首页 > 最新文献

Philosophia (Ramat-Gan, Israel)最新文献

英文 中文
Berg on Belief Reports. 伯格的信念报告。
Pub Date : 2017-01-01 Epub Date: 2016-09-05 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-016-9755-2
Anthony Everett

Jonathan Berg's insightful and lucid book Direct Belief develops a pragmatic account of our intuitions about Frege-cases. More precisely Berg argues that our practice of belief-reporting normally exhibits certain regularities. He argues that utterances of belief reports typically conversationally implicate that the reports adhere to these regularities. And he uses these implicatures to explain our intuitions about Frege-cases. I explore and unpack Berg's pragmatic account, considering and offering responses to three natural worries that might be raised. In particular, I respond to the objection that the regularities Berg invokes cannot generate the conversational implicatures he claims. I respond to the objection that the regularities Berg invokes do not, in fact, obtain. And I respond to the worry that Berg cannot explain how these regularities might arise in the first place.

乔纳森·伯格(Jonathan Berg)的《直接信念》(Direct Belief)深刻而清晰,对我们对弗雷格案例的直觉进行了务实的描述。更准确地说,伯格认为我们的信念报告实践通常表现出一定的规律。他认为,信念报告的话语通常在谈话中暗示这些报告遵循这些规律。他用这些暗示来解释我们对弗雷格案例的直觉。我探究并解读了伯格务实的描述,考虑并给出了对可能出现的三种自然担忧的回应。特别地,我回应了这样一种反对意见,即伯格所引用的规律不能产生他所声称的会话含义。我对这样一种反对意见作出回应,即伯格所引用的规律实际上并不存在。我对伯格无法解释这些规律最初是如何产生的担忧做出回应。
{"title":"Berg on Belief Reports.","authors":"Anthony Everett","doi":"10.1007/s11406-016-9755-2","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-016-9755-2","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Jonathan Berg's insightful and lucid book Direct Belief develops a pragmatic account of our intuitions about Frege-cases. More precisely Berg argues that our practice of belief-reporting normally exhibits certain regularities. He argues that utterances of belief reports typically conversationally implicate that the reports adhere to these regularities. And he uses these implicatures to explain our intuitions about Frege-cases. I explore and unpack Berg's pragmatic account, considering and offering responses to three natural worries that might be raised. In particular, I respond to the objection that the regularities Berg invokes cannot generate the conversational implicatures he claims. I respond to the objection that the regularities Berg invokes do not, in fact, obtain. And I respond to the worry that Berg cannot explain how these regularities might arise in the first place.</p>","PeriodicalId":74436,"journal":{"name":"Philosophia (Ramat-Gan, Israel)","volume":"45 1","pages":"35-47"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s11406-016-9755-2","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"36429111","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Mood, Delusions and Poetry: Emotional 'Wording of the World' in Psychosis, Philosophy and the Everyday. 情绪、妄想与诗歌:精神病、哲学与日常生活中的感性“世界措辞”。
Pub Date : 2017-01-01 Epub Date: 2017-05-27 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-017-9854-8
Owen Earnshaw

Starting from a comparison of the similarities between a poem by Sylvia Plath called Tulips and the words of someone in the thrall of a delusion I develop a phenomenology of how mood is basic to our articulation of the world. To develop this argument I draw on Heidegger's (1962) concept of attunement [befindlichkeit] and his contention that basic emotions open up aspects of the world for closer inspection and articulation. My thesis in this paper is that there is an underlying structural similarity between the forms of words used in poems and those found in medically diagnosed delusions and this similarity is based on the role of mood in both arenas. The difference, I argue, is that although both forms of articulation are negotiated 'as if' the subject matter was literal, the person writing the poem is self-aware that their uses of language are figurative and metaphorical. This is because the emotional lens they use to describe a situation poetically can always be removed by a return to a ground-mood of acceptance, that prevents them from becoming lost in the poetical mood. The person experiencing psychosis, on the other hand, is unable to extricate herself from the mood that underlies their delusional utterances as they have lost access to the ground-mood that the poet takes for granted. I illustrate the point using Hume's famous statement about the mood he philosophises in and look at ways sufferers from delusions could regain a sense of the non-literal projections of their words.

从比较西尔维娅·普拉斯的一首名为《郁金香》的诗和一个被错觉束缚的人的话语之间的相似之处开始,我发展了一种现象学,即情绪是我们表达世界的基础。为了发展这一论点,我借鉴了海德格尔(1962)的调谐概念,以及他的论点,即基本情感为更仔细的检查和表达打开了世界的各个方面。我在这篇论文中的论点是,诗歌中使用的词汇形式与医学诊断的妄想中发现的词汇形式之间存在潜在的结构相似性,这种相似性是基于情绪在这两个领域中的作用。我认为,不同之处在于,尽管这两种形式的表达都是“仿佛”主题是字面上的,但写诗的人自我意识到他们对语言的使用是比喻和隐喻的。这是因为他们用来诗意地描述一种情况的情感镜头总是可以通过回归到一种接受的基本情绪而被移除,这可以防止他们迷失在诗意的情绪中。另一方面,患有精神病的人无法从他们妄想的话语背后的情绪中解脱出来,因为他们失去了与地面的联系——诗人认为理所当然的情绪。我用休谟那句著名的话来说明这一点,那句话是关于他哲学思考时的情绪,并看看患有错觉的人是如何重新获得他们话语的非字面投射感的。
{"title":"Mood, Delusions and Poetry: Emotional 'Wording of the World' in Psychosis, Philosophy and the Everyday.","authors":"Owen Earnshaw","doi":"10.1007/s11406-017-9854-8","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-017-9854-8","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Starting from a comparison of the similarities between a poem by Sylvia Plath called <i>Tulips</i> and the words of someone in the thrall of a delusion I develop a phenomenology of how mood is basic to our articulation of the world. To develop this argument I draw on Heidegger's (1962) concept of attunement [befindlichkeit] and his contention that basic emotions open up aspects of the world for closer inspection and articulation. My thesis in this paper is that there is an underlying structural similarity between the forms of words used in poems and those found in medically diagnosed delusions and this similarity is based on the role of mood in both arenas. The difference, I argue, is that although both forms of articulation are negotiated 'as if' the subject matter was literal, the person writing the poem is self-aware that their uses of language are figurative and metaphorical. This is because the emotional lens they use to describe a situation poetically can always be removed by a return to a ground-mood of acceptance, that prevents them from becoming lost in the poetical mood. The person experiencing psychosis, on the other hand, is unable to extricate herself from the mood that underlies their delusional utterances as they have lost access to the ground-mood that the poet takes for granted. I illustrate the point using Hume's famous statement about the mood he philosophises in and look at ways sufferers from delusions could regain a sense of the non-literal projections of their words.</p>","PeriodicalId":74436,"journal":{"name":"Philosophia (Ramat-Gan, Israel)","volume":"45 4","pages":"1697-1708"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s11406-017-9854-8","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"36430937","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
The Political Theory of Modus Vivendi. 权宜之计的政治理论。
Pub Date : 2017-01-01 Epub Date: 2017-01-12 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-016-9800-1
Peter Jones

One of John Horton's most original and significant contributions to political theory is his development and exploration of the political theory of modus vivendi (MV). I examine what Horton understands a MV to be, what sort of theory he intends the political theory of MV to be, and why he believes a MV to be the best we can reasonably hope for. I consider how far his notion of MV matches the reality of contemporary political systems and whether 'liberal moralism' is quite as divorced from reality or as devoid of practical consequence as his political theory of MV would have us believe.

约翰·霍顿对政治理论最具原创性和意义的贡献之一是他对权宜之计政治理论的发展和探索。我考察了霍顿对MV的理解,他希望MV的政治理论是什么样的理论,以及为什么他认为MV是我们可以合理期望的最好的。我考虑他的MV概念在多大程度上符合当代政治制度的现实,以及“自由道德主义”是否像他的MV政治理论让我们相信的那样脱离现实或缺乏实践后果。
{"title":"The Political Theory of Modus Vivendi.","authors":"Peter Jones","doi":"10.1007/s11406-016-9800-1","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-016-9800-1","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>One of John Horton's most original and significant contributions to political theory is his development and exploration of the political theory of modus vivendi (MV). I examine what Horton understands a MV to be, what sort of theory he intends the political theory of MV to be, and why he believes a MV to be the best we can reasonably hope for. I consider how far his notion of MV matches the reality of contemporary political systems and whether 'liberal moralism' is quite as divorced from reality or as devoid of practical consequence as his political theory of MV would have us believe.</p>","PeriodicalId":74436,"journal":{"name":"Philosophia (Ramat-Gan, Israel)","volume":"45 2","pages":"443-461"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s11406-016-9800-1","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"36431579","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 14
Dismissing the Moral Sceptic: A Wittgensteinian Approach. 驳斥道德怀疑论者:一种维特根斯坦式的方法。
Pub Date : 2017-01-01 Epub Date: 2017-01-13 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-016-9805-9
Sasha Lawson-Frost

Cartesian scepticism poses the question of how we can justify our belief that other humans experience consciousness in the same way that we do. Wittgenstein's response to this scepticism is one that does not seek to resolve the problem by providing a sound argument against the Cartesian sceptic. Rather, he provides a method of philosophical inquiry which enables us to move past this and continue our inquiry without the possibility of solipsism arising as a philosophical problem in the first place. In this paper, I propose that Wittgenstein's method of dismissing the Cartesian sceptic can also be applied to the problems posed by the 'moral sceptic', who denies the truth of all ethical or moral claims. I will argue that in the same way Wittgenstein's focus on public language enables us to dismiss the traditional problem of other minds, a focus on public moral practices or language-games also enables us to dismiss the idea that moral claims are always 'meaningless', 'false' or 'nonsensical'. On this account, the moral sceptic is misguided in much the same way as the solipsist who implicitly admits the existence of other minds in her practices. The moral sceptic who still engages in moral activities also implicitly admits the existence of meaningful moral positions. Wittgenstein's dismissal of the Cartesian sceptic, as I understand it, can be broadly divided into two parts. The first part is an account of language acquisition. This part outlines how we might come to see other humans as conscious, thinking, feeling beings from a causal perspective. This suggests that we can arrive at an understanding of other minds as a primary perception itself - without needing to posit this perception as a kind of deductive or inductive hypothesis. Secondly, we can see how this relates to an epistemic model of language. This focuses on the role of language as something which consists of rule-governed activities, where the existence of other minds is embedded in our understanding of the world as a kind of grammatical rule, rather than an observational hypothesis. From both these arguments the Cartesian sceptic is, (on Wittgenstein's account), irrelevant to some forms of philosophical inquiry. This is because the sceptic takes the existence of other minds to be a rational hypothesis/inference when it is not. I suggest that this approach can be applied to moral scepticism if we take certain normative claims as grammatical dispositions (practical and tautological), rather than rational or metaphysical propositions. Hence, the moral sceptic who offers a rational or logical critique of these moral foundations is not necessarily saying anything relevant to our practices - the moral stances which they refute as rationally meaningless were never based on purely rational or logical hypotheses in the first place.

笛卡尔的怀疑主义提出了这样一个问题:我们如何证明我们的信念是正确的,即其他人的意识体验方式与我们相同。维特根斯坦对这种怀疑主义的回应,并不是试图通过提供一个反对笛卡尔怀疑主义的合理论证来解决问题。相反,他提供了一种哲学探究的方法,使我们能够超越这一点,继续我们的探究,而不会首先出现唯我论作为一个哲学问题的可能性。在本文中,我提出维特根斯坦驳斥笛卡尔怀疑论者的方法也可以应用于“道德怀疑论者”提出的问题,他们否认所有伦理或道德主张的真实性。我认为,就像维特根斯坦对公共语言的关注使我们能够摒弃传统的他人思想问题一样,对公共道德实践或语言游戏的关注也使我们能够摒弃道德主张总是“无意义”、“错误”或“荒谬”的观点。在这种情况下,道德怀疑论者和唯我论者一样,都被误导了,唯我论者在实践中含蓄地承认其他心灵的存在。从事道德活动的道德怀疑论者也含蓄地承认有意义的道德立场的存在。维特根斯坦对笛卡尔怀疑论的驳斥,在我看来,大致可以分为两部分。第一部分是关于语言习得的论述。这一部分概述了我们如何从因果关系的角度来看待其他人是有意识的、会思考的、有感情的生物。这表明,我们可以将他人的思想理解为一种基本感知本身,而无需将这种感知假定为一种演绎或归纳假设。其次,我们可以看到这是如何与语言的认知模型联系起来的。这一理论关注的是语言作为一种由规则支配的活动组成的东西的作用,在这种活动中,其他思想的存在作为一种语法规则嵌入到我们对世界的理解中,而不是一种观察假设。从这两个论点来看,笛卡尔式的怀疑论者(根据维特根斯坦的说法)与某些形式的哲学探究无关。这是因为怀疑论者认为其他心灵的存在是一种理性的假设/推论,而事实并非如此。我认为,如果我们把某些规范性主张作为语法倾向(实用的和重言式的),而不是理性的或形而上学的命题,那么这种方法可以应用于道德怀疑主义。因此,对这些道德基础提出理性或逻辑批判的道德怀疑论者不一定会说任何与我们的实践相关的东西——他们所驳斥的道德立场在理性上毫无意义,从一开始就不是基于纯粹理性或逻辑的假设。
{"title":"Dismissing the Moral Sceptic: A Wittgensteinian Approach.","authors":"Sasha Lawson-Frost","doi":"10.1007/s11406-016-9805-9","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-016-9805-9","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Cartesian scepticism poses the question of how we can justify our belief that other humans experience consciousness in the same way that we do. Wittgenstein's response to this scepticism is one that does not seek to resolve the problem by providing a sound argument against the Cartesian sceptic. Rather, he provides a method of philosophical inquiry which enables us to move past this and continue our inquiry without the possibility of solipsism arising as a philosophical problem in the first place. In this paper, I propose that Wittgenstein's method of dismissing the Cartesian sceptic can also be applied to the problems posed by the 'moral sceptic', who denies the truth of all ethical or moral claims. I will argue that in the same way Wittgenstein's focus on public language enables us to dismiss the traditional problem of other minds, a focus on public moral practices or language-games also enables us to dismiss the idea that moral claims are always 'meaningless', 'false' or 'nonsensical'. On this account, the moral sceptic is misguided in much the same way as the solipsist who implicitly admits the existence of other minds in her practices. The moral sceptic who still engages in moral activities also implicitly admits the existence of meaningful moral positions. Wittgenstein's dismissal of the Cartesian sceptic, as I understand it, can be broadly divided into two parts. The first part is an account of language acquisition. This part outlines how we might come to see other humans as conscious, thinking, feeling beings from a causal perspective. This suggests that we can arrive at an understanding of other minds as a primary perception itself - without needing to posit this perception as a kind of deductive or inductive hypothesis. Secondly, we can see how this relates to an epistemic model of language. This focuses on the role of language as something which consists of rule-governed activities, where the existence of other minds is embedded in our understanding of the world as a kind of grammatical rule, rather than an observational hypothesis. From both these arguments the Cartesian sceptic is, (on Wittgenstein's account), irrelevant to some forms of philosophical inquiry. This is because the sceptic takes the existence of other minds to be a rational hypothesis/inference when it is not. I suggest that this approach can be applied to moral scepticism if we take certain normative claims as grammatical dispositions (practical and tautological), rather than rational or metaphysical propositions. Hence, the moral sceptic who offers a rational or logical critique of these moral foundations is not necessarily saying anything relevant to our practices - the moral stances which they refute as rationally meaningless were never based on purely rational or logical hypotheses in the first place.</p>","PeriodicalId":74436,"journal":{"name":"Philosophia (Ramat-Gan, Israel)","volume":"45 3","pages":"1235-1251"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s11406-016-9805-9","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"36432032","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Embodied and Situated Nature of Moods. 情绪的具体性和情境性。
Pub Date : 2017-01-01 Epub Date: 2017-02-13 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-017-9817-0
Giovanna Colombetti

In this paper I argue that it is misleading to regard the brain as the physical basis or "core machinery" of moods. First, empirical evidence shows that brain activity not only influences, but is in turn influenced by, physical activity taking place in other parts of the organism (such as the endocrine and immune systems). It is therefore not clear why the core machinery of moods ought to be restricted to the brain. I propose, instead, that moods should be conceived as embodied, i.e., their physical basis should be enlarged so as to comprise not just brain but also bodily processes. Second, I emphasise that moods are also situated in the world. By this I do not simply mean that moods are influenced by the world, but that they are complexly interrelated with it, in at least three different ways: they are shaped by cultural values and norms; they are materially and intersubjectively "scaffolded"; and they can even "experientially incorporate" parts of the world, i.e., include the experience of parts of the world as part of oneself.

在这篇论文中,我认为将大脑视为情绪的物理基础或“核心机器”是一种误导。首先,经验证据表明,大脑活动不仅影响,而且反过来受到生物体其他部位(如内分泌和免疫系统)的身体活动的影响。因此,为什么情绪的核心机制应该局限于大脑还不清楚。相反,我建议,情绪应该被视为具体化的,也就是说,它们的物理基础应该扩大,不仅包括大脑,还包括身体过程。其次,我强调,情绪也存在于世界之中。我的意思不仅仅是说情绪受到世界的影响,而是说它们与世界有着复杂的相互联系,至少有三种不同的方式:它们是由文化价值观和规范塑造的;它们在物质上和主体间都是“脚手架”;他们甚至可以“经验地融入”世界的某些部分,即将世界某些部分的经验作为自己的一部分。
{"title":"The Embodied and Situated Nature of Moods.","authors":"Giovanna Colombetti","doi":"10.1007/s11406-017-9817-0","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s11406-017-9817-0","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>In this paper I argue that it is misleading to regard the brain as <i>the</i> physical basis or \"core machinery\" of moods. First, empirical evidence shows that brain activity not only influences, but is in turn influenced by, physical activity taking place in other parts of the organism (such as the endocrine and immune systems). It is therefore not clear why the core machinery of moods ought to be restricted to the brain. I propose, instead, that moods should be conceived as <i>embodied</i>, i.e., their physical basis should be enlarged so as to comprise not just brain but also bodily processes. Second, I emphasise that moods are also <i>situated</i> in the world. By this I do not simply mean that moods are influenced by the world, but that they are complexly interrelated with it, in at least three different ways: they are shaped by cultural values and norms; they are materially and intersubjectively \"scaffolded\"; and they can even \"experientially incorporate\" parts of the world, i.e., include the experience of parts of the world as part of oneself.</p>","PeriodicalId":74436,"journal":{"name":"Philosophia (Ramat-Gan, Israel)","volume":"45 4","pages":"1437-1451"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC6086258/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"36432035","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
What is it like to be the Metaphysical Subject? An Essay on Early Wittgenstein, our Epistemic Position, and Beyond. 作为形而上学主体是什么样的?论早期维特根斯坦、我们的认知立场及其以后。
Pub Date : 2016-01-01 Epub Date: 2016-02-09 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-016-9693-z
Konrad Werner

I argue that Ludwig Wittgenstein's idea of the metaphysical subject sheds new light on subjective qualities of experience. In this article I draw first of all on the interpretations provided by Michael Kremer and James Conant. Subsequently, I conclude that "what is it like" means primarily "what is it like to see myself as the metaphysical subject".

我认为路德维希·维特根斯坦(Ludwig Wittgenstein)关于形而上学主体的观点为经验的主观品质提供了新的启示。在本文中,我首先借鉴了Michael Kremer和James Conant提供的解释。随后,我得出结论,“它是什么样子”主要意味着“把我自己看作形而上学的主体是什么样子”。
{"title":"What is it like to be the Metaphysical Subject? An Essay on Early Wittgenstein, our Epistemic Position, and Beyond.","authors":"Konrad Werner","doi":"10.1007/s11406-016-9693-z","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-016-9693-z","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>I argue that Ludwig Wittgenstein's idea of the metaphysical subject sheds new light on subjective qualities of experience. In this article I draw first of all on the interpretations provided by Michael Kremer and James Conant. Subsequently, I conclude that \"what is it like\" means primarily \"what is it like to see myself as the metaphysical subject\".</p>","PeriodicalId":74436,"journal":{"name":"Philosophia (Ramat-Gan, Israel)","volume":"44 3","pages":"921-946"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2016-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s11406-016-9693-z","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"36439165","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Forgiveness and Moral Development. 宽恕与道德发展。
Pub Date : 2016-01-01 Epub Date: 2016-07-05 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-016-9727-6
Paula Satne

Forgiveness is clearly an important aspect of our moral lives, yet surprisingly Kant, one of the most important authors in the history of Western ethics, seems to have very little to say about it. Some authors explain this omission by noting that forgiveness sits uncomfortably in Kant's moral thought: forgiveness seems to have an ineluctably 'elective' aspect which makes it to a certain extent arbitrary; thus it stands in tension with Kant's claim that agents are autonomous beings, capable of determining their own moral status through rational reflection and choice. Other authors recognise that forgiveness plays a role in Kant's philosophy but fail to appreciate the nature of this duty and misrepresent the Kantian argument in support of it. This paper argues that there is space in Kant's philosophy for a genuine theory of forgiveness and hopes to lay the grounds for a correct interpretation of this theory. I argue that from a Kantian perspective, forgiveness is not 'elective' but, at least in some cases, morally required. I claim that, for Kant, we have an imperfect duty of virtue to forgive repentant wrongdoers that have embarked on a project of self-reflection and self-reform. I develop a novel argument in support of this duty by drawing on Kant's theory of rational agency, the thesis of radical evil, Kant's theory of moral development, and the formula of humanity. However, it must be noted that this is a conditional duty and Kant's position also entails that absence of repentance on the part of the wrongdoer should be taken as evidence of a lack of commitment to a project of self-reflection and self-reform. In such cases, Kant claims, we have a perfect duty to ourselves not to forgive unrepentant wrongdoers. I argue that this duty should be understood as one of the duties of self-esteem, which involves the duty to respect and recognise our own dignity as rational beings.

宽恕显然是我们道德生活的一个重要方面,但令人惊讶的是,作为西方伦理学史上最重要的作家之一,康德似乎对此几乎没有什么看法。一些作者通过指出宽恕在康德的道德思想中令人不安地存在来解释这一遗漏:宽恕似乎具有不可避免的“选择性”方面,这使得它在一定程度上是任意的;因此,它与康德的主张相悖,康德主张行为人是自主的存在,能够通过理性的反思和选择来决定自己的道德地位。其他作者认识到宽恕在康德的哲学中扮演着重要角色,但却未能理解这种责任的本质,并歪曲了康德支持宽恕的论点。本文认为康德哲学中存在着一种真正意义上的宽恕理论的空间,并希望为这一理论的正确解读奠定基础。我认为,从康德的角度来看,宽恕不是“可选择的”,而是,至少在某些情况下,道德要求。我认为,对康德来说,我们有一种不完美的美德义务去原谅那些已经开始自我反思和自我改造的悔过者。我通过引用康德的理性能动性理论、激进恶论、康德的道德发展理论和人性公式,提出了一个新的论点来支持这一义务。然而,必须指出的是,这是一种有条件的义务,康德的立场也意味着,犯错的一方缺乏忏悔,应该被视为缺乏自我反思和自我改革的承诺的证据。康德认为,在这种情况下,我们对自己有完全的责任,不去原谅不悔改的作恶者。我认为,这种义务应该被理解为自尊的义务之一,自尊包括尊重和承认我们作为理性人的尊严的义务。
{"title":"Forgiveness and Moral Development.","authors":"Paula Satne","doi":"10.1007/s11406-016-9727-6","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-016-9727-6","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Forgiveness is clearly an important aspect of our moral lives, yet surprisingly Kant, one of the most important authors in the history of Western ethics, seems to have very little to say about it. Some authors explain this omission by noting that forgiveness sits uncomfortably in Kant's moral thought: forgiveness seems to have an ineluctably 'elective' aspect which makes it to a certain extent arbitrary; thus it stands in tension with Kant's claim that agents are autonomous beings, capable of determining their own moral status through rational reflection and choice. Other authors recognise that forgiveness plays a role in Kant's philosophy but fail to appreciate the nature of this duty and misrepresent the Kantian argument in support of it. This paper argues that there is space in Kant's philosophy for a genuine theory of forgiveness and hopes to lay the grounds for a correct interpretation of this theory. I argue that from a Kantian perspective, forgiveness is not 'elective' but, at least in some cases, morally required. I claim that, for Kant, we have an imperfect duty of virtue to forgive repentant wrongdoers that have embarked on a project of self-reflection and self-reform. I develop a novel argument in support of this duty by drawing on Kant's theory of rational agency, the thesis of radical evil, Kant's theory of moral development, and the formula of humanity. However, it must be noted that this is a conditional duty and Kant's position also entails that absence of repentance on the part of the wrongdoer should be taken as evidence of a lack of commitment to a project of self-reflection and self-reform. In such cases, Kant claims, we have a perfect duty to ourselves not to forgive unrepentant wrongdoers. I argue that this duty should be understood as one of the duties of <i>self-esteem</i>, which involves the duty to respect and recognise our own dignity as rational beings.</p>","PeriodicalId":74436,"journal":{"name":"Philosophia (Ramat-Gan, Israel)","volume":"44 4","pages":"1029-1055"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2016-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s11406-016-9727-6","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"36439169","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 9
Forgiveness, Representative Judgement and Love of the World: Exploring the Political Significance of Forgiveness in the Context of Transitional Justice and Reconciliation Debates. 宽恕、代表性审判与对世界的爱:在过渡正义与和解辩论的背景下探索宽恕的政治意义。
Pub Date : 2016-01-01 Epub Date: 2016-06-08 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-016-9726-7
Maša Mrovlje

The article examines the political challenge and significance of forgiveness as an indispensable response to the inherently imperfect and tragic nature of political life through the lens of the existential, narrative-inspired judging sensibility. While the political significance of forgiveness has been broadly recognized in transitional justice and reconciliation contexts, the question of its importance and appropriateness in the wake of grave injustice and suffering has commonly been approached through constructing a self-centred, rule-based framework, defining forgiveness in terms of a moral duty or virtue. Reliant on a set of prefabricated moral standards, however, this approach risks abstracting from the historical, situated condition of human political existence and thus arguably stands at a remove from the very quandaries and imperfections of the political world, which it purports to address. Against this background, this article draws on Albert Camus's and Hannah Arendt's aesthetic, worldly judging sensibility and its ability to kindle the process of coming to terms with the absurd, and perhaps unforgivable character of reality after evil. As an aptitude to engage the world in its particularity, plurality and contingency rather than seeking to subdue and tame it under prefabricated standards of thought, namely, worldly judgement is able to reveal how past tragedies have arisen from the ambiguity of human engagement in the world and thereby also elicit the distinctly human capacities of beginning anew and resisting such actions in the future. As such, I suggest, it is well-suited to bring into clearer focus and confront the main political challenge and significance of forgiveness: how to acknowledge the seriousness of the wrongs committed, yet also enable the possibility of a new beginning and restore among former enemies the sense of responsibility for the shared world.

本文通过存在主义、叙事启发的判断敏感性的视角,考察了宽恕作为对政治生活固有的不完美和悲剧性的不可或缺的回应所面临的政治挑战和意义。虽然宽恕的政治意义在过渡时期的司法和和解情况下已得到广泛承认,但在严重的不公正和苦难之后,宽恕的重要性和适当性问题通常是通过建立一个以自我为中心、以规则为基础的框架来解决的,从道德责任或美德的角度来定义宽恕。然而,这种方法依赖于一套预先设定的道德标准,有可能从人类政治存在的历史和情境中抽象出来,因此可以说,它远离了政治世界的困境和不完善,而这正是它所要解决的。在此背景下,本文借鉴了阿尔贝·加缪和汉娜·阿伦特的审美、世俗的判断力,以及它在邪恶之后与荒谬、也许是不可原谅的现实性格达成协议的过程中的能力。作为一种以世界的特殊性、多元性和偶然性参与世界的能力,而不是试图在预先制定的思想标准下征服和驯服世界,也就是说,世俗判断能够揭示过去的悲剧是如何从人类参与世界的模糊性中产生的,从而也引出了人类重新开始和抵制未来此类行为的独特能力。因此,我认为,这本书非常适合让人们更清楚地关注和面对宽恕的主要政治挑战和意义:如何承认所犯错误的严重性,同时又使新的开始成为可能,并在以前的敌人之间恢复对共同世界的责任感。
{"title":"Forgiveness, Representative Judgement and Love of the World: Exploring the Political Significance of Forgiveness in the Context of Transitional Justice and Reconciliation Debates.","authors":"Maša Mrovlje","doi":"10.1007/s11406-016-9726-7","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-016-9726-7","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>The article examines the political challenge and significance of forgiveness as an indispensable response to the inherently imperfect and tragic nature of political life through the lens of the existential, narrative-inspired judging sensibility. While the political significance of forgiveness has been broadly recognized in transitional justice and reconciliation contexts, the question of its importance and appropriateness in the wake of grave injustice and suffering has commonly been approached through constructing a self-centred, rule-based framework, defining forgiveness in terms of a moral duty or virtue. Reliant on a set of prefabricated moral standards, however, this approach risks abstracting from the historical, situated condition of human political existence and thus arguably stands at a remove from the very quandaries and imperfections of the political world, which it purports to address. Against this background, this article draws on Albert Camus's and Hannah Arendt's aesthetic, worldly judging sensibility and its ability to kindle the process of coming to terms with the absurd, and perhaps unforgivable character of reality after evil. As an aptitude to engage the world in its particularity, plurality and contingency rather than seeking to subdue and tame it under prefabricated standards of thought, namely, worldly judgement is able to reveal how past tragedies have arisen from the ambiguity of human engagement in the world and thereby also elicit the distinctly human capacities of beginning anew and resisting such actions in the future. As such, I suggest, it is well-suited to bring into clearer focus and confront the main <i>political</i> challenge and significance of forgiveness: how to acknowledge the seriousness of the wrongs committed, yet also enable the possibility of a new beginning and restore among former enemies the sense of responsibility for the shared world.</p>","PeriodicalId":74436,"journal":{"name":"Philosophia (Ramat-Gan, Israel)","volume":"44 4","pages":"1079-1098"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2016-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s11406-016-9726-7","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"36439171","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
The Foundations of Agency - and Ethics? 代理与伦理的基础?
Pub Date : 2016-01-01 Epub Date: 2016-04-10 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-016-9702-2
Olof Leffler

In this article, I take off from some central issues in Paul Katsafanas' recent book Agency and the Foundations of Ethics. I argue that Katsafanas' alleged aims of action fail to do the work he requires them to do. First, his approach to activity or control is deeply problematic in the light of counterexamples. More importantly, the view of activity or control he needs to get his argument going is most likely false, as it requires our values to do work that they are too fickle to do. Second, I take issue with the Nietzschean drive psychology underlying the second agential aim, viz. power. I argue that ordinary desires better describe a number of phenomena that Katsafanas uses drives to explain, and that some actions can aim in the opposite direction. As only drive-motivated actions aim at power, action does not, therefore, constitutively aim at power. Finally, I sketch a Humean approach to constitutivism, and argue that it both explains the desiderata that Katsafanas posits as well as solves the problems for his view. The Humean view is preferable, and should be developed further.

在这篇文章中,我从Paul Katsafanas的新书《代理和伦理基础》中选取了一些核心问题。我认为,Katsafanas所谓的行动目标未能完成他要求他们完成的工作。首先,从反例的角度来看,他对活动或控制的方法存在严重问题。更重要的是,他所需要的活动或控制的观点很可能是错误的,因为它需要我们的价值观去做他们太易变而无法做的工作。其次,我对尼采的驱力心理学提出质疑,尼采的驱力心理学是第二个能动目标的基础,即权力。我认为,Katsafanas用“驱力”来解释的一些现象,可以用“普通欲望”来更好地描述,而有些行为的目标可能是相反的。由于只有动机驱动的行动以权力为目标,因此行动不是以权力为根本目标。最后,我概述了一种休谟的建构主义方法,并认为它既解释了卡萨法纳斯所假设的欲望,也解决了他的观点所存在的问题。休谟的观点是可取的,并应进一步发展。
{"title":"The Foundations of Agency - and Ethics?","authors":"Olof Leffler","doi":"10.1007/s11406-016-9702-2","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-016-9702-2","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>In this article, I take off from some central issues in Paul Katsafanas' recent book Agency and the Foundations of Ethics. I argue that Katsafanas' alleged aims of action fail to do the work he requires them to do. First, his approach to activity or control is deeply problematic in the light of counterexamples. More importantly, the view of activity or control he needs to get his argument going is most likely false, as it requires our values to do work that they are too fickle to do. Second, I take issue with the Nietzschean drive psychology underlying the second agential aim, viz. power. I argue that ordinary desires better describe a number of phenomena that Katsafanas uses drives to explain, and that some actions can aim in the opposite direction. As only drive-motivated actions aim at power, action does not, therefore, constitutively aim at power. Finally, I sketch a Humean approach to constitutivism, and argue that it both explains the desiderata that Katsafanas posits as well as solves the problems for his view. The Humean view is preferable, and should be developed further.</p>","PeriodicalId":74436,"journal":{"name":"Philosophia (Ramat-Gan, Israel)","volume":"44 2","pages":"547-563"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2016-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s11406-016-9702-2","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"36441742","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
The Principle of Alternate Possibilities as Sufficient but not Necessary for Moral Responsibility: A way to Avoid the Frankfurt Counter-Example. 道德责任的充分而非必要的交替可能性原则:避免法兰克福反例的途径。
Pub Date : 2016-01-01 Epub Date: 2016-02-27 DOI: 10.1007/s11406-016-9690-2
Garry Young

The aim of this paper is to present a version of the principle of alternate possibilities (PAP) which is not susceptible to the Frankfurt-style counter-example. I argue that PAP does not need to be endorsed as a necessary condition for moral responsibility and, in fact, presenting PAP as a sufficient condition maintains its usefulness as a maxim for moral accountability whilst avoiding Frankfurt-style counter-examples. In addition, I provide a further sufficient condition for moral responsibility - the twin world condition - and argue that this provides a means of justifying why the protagonist in Frankfurt-style scenarios (e.g., Jones) is still felt to be morally responsible. I conclude with the claim that neither the amended PAP nor the twin world condition is necessary for the ascription of moral responsibility; rather, what is necessary is simply that one of these conditions is satisfied.

本文的目的是提出一种不受法兰克福式反例影响的替代可能性原则。我认为,PAP不需要被认可为道德责任的必要条件,事实上,将PAP作为充分条件提出,可以保持其作为道德责任准则的有效性,同时避免法兰克福式的反例。此外,我还提供了道德责任的进一步充分条件——孪生世界条件——并认为这提供了一种方法来证明为什么法兰克福式场景中的主角(例如琼斯)仍然被认为是有道德责任的。我的结论是,修正后的PAP和双世界条件都不是道德责任归属的必要条件;相反,必要的仅仅是满足这些条件中的一个。
{"title":"The Principle of Alternate Possibilities as Sufficient but not Necessary for Moral Responsibility: A way to Avoid the Frankfurt Counter-Example.","authors":"Garry Young","doi":"10.1007/s11406-016-9690-2","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-016-9690-2","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>The aim of this paper is to present a version of the principle of alternate possibilities (PAP) which is not susceptible to the Frankfurt-style counter-example. I argue that PAP does not need to be endorsed as a necessary condition for moral responsibility and, in fact, presenting PAP as a sufficient condition maintains its usefulness as a maxim for moral accountability whilst avoiding Frankfurt-style counter-examples. In addition, I provide a further sufficient condition for moral responsibility - the twin world condition - and argue that this provides a means of justifying why the protagonist in Frankfurt-style scenarios (e.g., Jones) is still felt to be morally responsible. I conclude with the claim that neither the amended PAP nor the twin world condition is necessary for the ascription of moral responsibility; rather, what is necessary is simply that one of these conditions is satisfied.</p>","PeriodicalId":74436,"journal":{"name":"Philosophia (Ramat-Gan, Israel)","volume":"44 3","pages":"961-969"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2016-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1007/s11406-016-9690-2","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"36439166","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 7
期刊
Philosophia (Ramat-Gan, Israel)
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1