as I demonstrate here) without undermining my original position.</p>","PeriodicalId":74436,"journal":{"name":"Philosophia (Ramat-Gan, Israel)","volume":"45 3","pages":"1365-1380"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s11406-017-9819-y","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"36432034","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
期刊
Philosophia (Ramat-Gan, Israel)
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1