首页 > 最新文献

Asian journal of philosophy最新文献

英文 中文
Heuristics in philosophy 哲学中的启发式
Pub Date : 2024-06-15 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00174-7
Timothy Williamson

This article argues that heuristics play a key role in philosophy, in generating both our verdicts on proposed counterexamples to philosophical theories and philosophical paradoxes. Heuristics are efficient ways of answering questions, quick and easy to use, but imperfectly reliable. They have been studied by psychologists and cognitive scientists such as Gigerenzer and Kahneman, but their relevance to philosophical methodology has not been properly recognized. Several heuristics are discussed at length. The persistence heuristic can be summarized in the slogan ‘Small changes don’t matter’. Without it, updating would present an intractable problem for both natural and artificial intelligence. But our reliance on the persistence heuristic also makes us vulnerable to paradoxes of vagueness. Disquotational heuristics of various kinds are considered. They play central roles in our ascriptions of truth, falsity, and belief, but they also generate semantic paradoxes such as the Liar and Frege puzzles about coreference. The use of an additive heuristic for combining reasons is also discussed. Our reliance on fallible heuristics in philosophy does not make philosophical knowledge impossible, just as our reliance on fallible heuristics in perception does not make perceptual knowledge impossible. Nevertheless, it should motivate us to take a more critical attitude to our data. By identifying and analyzing the heuristics on which we rely, we may be able to work out where they make us most vulnerable to error.

本文认为,启发法在哲学中发挥着关键作用,它既能产生我们对哲学理论反例的判断,也能产生哲学悖论。启发式是回答问题的有效方法,使用起来快捷方便,但并不完全可靠。心理学家和认知科学家(如吉格伦泽和卡尼曼)对启发式进行了研究,但它们与哲学方法论的相关性尚未得到正确认识。本文详细讨论了几种启发式。持续性启发式可以概括为 "微小变化无关紧要"。没有它,更新就会给自然智能和人工智能带来难以解决的问题。但是,我们对持久性启发式的依赖也使我们容易受到模糊性悖论的影响。我们考虑了各种类型的断句启发式。它们在我们对真假和信念的描述中起着核心作用,但也会产生语义悖论,如关于核心推理的说谎者之谜和弗雷格之谜。我们还讨论了使用加法启发式来组合理由的问题。我们在哲学中对易错启发式的依赖并没有使哲学知识成为不可能,正如我们在知觉中对易错启发式的依赖并没有使知觉知识成为不可能一样。然而,它应该促使我们对我们的数据采取更加批判性的态度。通过识别和分析我们所依赖的启发式方法,我们也许能够找出它们在哪些方面使我们最容易出错。
{"title":"Heuristics in philosophy","authors":"Timothy Williamson","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00174-7","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00174-7","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>This article argues that heuristics play a key role in philosophy, in generating both our verdicts on proposed counterexamples to philosophical theories and philosophical paradoxes. Heuristics are efficient ways of answering questions, quick and easy to use, but imperfectly reliable. They have been studied by psychologists and cognitive scientists such as Gigerenzer and Kahneman, but their relevance to philosophical methodology has not been properly recognized. Several heuristics are discussed at length. The <i>persistence heuristic</i> can be summarized in the slogan ‘Small changes don’t matter’. Without it, updating would present an intractable problem for both natural and artificial intelligence. But our reliance on the persistence heuristic also makes us vulnerable to paradoxes of vagueness. <i>Disquotational heuristics</i> of various kinds are considered. They play central roles in our ascriptions of truth, falsity, and belief, but they also generate semantic paradoxes such as the Liar and Frege puzzles about coreference. The use of an additive heuristic for combining reasons is also discussed. Our reliance on fallible heuristics in philosophy does not make philosophical knowledge impossible, just as our reliance on fallible heuristics in perception does not make perceptual knowledge impossible. Nevertheless, it should motivate us to take a more critical attitude to our data. By identifying and analyzing the heuristics on which we rely, we may be able to work out where they make us most vulnerable to error.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-06-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007/s44204-024-00174-7.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141336191","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Madhyamaka and Ontic Structural Realism 偈颂与本体结构现实主义
Pub Date : 2024-06-12 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00146-x
Toby Friend

I’ll argue that one particular argument of Nāgārjuna’s against causation in the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā deserves careful consideration from the perspective of contemporary western metaphysics. To show why this is the case, I’ll offer an interpretation of the key passages which differs from at least one popular reading. I’ll then aim to show that a whole swathe of metaphysical views about causation are problematic in light of Nāgārjuna’s argument, so interpreted. I’ll conclude, however, that one contemporary view in metaphysics has the means to respond to this argument: Ontic Structural Realism.

我将论证,从当代西方形而上学的角度来看,那伽牟尼在《无量寿经》(Mūlamadhyamakakārikā)中反对因果关系的一个特殊论点值得仔细斟酌。为了说明为什么会出现这种情况,我将对关键段落进行解读,这种解读至少与一种流行的解读不同。然后,我将说明,从那跋陀罗的论证来看,形而上学关于因果关系的各种观点都是有问题的。不过,我的结论是,形而上学中的一种当代观点有办法回应这一论证:本体结构现实主义。
{"title":"Madhyamaka and Ontic Structural Realism","authors":"Toby Friend","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00146-x","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00146-x","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>I’ll argue that one particular argument of Nāgārjuna’s against causation in the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā deserves careful consideration from the perspective of contemporary western metaphysics. To show why this is the case, I’ll offer an interpretation of the key passages which differs from at least one popular reading. I’ll then aim to show that a whole swathe of metaphysical views about causation are problematic in light of Nāgārjuna’s argument, so interpreted. I’ll conclude, however, that one contemporary view in metaphysics has the means to respond to this argument: Ontic Structural Realism.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-06-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007/s44204-024-00146-x.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141353013","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Thoughts on Jun Otsuka’s Thinking about Statistics – the Philosphical Foundations 对大塚淳《统计学的思考--哲学基础》的思考
Pub Date : 2024-06-03 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00173-8
elliott sober

Jun Otsuka’s excellent book, Thinking about Statistics - the Philosophical Foundations (Otsuka 2023) is mostly organized around the idea that different statistical approaches can be illuminated by linking them to different ideas in general epistemology. Otsuka connects Bayesianism to internalism and foundationalism, frequentism to reliabilism, and the Akaike Information Criterion in model selection theory to instrumentalism. This useful mapping doesn’t cover all the interesting ideas he presents. His discussions of causal inference and machine learning are philosophically insightful, as is his idea that statisticians embrace an assumption that is similar to Hume’s Principle of the Uniformity of Nature. I discuss these topics in what follows, sometimes disagreeing with details while at other times adding ideas that complement those presented in the book.

大塚淳(Jun Otsuka)的优秀著作《思考统计学--哲学基础》(Otsuka 2023)主要围绕以下观点展开:通过将不同的统计方法与一般认识论中的不同观点联系起来,可以阐明这些方法。大冢将贝叶斯主义与内部主义和基础主义联系起来,将频繁主义与可靠主义联系起来,将模型选择理论中的阿凯克信息准则与工具主义联系起来。这个有用的映射并没有涵盖他提出的所有有趣观点。他对因果推理和机器学习的讨论很有哲学洞察力,他认为统计学家接受的假设类似于休谟的 "自然统一性原则",这也很有哲学洞察力。我将在下文中讨论这些话题,有时会对一些细节持不同意见,有时则会补充一些观点,以补充书中的内容。
{"title":"Thoughts on Jun Otsuka’s Thinking about Statistics – the Philosphical Foundations","authors":"elliott sober","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00173-8","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00173-8","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Jun Otsuka’s excellent book, <i>Thinking about Statistics - the Philosophical Foundations</i> (Otsuka 2023) is mostly organized around the idea that different statistical approaches can be illuminated by linking them to different ideas in general epistemology. Otsuka connects Bayesianism to internalism and foundationalism, frequentism to reliabilism, and the Akaike Information Criterion in model selection theory to instrumentalism. This useful mapping doesn’t cover all the interesting ideas he presents. His discussions of causal inference and machine learning are philosophically insightful, as is his idea that statisticians embrace an assumption that is similar to Hume’s Principle of the Uniformity of Nature. I discuss these topics in what follows, sometimes disagreeing with details while at other times adding ideas that complement those presented in the book.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-06-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141268969","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Sosa’s virtue account vs. responsibilism 索萨的美德论与责任论
Pub Date : 2024-06-03 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00170-x
Xingming Hu

I first present a brief interpretation of Sosa’s virtue epistemology by showing how it is arguably better than Goldman’s process reliabilism, why Sosa distinguishes between animal knowledge and reflective knowledge, and how Sosa’s recent account of knowing full well can deal with pragmatic encroachment. Then, I raise two worries about Sosa’s account: (a) Sosa’s claim that one might have animal knowledge without knowing reflectively or knowing full well implies that one’s true belief might manifest both competence and luck, which seems to pose a challenge to Sosa’s solution to the Gettier problem; (b) intellectual virtue or competence does not seem to be a necessary condition for knowledge: there are cases where one knows without possessing the relevant intellectual virtue or competence. Finally, I suggest a responsibilist account of knowledge and show how it can not only handle the cases that pose a problem for Sosa’s account but also explain our intuitions about different grades of knowledge.

我首先简要阐释了索萨的美德认识论,说明它如何可以说比戈德曼的过程可靠论更好,为什么索萨区分了动物性知识和反思性知识,以及索萨最近关于 "完全知道 "的论述如何能够应对实用主义的侵蚀。然后,我对索萨的论述提出两点担忧:(a) 索萨声称,一个人可能拥有动物知识而不反思性地知道或完全知道,这意味着一个人的真实信念可能同时体现出能力和运气,这似乎对索萨解决格蒂埃问题的方法提出了挑战;(b) 智力美德或能力似乎不是知识的必要条件:在有些情况下,一个人知道而不具备相关的智力美德或能力。最后,我提出了一个关于知识的责任主义解释,并说明它如何不仅能处理给索萨的解释带来问题的情况,而且还能解释我们对不同等级知识的直觉。
{"title":"Sosa’s virtue account vs. responsibilism","authors":"Xingming Hu","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00170-x","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00170-x","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>I first present a brief interpretation of Sosa’s virtue epistemology by showing how it is arguably better than Goldman’s process reliabilism, why Sosa distinguishes between animal knowledge and reflective knowledge, and how Sosa’s recent account of knowing full well can deal with pragmatic encroachment. Then, I raise two worries about Sosa’s account: (a) Sosa’s claim that one might have animal knowledge without knowing reflectively or knowing full well implies that one’s true belief might manifest <i>both</i> competence and luck, which seems to pose a challenge to Sosa’s solution to the Gettier problem; (b) intellectual virtue or competence does not seem to be a necessary condition for knowledge: there are cases where one knows without possessing the relevant intellectual virtue or competence. Finally, I suggest a responsibilist account of knowledge and show how it can not only handle the cases that pose a problem for Sosa’s account but also explain our intuitions about different grades of knowledge.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-06-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141271363","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
On Beall’s contradictory Christology and beyond 论比奥尔自相矛盾的基督论及其他
Pub Date : 2024-05-29 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00165-8
Filippo Casati, Naoya Fujikawa

According to Conciliar Christology, Christ has a divine nature and a human nature. This dual nature of Christ leads us to face many apparent inconsistencies: For example, it seems to follow that He is both immutable and mutable (and, therefore, not immutable). This long-standing issue in Christology has been called the fundamental problem of Christology. Recently, Jc Beall has proposed a novel approach to the fundamental problem: contradictory Christology, that is, Christology which takes those apparent inconsistencies as genuinely contradictory. This paper examines Beall’s contradictory Christology by comparing it with James Anderson’s version of consistent Christology. Such a comparison highlights an important assumption of Beall’s contradictory Christology, that is, the language used to state the fundamental problem is univocal. ‘Immutable’ is, thus, used in the same literal sense in both `Christ is immutable’ and `Christ is not immutable’. On the one hand, this assumption has a good reason given the human nature of Christ. On the other hand, we follow Anderson in showing that the view that `immutable’ is equivocal has a good reason too. For there is an established theological tradition according to which, when we speak about the divine, our language is analogical. In light of those considerations, this paper presents a semantic explication of how the predicates used to state the fundamental problem are both literal and analogical. The proposed semantics treats those predicates as cases of multiple denotations and shows that the apparent inconsistencies are genuinely contradictory, but in a different way from Beall’s contradictory Christology.

根据教会基督论,基督具有神性和人性。基督的这种双重性格使我们面临许多明显的矛盾:例如,祂似乎既是永恒不变的,又是可变的(因此不是永恒不变的)。基督论中的这一长期问题被称为基督论的基本问题。最近,比厄尔(Jc Beall)提出了一个解决这一根本问题的新方法:矛盾基督论,即把那些明显的不一致视为真正矛盾的基督论。本文通过比较比厄尔的矛盾基督论与詹姆斯-安德森(James Anderson)版本的一致基督论,对其进行了研究。这种比较凸显了比尔的矛盾基督论的一个重要假设,即阐述基本问题的语言是单一的。因此,在 "基督是永恒不变的 "和 "基督不是永恒不变的 "中,"永恒不变 "的字面意义是相同的。一方面,鉴于基督的人性,这一假设有其充分的理由。另一方面,我们追随安德森的观点,指出 "不可改变 "这一观点也有其合理性。因为有一种既定的神学传统认为,当我们谈论神性时,我们的语言是类比的。鉴于这些考虑,本文提出了一个语义学解释,说明用来陈述基本问题的谓词是如何既是字面的又是类比的。所提出的语义学将这些谓词视为多重指称的情况,并表明表面上的不一致确实是矛盾的,但其方式与比尔的矛盾基督论不同。
{"title":"On Beall’s contradictory Christology and beyond","authors":"Filippo Casati,&nbsp;Naoya Fujikawa","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00165-8","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00165-8","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>According to Conciliar Christology, Christ has a divine nature and a human nature. This dual nature of Christ leads us to face many apparent inconsistencies: For example, it seems to follow that He is both immutable and mutable (and, therefore, not immutable). This long-standing issue in Christology has been called the fundamental problem of Christology. Recently, Jc Beall has proposed a novel approach to the fundamental problem: <i>contradictory</i> Christology, that is, Christology which takes those apparent inconsistencies as genuinely contradictory. This paper examines Beall’s contradictory Christology by comparing it with James Anderson’s version of consistent Christology. Such a comparison highlights an important assumption of Beall’s contradictory Christology, that is, the language used to state the fundamental problem is <i>univocal</i>. ‘Immutable’ is, thus, used in the same <i>literal</i> sense in both `Christ is immutable’ and `Christ is not immutable’. On the one hand, this assumption has a good reason given the human nature of Christ. On the other hand, we follow Anderson in showing that the view that `immutable’ is <i>equivocal</i> has a good reason too. For there is an established theological tradition according to which, when we speak about the divine, our language is <i>analogical</i>. In light of those considerations, this paper presents a semantic explication of how the predicates used to state the fundamental problem are <i>both</i> literal and analogical. The proposed semantics treats those predicates as cases of multiple denotations and shows that the apparent inconsistencies are genuinely contradictory, but in a different way from Beall’s contradictory Christology.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007/s44204-024-00165-8.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142414972","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The truth conditions of sentences with referentially used definite descriptions 带有指代性定语描述的句子的真实条件
Pub Date : 2024-05-16 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00167-6
Wenqi Li

Keith Donnellan’s distinction between the attributive and referential uses of definite descriptions has spurred debates regarding the truth conditions of the utterance “the F is G” with definite descriptions used referentially. In this article, I present a semantic account of referential descriptions, grounded in the contextual factors of the utterance, including the speaker’s intention and presupposition as well as the interlocutor’s recognition of them. This account is called the IPR-semantic account, according to which the speaker’s intention (I) and presupposition (P) and the interlocutor’s recognition (R) jointly determine whether “the F” in an utterance “the F is G” is used referentially or attributively, and the meaning of “the F” is determined by whether it is used referentially or attributively. Moreover, I argue that the meaning of the referential description “the F” is the intended object e, embodied with a property H that has prompted the speaker to presuppose that e is F and to intend to use “the F” to refer to e, as well as the interlocutor to recognize the presupposition and intention. According to the IPR-semantic account, the utterance “the F is G” with “the F” used referentially expresses a singular proposition, namely, that e is G, and it is true if and only if the intended object e is G. Additionally, I argue that the IPR-semantic account not only surpasses some alternative semantic accounts but also outperforms Kripke’s pragmatic account.

Keith Donnellan 对定语描述的归属性使用和指称性使用所做的区分引发了关于 "the F is G "这一语句的真假条件的争论。在本文中,我提出了一种关于指称描述的语义解释,它以语篇的语境因素为基础,包括说话人的意图和预设以及对话者对它们的认识。根据这一观点,说话者的意图(I)和预设(P)以及对话者的认知(R)共同决定了 "F 是 G "语篇中的 "F "是指代性使用还是属性性使用,而 "F "的意义则取决于它是指代性使用还是属性性使用。此外,我还认为,"F "这一指称性描述的意义是意指的对象 e,它体现的属性 H 促使说话者预设 e 是 F,并打算用 "F "来指称 e,同时也促使对话者认识到这一预设和意图。根据 IPR 语义账户,"该 F 是 G"("该 F "是指代性地使用的)这一语篇表达了一个单数命题,即 e 是 G,并且当且仅当预期对象 e 是 G 时,该命题才为真。
{"title":"The truth conditions of sentences with referentially used definite descriptions","authors":"Wenqi Li","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00167-6","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00167-6","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Keith Donnellan’s distinction between the attributive and referential uses of definite descriptions has spurred debates regarding the truth conditions of the utterance “the F is G” with definite descriptions used referentially. In this article, I present a semantic account of referential descriptions, grounded in the contextual factors of the utterance, including the speaker’s intention and presupposition as well as the interlocutor’s recognition of them. This account is called the IPR-semantic account, according to which the speaker’s intention (I) and presupposition (P) and the interlocutor’s recognition (R) jointly determine whether “the F” in an utterance “the F is G” is used referentially or attributively, and the meaning of “the F” is determined by whether it is used referentially or attributively. Moreover, I argue that the meaning of the referential description “the F” is the intended object <i>e</i>, embodied with a property H that has prompted the speaker to presuppose that <i>e</i> is F and to intend to use “the F” to refer to <i>e</i>, as well as the interlocutor to recognize the presupposition and intention. According to the IPR-semantic account, the utterance “the F is G” with “the F” used referentially expresses a singular proposition, namely, that <i>e</i> is G, and it is true if and only if the intended object <i>e</i> is G. Additionally, I argue that the IPR-semantic account not only surpasses some alternative semantic accounts but also outperforms Kripke’s pragmatic account.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140969560","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Parfitian or Buddhist reductionism? Revisiting a debate about personal identity 帕菲特主义还是佛教还原论?重温关于个人身份的辩论
Pub Date : 2024-05-14 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00166-7
Javier Hidalgo

Derek Parfit influentially defends reductionism about persons, the view that a person’s existence just consists in the existence of a brain and body and the occurrence of a series of physical and mental events. Yet some critics, particularly Mark Johnston, have raised powerful objections to Parfit’s reductionism. In this paper, I defend reductionism against Johnston. In particular, I defend a radical form of reductionism that Buddhist philosophers developed. Buddhist reductionism can justify key features of Parfit’s position, such as the claims that personal identity is not what matters and can also be indeterminate. Furthermore, Buddhist reductionism can avoid Johnston’s objections to Parfit’s reductionism. I conclude that reductionists have good reasons to favor Buddhist reductionism over Parfit’s version.

德里克-帕菲特(Derek Parfit)为人的还原论辩护,认为人的存在仅仅是大脑和身体的存在,以及一系列生理和心理事件的发生。然而,一些批评家,尤其是马克-约翰斯顿(Mark Johnston),对帕菲特的还原论提出了强烈的反对意见。在本文中,我将针对约翰斯顿为还原论辩护。特别是,我为佛教哲学家所发展的一种激进形式的还原论辩护。佛教还原论可以证明帕菲特立场的关键特征是正确的,例如个人身份并不重要,而且也可以是不确定的。此外,佛教还原论可以避免约翰斯顿对帕菲特还原论的反对。我的结论是,还原论者有充分的理由支持佛教还原论,而不是帕菲特的版本。
{"title":"Parfitian or Buddhist reductionism? Revisiting a debate about personal identity","authors":"Javier Hidalgo","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00166-7","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00166-7","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Derek Parfit influentially defends reductionism about persons, the view that a person’s existence just consists in the existence of a brain and body and the occurrence of a series of physical and mental events. Yet some critics, particularly Mark Johnston, have raised powerful objections to Parfit’s reductionism. In this paper, I defend reductionism against Johnston. In particular, I defend a radical form of reductionism that Buddhist philosophers developed. Buddhist reductionism can justify key features of Parfit’s position, such as the claims that personal identity is not what matters and can also be indeterminate. Furthermore, Buddhist reductionism can avoid Johnston’s objections to Parfit’s reductionism. I conclude that reductionists have good reasons to favor Buddhist reductionism over Parfit’s version.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007/s44204-024-00166-7.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140979143","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Frankfurt’s concept of identification 法兰克福的认同概念
Pub Date : 2024-05-08 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00168-5
Chen Yajun

Harry Frankfurt had insightfully pointed out that an agent acts freely when he acts in accord with the mental states with which he identifies. The concept of identification rightly captures the ownership condition (something being one’s really own), which plays a significant role in the issues of freedom and moral responsibility. For Frankfurt, identification consists of one’s forming second-order volitions, endorsing first-order desires, and issuing in his actions wholeheartedly. An agent not only wants to φ but also fully embraces his desire to φ (and φ). Frankfurt’s official theory above encounters some serious problems, especially since it is believed that his concept of wholehearted identification is too strong to be necessary for freedom. In this paper, I propose that we can uncouple identification from wholeheartedness and thus get two different senses of identification: weak identification and strong identification. Then, I argue that this distinction does a better job than Frankfurt’s official theory. On the one hand, weak identification is enough for ownership and freedom and thus more promising than strong identification; on the other hand, this distinction has an attractive implication that it fits well with our intuition about the degree of freedom and responsibility.

哈里-法兰克福曾精辟地指出,当行为人的行为符合他所认同的心理状态时,他就是自由的。认同的概念正确地捕捉到了所有权条件(某物真正属于自己),这在自由和道德责任问题上起着重要作用。在法兰克福看来,认同包括一个人形成二阶意志,认可一阶欲望,并全心全意地付诸行动。行为者不仅希望φ,而且完全接受他对φ(和φ)的渴望。法兰克福的上述官方理论遇到了一些严重的问题,尤其是有人认为他的 "全心全意认同 "概念过于强烈,不是自由所必需的。在本文中,我提出我们可以将认同与全心全意脱钩,从而得到两种不同意义上的认同:弱认同和强认同。然后,我认为这种区分比法兰克福的官方理论做得更好。一方面,弱认同足以实现所有权和自由,因此比强认同更有前途;另一方面,这种区分具有一种诱人的含义,即它非常符合我们对自由和责任程度的直觉。
{"title":"Frankfurt’s concept of identification","authors":"Chen Yajun","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00168-5","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00168-5","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Harry Frankfurt had insightfully pointed out that an agent acts freely when he acts in accord with the mental states with which he identifies. The concept of identification rightly captures the ownership condition (something being one’s really own), which plays a significant role in the issues of freedom and moral responsibility. For Frankfurt, identification consists of one’s forming second-order volitions, endorsing first-order desires, and issuing in his actions wholeheartedly. An agent not only wants to φ but also fully embraces his desire to φ (and φ). Frankfurt’s official theory above encounters some serious problems, especially since it is believed that his concept of wholehearted identification is too strong to be necessary for freedom. In this paper, I propose that we can uncouple identification from wholeheartedness and thus get two different senses of identification: weak identification and strong identification. Then, I argue that this distinction does a better job than Frankfurt’s official theory. On the one hand, weak identification is enough for ownership and freedom and thus more promising than strong identification; on the other hand, this distinction has an attractive implication that it fits well with our intuition about the degree of freedom and responsibility.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141000905","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Contextual approaches to combating fake news: lessons from Thailand 根据具体情况打击假新闻:泰国的经验教训
Pub Date : 2024-05-01 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00162-x
Siraprapa Chavanayarn

The pervasive issue of fake news poses a formidable challenge to knowledge acquisition, further complicated by the difficulty in distinguishing it from legitimate information due to human epistemic limitations. This article argues for the necessity of adopting contextual strategies to effectively combat the spread of fake news. Through a focused examination of COVID-19-related fake news in Thailand, it explores how unique national characteristics can shape tailored approaches to mitigate this problem. The analysis draws on the theoretical insights of David Coady and Regina Rini, advocating for the integration of an open science framework to enhance transparency and public access to information. Despite the potential benefits of an open science culture, the persistence of epistemic vices among the populace may limit its effectiveness in reducing the acceptance of fake news. This article proposes that, instead of using law enforcement or fact-checking organizations, the Thai government and media entities play a critical role in addressing epistemic shortcomings and fostering epistemic virtues. However, it emphasizes that the effectiveness of these approaches is contingent upon their adaptability to the socio-cultural and epistemological context of Thailand. The discussion highlights the importance of recognizing and accommodating these contextual differences in devising strategies against the dissemination of fake news.

无处不在的假新闻问题给知识获取带来了巨大挑战,而由于人类认识论的局限性,很难将假新闻与合法信息区分开来,这使得问题变得更加复杂。本文论证了采用语境策略有效打击假新闻传播的必要性。通过对泰国与 COVID-19 相关的假新闻的重点研究,文章探讨了独特的国家特征如何形成有针对性的方法来缓解这一问题。分析借鉴了戴维-科迪(David Coady)和雷吉娜-里尼(Regina Rini)的理论见解,主张整合开放科学框架,以提高透明度和公众对信息的获取。尽管开放科学文化具有潜在的益处,但民众中持续存在的认识论恶习可能会限制其在减少假新闻接受度方面的有效性。本文建议,泰国政府和媒体实体在解决认识论缺陷和培养认识论美德方面发挥关键作用,而不是利用执法机构或事实核查组织。但讨论强调,这些方法的有效性取决于它们是否适应泰国的社会文化和认识论背景。讨论强调,在制定打击假新闻传播的战略时,必须认识到并适应这些背景差异。
{"title":"Contextual approaches to combating fake news: lessons from Thailand","authors":"Siraprapa Chavanayarn","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00162-x","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00162-x","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>The pervasive issue of fake news poses a formidable challenge to knowledge acquisition, further complicated by the difficulty in distinguishing it from legitimate information due to human epistemic limitations. This article argues for the necessity of adopting contextual strategies to effectively combat the spread of fake news. Through a focused examination of COVID-19-related fake news in Thailand, it explores how unique national characteristics can shape tailored approaches to mitigate this problem. The analysis draws on the theoretical insights of David Coady and Regina Rini, advocating for the integration of an open science framework to enhance transparency and public access to information. Despite the potential benefits of an open science culture, the persistence of epistemic vices among the populace may limit its effectiveness in reducing the acceptance of fake news. This article proposes that, instead of using law enforcement or fact-checking organizations, the Thai government and media entities play a critical role in addressing epistemic shortcomings and fostering epistemic virtues. However, it emphasizes that the effectiveness of these approaches is contingent upon their adaptability to the socio-cultural and epistemological context of Thailand. The discussion highlights the importance of recognizing and accommodating these contextual differences in devising strategies against the dissemination of fake news.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141053388","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The moving open future, temporal phenomenology, and temporal passage 移动的开放未来、时间现象学和时间流逝
Pub Date : 2024-05-01 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00157-8
Batoul Hodroj, Andrew J. Latham, Kristie Miller

Empirical evidence suggests that people naïvely represent time as dynamical (i.e. as containing robust temporal passage). Yet many contemporary B-theorists deny that it seems to us, in perceptual experience, as though time robustly passes. The question then arises as to why we represent time as dynamical if we do not have perceptual experiences which represent time as dynamical. We consider two hypotheses about why this might be: the temporally aperspectival replacement hypothesis and the moving open future hypothesis. We then empirically test the moving open future hypothesis. According to that hypothesis, we represent the past as objectively fixed and the future open. And we represent that this objective openness moves as events that were open become fixed, such that in doing so, we represent a privileged moving present. We found no evidence for the moving open future hypothesis, which suggests that further investigation of the temporally aperspectival replacement hypothesis is called for. Our results also shed further light on our understanding of the respects in which we represent the future to be open, which, in turn, has implications for our theorising about the open future.

经验证据表明,人们天真地认为时间是动态的(即包含稳健的时间流逝)。然而,许多当代 B 理论家否认,在我们的感知经验中,时间似乎是有力地流逝的。这就产生了一个问题:如果我们的知觉经验没有把时间表征为动态的,那么我们为什么要把时间表征为动态的?我们考虑了两种假设:时间上的非视角替代假设和移动的开放未来假设。然后,我们对移动的开放式未来假说进行了实证检验。根据这一假说,我们将过去客观地表述为固定的,而将未来表述为开放的。当开放的事件变成固定的事件时,这种客观的开放性就会发生移动,这样,我们就代表了一个具有特权的移动的现在。我们没有发现移动的开放未来假说的证据,这表明我们需要进一步研究时间非视角替换假说。我们的研究结果还进一步揭示了我们对未来开放性的理解,这反过来又对我们关于开放未来的理论研究产生了影响。
{"title":"The moving open future, temporal phenomenology, and temporal passage","authors":"Batoul Hodroj,&nbsp;Andrew J. Latham,&nbsp;Kristie Miller","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00157-8","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00157-8","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Empirical evidence suggests that people naïvely represent time as dynamical (i.e. as containing robust temporal passage). Yet many contemporary B-theorists deny that it seems to us, in perceptual experience, as though time robustly passes. The question then arises as to why we represent time as dynamical if we do not have perceptual experiences which represent time as dynamical. We consider two hypotheses about why this might be: the temporally aperspectival replacement hypothesis and the moving open future hypothesis. We then empirically test the moving open future hypothesis. According to that hypothesis, we represent the past as objectively fixed and the future open. And we represent that this objective openness moves as events that were open become fixed, such that in doing so, we represent a privileged moving present. We found no evidence for the moving open future hypothesis, which suggests that further investigation of the temporally aperspectival replacement hypothesis is called for. Our results also shed further light on our understanding of the respects in which we represent the future to be open, which, in turn, has implications for our theorising about the open future.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007/s44204-024-00157-8.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141033302","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Asian journal of philosophy
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1