首页 > 最新文献

Asian journal of philosophy最新文献

英文 中文
On Pettit’s thought ascription to groups 关于佩蒂特对群体的思想归属
Pub Date : 2024-04-18 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00160-z
Kanit (Mitinunwong) Sirichan

A thought, taken as a propositional attitude or the content of psychological predicates such as believe, wish, desire, and hope, is ascribed to an entity with mental states. A thought is not only allegedly ascribed to particular non-mental things like computer and book, it is also ascribed to non-material things, linguistically in plural terms, e.g., plural pronouns (e.g., we, they), collective names or singular proper names (e.g., the United States), and proper names in plural form or general terms (e.g., the Microsoft, feminists). Plural terms are terms referring to groups of entities. The question is—what is it for a group to have a thought? Two main views are currently on centered stage—the literal view and the metaphorical view. This paper argues that the main argument supporting the literal view, in particular Pettit’s view, faces three main problems, namely, the problem of rule-following in propositional coawareness, the problem of an independent verifiability for group beliefs, and the problem of the indexical “we”-thought.

思想,作为一种命题态度或心理谓词的内容,如相信、愿望、渴望和希望,被归结为具有心理状态的实体。据称,思想不仅被赋予计算机和书籍等特定的非精神性事物,它还被赋予非物质性事物,在语言上表现为复数形式,如复数代词(如 "我们"、"他们")、集体名称或单数专有名称(如美国),以及复数形式的专有名称或一般术语(如微软、女权主义者)。复数术语是指实体群体的术语。问题是--什么是有思想的群体?目前主要有两种观点--字面观点和隐喻观点。本文认为,支持字面观点的主要论据,尤其是佩蒂特的观点,面临着三个主要问题,即命题共同意识中的规则遵循问题、群体信念的独立可验证性问题以及 "我们"--思想的索引问题。
{"title":"On Pettit’s thought ascription to groups","authors":"Kanit (Mitinunwong) Sirichan","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00160-z","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00160-z","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>A thought, taken as a propositional attitude or the content of psychological predicates such as believe, wish, desire, and hope, is ascribed to an entity with mental states. A thought is not only allegedly ascribed to particular non-mental things like computer and book, it is also ascribed to non-material things, linguistically in plural terms, e.g., plural pronouns (e.g., we, they), collective names or singular proper names (e.g., the United States), and proper names in plural form or general terms (e.g., the Microsoft, feminists). Plural terms are terms referring to groups of entities. The question is—what is it for a group to have a thought? Two main views are currently on centered stage—the literal view and the metaphorical view. This paper argues that the main argument supporting the literal view, in particular Pettit’s view, faces three main problems, namely, the problem of rule-following in propositional coawareness, the problem of an independent verifiability for group beliefs, and the problem of the indexical “we”-thought.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-04-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140688109","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The ambiguity of “true” in English, German, and Chinese 英语、德语和汉语中 "true "的模糊性
Pub Date : 2024-04-15 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00150-1
Kevin Reuter

Through a series of empirical studies involving native speakers of English, German, and Chinese, this paper reveals that the predicate “true” is inherently ambiguous in the empirical domain. Truth statements such as “It is true that Tom is at the party” seem to be ambivalent between two readings. On the first reading, the statement means “Reality is such that Tom is at the party.” On the second reading, the statement means “According to what X believes, Tom is at the party.” While there appear to exist some cross-cultural differences in the interpretation of the statements, the overall findings robustly indicate that “true” has multiple meanings in the realm of empirical matters.

通过一系列以英语、德语和汉语为母语的实证研究,本文揭示了谓词 "true "在实证领域中的内在模糊性。诸如 "汤姆参加聚会是真的 "这样的真理陈述似乎在两种解读之间摇摆不定。在第一种解读中,这句话的意思是 "现实就是这样,汤姆在聚会上"。在第二种解读中,这句话的意思是 "根据 X 所相信的,汤姆在派对上"。虽然对语句的解释似乎存在一些跨文化差异,但总体研究结果有力地表明,"真实 "在经验问题上具有多重含义。
{"title":"The ambiguity of “true” in English, German, and Chinese","authors":"Kevin Reuter","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00150-1","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00150-1","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Through a series of empirical studies involving native speakers of English, German, and Chinese, this paper reveals that the predicate “true” is inherently ambiguous in the empirical domain. Truth statements such as “It is true that Tom is at the party” seem to be ambivalent between two readings. On the first reading, the statement means “Reality is such that Tom is at the party.” On the second reading, the statement means “According to what <i>X</i> believes, Tom is at the party.” While there appear to exist some cross-cultural differences in the interpretation of the statements, the overall findings robustly indicate that “true” has multiple meanings in the realm of empirical matters.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-04-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007/s44204-024-00150-1.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140701751","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Replies to critics 对批评者的答复
Pub Date : 2024-04-13 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00159-6
Eva Schmidt

In these replies, I react to comments on my paper “Facts about Incoherence as Non-Evidential Epistemic Reasons”, provided by Aleks Knoks, Sebastian Schmidt, Keshav Singh, and Conor McHugh. I discuss potential counterexamples to my claim that the fact that the subject’s doxastic attitudes are incoherent is an epistemic reason for her to suspend; whether such incoherence-based reasons bear on individual attitudes or only on combinations of attitudes; the prospects of restricting evidentialism about epistemic reasons to reasons to believe; whether incoherence-based reasons are truly epistemic; the alleged normative and motivational expendability of incoherence-based reasons; the possibility of incoherence-based reasons to suspend without actual belief in the incoherent propositions; the relationship between suspension, inquiry, and incoherence; and the nature of suspension of judgment.

在这些答复中,我回应了阿列克斯-克诺克斯、塞巴斯蒂安-施密特、凯沙夫-辛格和康纳-麦克休对我的论文 "作为非证据认识论理由的不一致性事实 "的评论。我的主张是,主体的逻各斯态度不一致这一事实是她中止的认识论理由,我讨论了这一主张的潜在反例;这种基于不一致的理由是对个别态度有影响,还是只对态度的组合有影响;将认识论理由的证据主义限制为相信理由的前景;基于不连贯的理由是否真正属于认识论的理由;基于不连贯的理由在规范和动机上的所谓消耗性;基于不连贯的理由在不实际相信不连贯命题的情况下中止的可能性;中止、探究和不连贯之间的关系;以及中止判断的性质。
{"title":"Replies to critics","authors":"Eva Schmidt","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00159-6","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00159-6","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>In these replies, I react to comments on my paper “Facts about Incoherence as Non-Evidential Epistemic Reasons”, provided by Aleks Knoks, Sebastian Schmidt, Keshav Singh, and Conor McHugh. I discuss potential counterexamples to my claim that the fact that the subject’s doxastic attitudes are incoherent is an epistemic reason for her to suspend; whether such incoherence-based reasons bear on individual attitudes or only on combinations of attitudes; the prospects of restricting evidentialism about epistemic reasons to reasons to believe; whether incoherence-based reasons are truly epistemic; the alleged normative and motivational expendability of incoherence-based reasons; the possibility of incoherence-based reasons to suspend without actual belief in the incoherent propositions; the relationship between suspension, inquiry, and incoherence; and the nature of suspension of judgment.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-04-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007/s44204-024-00159-6.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140707271","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Inconsistent metaphysical dependence: cases from the Kyoto School 不一致的形而上学依赖:京都学派的案例
Pub Date : 2024-04-12 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00155-w
Filippo Casati, Naoya Fujikawa

Even though metaphysical dependence has been a subject of a lively debate in contemporary metaphysics, it is rare in such a debate to seriously consider the possibility that the metaphysical dependence relations among the things in the reality is inconsistent. This paper focuses on two philosophers of the Kyoto School, Kitaro Nishida and Keiji Nishitani, who challenge the common supposition that the structure of reality is consistent. In this paper, we show that Nishida’s logic of place is a version of inconsistent foundationalism, according to which absolute nothingness as a foundational element does not depend on anything but depends on itself, and that Nishtani’s theory of the field of emptiness is a version of inconsistent coherentism, according to which emptiness does not depend on anything but depends on everything else (and possibly on itself).

尽管形而上学的依存关系一直是当代形而上学热烈讨论的主题,但在这样的讨论中,认真思考现实中事物之间的形而上学依存关系不一致的可能性却是罕见的。本文聚焦于京都学派的两位哲学家--西田喜太郎和西谷圭司,他们对 "现实的结构是一致的 "这一普遍假设提出了质疑。在本文中,我们证明了西田的位置逻辑是不一致基础主义的一个版本,根据这一版本,作为基础要素的绝对虚无不依赖于任何事物,而是依赖于自身;而西谷的虚无场理论是不一致一致性主义的一个版本,根据这一版本,虚无不依赖于任何事物,而是依赖于其他一切(也可能依赖于自身)。
{"title":"Inconsistent metaphysical dependence: cases from the Kyoto School","authors":"Filippo Casati,&nbsp;Naoya Fujikawa","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00155-w","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00155-w","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Even though metaphysical dependence has been a subject of a lively debate in contemporary metaphysics, it is rare in such a debate to seriously consider the possibility that the metaphysical dependence relations among the things in the reality is inconsistent. This paper focuses on two philosophers of the Kyoto School, Kitaro Nishida and Keiji Nishitani, who challenge the common supposition that the structure of reality is consistent. In this paper, we show that Nishida’s logic of place is a version of inconsistent foundationalism, according to which absolute nothingness as a foundational element does not depend on anything but depends on itself, and that Nishtani’s theory of the field of emptiness is a version of inconsistent coherentism, according to which emptiness does not depend on anything but depends on everything else (and possibly on itself).</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-04-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007/s44204-024-00155-w.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140712289","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
On the causal arguments for physicalism 关于物理主义的因果论证
Pub Date : 2024-04-03 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00156-9
Wenjun Zhang

In his paper, “A Causal Argument for Physicalism” (Zhong, 2023), Zhong presents a novel argument for non-reductive physicalism (which he calls “A2”), based on the causal argument for reductive physicalism (which he calls “A1”), and claims that A2 is better than A1 since the premises in A2 are more plausible than those in A1. In this paper, I will argue that A2 fails to be a sound argument for non-reductive physicalism, or even physicalism per se, because the premises in A2 can be fulfilled by the kind of dualism which claims that the physical event (P), the mental event (M), and their effect (E) form a causal chain and that P and M are simultaneous causes. Also, I will argue that we do have ways to strengthen A2 to block the aforementioned problem. But the only plausible way to strengthen the argument is to appeal to the conservation of energy and momentum. And this favors A1 more than A2. So, I conclude that A2 is not better than A1, and a causal argument for physicalism still naturally favors reductive physicalism.

在他的论文《物理主义的因果论证》(Zhong, 2023)中,Zhong 以还原物理主义的因果论证(他称之为 "A1")为基础,为非还原物理主义提出了一个新颖的论证(他称之为 "A2"),并声称 A2 比 A1 更好,因为 A2 中的前提比 A1 中的前提更可信。在本文中,我将论证 A2 不能成为非还原物理主义甚至物理主义本身的合理论证,因为 A2 中的前提可以通过二元论来实现,即物理事件(P)、心理事件(M)和它们的影响(E)构成一个因果链,并且 P 和 M 是同时存在的原因。此外,我还将论证,我们确实有办法强化 A2,以阻止上述问题的出现。但加强论证的唯一可行方法是诉诸能量和动量守恒。而这对 A1 比对 A2 更有利。因此,我的结论是,A2并不比A1更好,物理主义的因果论证仍然自然地倾向于还原物理主义。
{"title":"On the causal arguments for physicalism","authors":"Wenjun Zhang","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00156-9","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00156-9","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>In his paper, “A Causal Argument for Physicalism” (Zhong, 2023), Zhong presents a novel argument for non-reductive physicalism (which he calls “A2”), based on the causal argument for reductive physicalism (which he calls “A1”), and claims that A2 is better than A1 since the premises in A2 are more plausible than those in A1. In this paper, I will argue that A2 fails to be a sound argument for non-reductive physicalism, or even physicalism <i>per se</i>, because the premises in A2 can be fulfilled by the kind of dualism which claims that the physical event (P), the mental event (M), and their effect (E) form a causal chain and that P and M are simultaneous causes. Also, I will argue that we do have ways to strengthen A2 to block the aforementioned problem. But the only plausible way to strengthen the argument is to appeal to the conservation of energy and momentum. And this favors A1 more than A2. So, I conclude that A2 is not better than A1, and a causal argument for physicalism still naturally favors reductive physicalism.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-04-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140749804","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Truth in philosophy: a conceptual engineering approach 哲学中的真理:概念工程学方法
Pub Date : 2024-03-16 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00151-0
Jennifer Nado

The focus of this paper will be to examine the implications that a “practical” approach to conceptual engineering might have for the “traditional” conception of philosophy as uncovering truths about phenomena of philosophical interest. In doing so, I will be building on the ideas of a figure that many take to be the first major philosopher to write on conceptual engineering: Rudolf Carnap. Though the current wave of interest in conceptual engineering goes back less than a decade, many conceptual engineers have found precedent for their views in Carnap’s characterization of what he called “explication.” Interestingly, however, not nearly as much attention has been paid to another Carnapian thesis which seems to me to have deep relevance to methodological questions about conceptual engineering. I have in mind here the distinction between internal and external questions proposed in “Empiricism, Semantics and Ontology” (1950b) and the accompanying claim that external questions lack cognitive content and can be cogently approached only as a matter of pragmatic decision-making. This is the aspect of Carnap’s views upon which I propose to build. I'll first make the case that there is a suggestive similarity between Carnap’s claim that external questions are matters of pragmatic choice and the practical conceptual engineer’s claim that engineering success should be characterized in terms of suitability to a function or purpose. After that, I'll look at potential worries about the Carnapian distinction—including, e.g., the concern that it relies on the analytic/synthetic distinction. Finally, I will propose a somewhat modified and expanded version of the distinction and examine its consequences for the thesis that philosophy aims at discovering truths about phenomena of philosophical interest.

本文的重点是探讨概念工程学的 "实践 "方法对哲学作为揭示哲学感兴趣的现象的真理的 "传统 "概念可能产生的影响。在此过程中,我将借鉴被许多人视为第一位撰写概念工程学著作的主要哲学家的思想:鲁道夫-卡尔纳普(Rudolf Carnap)。尽管目前对概念工程学的兴趣浪潮可以追溯到不到十年前,但许多概念工程师已经从卡尔纳普对他所谓的 "阐释 "的描述中找到了他们观点的先例。然而,有趣的是,人们对卡尔纳普的另一个论点的关注却远远不够,在我看来,这个论点与概念工程学的方法论问题有着深刻的关联。在这里,我想到了《经验主义、语义学与本体论》(1950b)中提出的内部问题与外部问题之间的区别,以及随之而来的说法,即外部问题缺乏认知内容,只能作为实用决策问题来有说服力地处理。卡纳普的观点正是基于这一点提出的。我将首先论证,在卡纳普关于外部问题是实用选择问题的主张与实用概念工程师关于工程成功的特征应该是对功能或目的的适合性的主张之间,存在着暗示性的相似之处。之后,我将探讨对卡尔纳普区分的潜在担忧--包括对它依赖于分析/合成区分的担忧。最后,我将提出一个稍作修改和扩展的区分版本,并考察其对哲学旨在发现哲学感兴趣的现象的真理这一论点的影响。
{"title":"Truth in philosophy: a conceptual engineering approach","authors":"Jennifer Nado","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00151-0","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00151-0","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>The focus of this paper will be to examine the implications that a “practical” approach to conceptual engineering might have for the “traditional” conception of philosophy as uncovering truths about phenomena of philosophical interest. In doing so, I will be building on the ideas of a figure that many take to be the first major philosopher to write on conceptual engineering: Rudolf Carnap. Though the current wave of interest in conceptual engineering goes back less than a decade, many conceptual engineers have found precedent for their views in Carnap’s characterization of what he called “explication.” Interestingly, however, not nearly as much attention has been paid to another Carnapian thesis which seems to me to have deep relevance to methodological questions about conceptual engineering. I have in mind here the distinction between internal and external questions proposed in “Empiricism, Semantics and Ontology” (1950b) and the accompanying claim that external questions lack cognitive content and can be cogently approached only as a matter of pragmatic decision-making. This is the aspect of Carnap’s views upon which I propose to build. I'll first make the case that there is a suggestive similarity between Carnap’s claim that external questions are matters of pragmatic choice and the practical conceptual engineer’s claim that engineering success should be characterized in terms of suitability to a function or purpose. After that, I'll look at potential worries about the Carnapian distinction—including, e.g., the concern that it relies on the analytic/synthetic distinction. Finally, I will propose a somewhat modified and expanded version of the distinction and examine its consequences for the thesis that philosophy aims at discovering truths about phenomena of philosophical interest.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-03-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007/s44204-024-00151-0.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140236855","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Looking across languages: Anglocentrism, cross-linguistic experimental philosophy, and the future of inquiry about truth 跨越语言:盎格鲁中心主义、跨语言实验哲学和探究真理的未来
Pub Date : 2024-03-13 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00148-9
Jeremy Wyatt, Joseph Ulatowski

Analytic debates about truth are wide-ranging, but certain key themes tend to crop up time and again. The three themes that we will examine in this paper are (i) the nature and behaviour of the ordinary concept of truth, (ii) the meaning of discourse about truth, and (iii) the nature of the property truth. We will start by offering a brief overview of the debates centring on these themes. We will then argue that cross-linguistic experimental philosophy has an indispensable yet underappreciated role to play in all of these debates. Recognising the indispensability of cross-linguistic experimental philosophy should compel philosophers to significantly revise the ways in which they inquire about truth. It should also prompt analytic philosophers more generally to consider whether similar revisions might be necessary elsewhere in the field.

关于真理的分析辩论范围广泛,但某些关键主题往往会反复出现。本文将探讨的三个主题是:(i) 普通真理概念的性质和行为;(ii) 关于真理的话语的意义;(iii) 真理属性的性质。首先,我们将简要概述围绕这些主题展开的争论。然后,我们将论证跨语言实验哲学在所有这些争论中不可或缺但却未被充分重视的作用。认识到跨语言实验哲学的不可或缺性,应迫使哲学家们对他们探究真理的方式进行重大修正。它还应促使分析哲学家们更普遍地考虑,在该领域的其他地方是否也需要类似的修正。
{"title":"Looking across languages: Anglocentrism, cross-linguistic experimental philosophy, and the future of inquiry about truth","authors":"Jeremy Wyatt,&nbsp;Joseph Ulatowski","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00148-9","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00148-9","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Analytic debates about truth are wide-ranging, but certain key themes tend to crop up time and again. The three themes that we will examine in this paper are (i) the nature and behaviour of the ordinary concept of truth, (ii) the meaning of discourse about truth, and (iii) the nature of the property <i>truth</i>. We will start by offering a brief overview of the debates centring on these themes. We will then argue that <i>cross-linguistic experimental philosophy</i> has an indispensable yet underappreciated role to play in all of these debates. Recognising the indispensability of cross-linguistic experimental philosophy should compel philosophers to significantly revise the ways in which they inquire about truth. It should also prompt analytic philosophers more generally to consider whether similar revisions might be necessary elsewhere in the field.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-03-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007/s44204-024-00148-9.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140246987","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Nāgārjuna and Vasubandhu on the principle of sufficient reason 那跋陀罗和瓦苏班杜论充足理由原则
Pub Date : 2024-03-13 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00142-1
Allison Aitken

Canonical defenders of the principle of sufficient reason (PSR), such as Leibniz and Spinoza, are metaphysical foundationalists of one stripe or another. This is curious since the PSR—which says that everything has a ground, cause, or explanation—in effect, denies fundamental entities. In this paper, I explore the apparent inconsistency between metaphysical foundationalism and approaches to metaphysical system building that are driven by a commitment to the PSR. I do so by analyzing how Indian Buddhist philosophers arrive at foundationalist and anti-foundationalist positions motivated by implicit commitments to different versions of the PSR. I begin by introducing the Buddhist principle of dependent origination (pratītyasamutpāda) as a proto-PSR that is restricted to causal explanation. Next, I show how Vasubandhu’s Sautrāntika Abhidharma metaphysics is shaped by a qualified commitment to both causal and metaphysical grounding versions of the PSR. I then reveal how Nāgārjuna’s Madhyamaka metaphysics is driven by an unrestricted and exceptionless commitment to causal and metaphysical grounding versions of the PSR. Finally, I consider how Nāgārjuna’s account may put him in a unique position to respond to a common contemporary objection to the PSR from necessitarianism. I conclude by addressing a competing interpretation on which Nāgārjuna is best understood as an anti-rationalist rather than an uber-rationalist, as I characterize him.

充足理由原则(PSR)的典型捍卫者,如莱布尼茨和斯宾诺莎,都是形而上学的基础论者。这一点很奇怪,因为充足理由原则认为万事万物都有根据、原因或解释,这实际上否认了基本实体。在本文中,我将探讨形而上学基础论与形而上学体系构建方法之间的明显不一致之处。为此,我分析了印度佛教哲学家是如何在对不同版本的 PSR 的隐性承诺的驱使下达成基础主义和反基础主义立场的。首先,我介绍了佛教的依他起性原则(pratītyasamutpāda),将其视为仅限于因果解释的原初 PSR。接下来,我将说明瓦苏班杜的 Sautrāntika Abhidharma 形而上学是如何通过对 PSR 的因果和形而上学基础版本的限定性承诺而形成的。然后,我将揭示那跋陀罗的偈颂形而上学是如何被对因果论和形而上学基础版本的 PSR 的无限制和无例外的承诺所驱动的。最后,我将考虑那跋陀罗的论述如何使他处于一个独特的位置,以回应当代人从必然性出发对 PSR 提出的常见反对意见。最后,我将讨论一种相互竞争的解释,根据这种解释,那伽牟尼最好被理解为反理性主义者,而不是我所描述的超级理性主义者。
{"title":"Nāgārjuna and Vasubandhu on the principle of sufficient reason","authors":"Allison Aitken","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00142-1","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00142-1","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Canonical defenders of the <i>principle of sufficient reason</i> (PSR), such as Leibniz and Spinoza, are metaphysical foundationalists of one stripe or another. This is curious since the PSR—which says that everything has a ground, cause, or explanation—in effect, denies fundamental entities. In this paper, I explore the apparent inconsistency between metaphysical foundationalism and approaches to metaphysical system building that are driven by a commitment to the PSR. I do so by analyzing how Indian Buddhist philosophers arrive at foundationalist and anti-foundationalist positions motivated by implicit commitments to different versions of the PSR. I begin by introducing the Buddhist <i>principle of dependent origination</i> (<i>pratītyasamutpāda</i>) as a proto-PSR that is restricted to causal explanation. Next, I show how Vasubandhu’s Sautrāntika Abhidharma metaphysics is shaped by a qualified commitment to both causal and metaphysical grounding versions of the PSR. I then reveal how Nāgārjuna’s Madhyamaka metaphysics is driven by an unrestricted and exceptionless commitment to causal and metaphysical grounding versions of the PSR. Finally, I consider how Nāgārjuna’s account may put him in a unique position to respond to a common contemporary objection to the PSR from necessitarianism. I conclude by addressing a competing interpretation on which Nāgārjuna is best understood as an anti-rationalist rather than an uber-rationalist, as I characterize him.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-03-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140247085","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Meta-metaphysics, constructivism, and psychology as queen of the sciences 元形而上学、建构主义和作为科学女王的心理学
Pub Date : 2024-03-12 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00154-x
James A. Mollison

Remhof contends that Nietzsche is a metaphysician. According to his Meta-Metaphysical Argument, Nietzsche’s texts satisfy the criteria for an adequate conception of metaphysics. According to his Constructivist Argument, Nietzsche adopts a metaphysical position on which concepts’ application conditions constitute the identity conditions of their objects. This article critically appraises these arguments. I maintain that the criteria advanced in the Meta-Metaphysical Argument are collectively insufficient for delineating metaphysics as a distinct field of inquiry and that the Constructivist Argument attributes a position to Nietzsche that remains vulnerable to his evaluative and psychological indictments of two-world metaphysics. I conclude by discussing how these objections might help non-metaphysical readers of Nietzsche resist Remhof’s interpretation.

Remhof 认为尼采是一位形而上学家。根据他的元形而上学论证,尼采的文本符合形而上学适当概念的标准。根据他的建构主义论证,尼采采取的形而上学立场是,概念的应用条件构成其对象的同一条件。本文对这些论点进行了批判性的评价。我认为,元形而上学论证中提出的标准总体上不足以将形而上学划分为一个独特的研究领域,而且建构主义论证赋予尼采的立场仍然容易受到他对两个世界形而上学的评价性和心理学控诉的影响。最后,我将讨论这些反对意见如何帮助尼采的非形而上学读者抵制雷姆霍夫的阐释。
{"title":"Meta-metaphysics, constructivism, and psychology as queen of the sciences","authors":"James A. Mollison","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00154-x","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00154-x","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Remhof contends that Nietzsche is a metaphysician. According to his Meta-Metaphysical Argument, Nietzsche’s texts satisfy the criteria for an adequate conception of metaphysics. According to his Constructivist Argument, Nietzsche adopts a metaphysical position on which concepts’ application conditions constitute the identity conditions of their objects. This article critically appraises these arguments. I maintain that the criteria advanced in the Meta-Metaphysical Argument are collectively insufficient for delineating metaphysics as a distinct field of inquiry and that the Constructivist Argument attributes a position to Nietzsche that remains vulnerable to his evaluative and psychological indictments of two-world metaphysics. I conclude by discussing how these objections might help non-metaphysical readers of Nietzsche resist Remhof’s interpretation.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-03-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140248784","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Nietzsche as metaphysician but which metaphysics? A response to Justin Remhof 尼采是形而上学家,但又是哪种形而上学?回应贾斯汀-雷姆霍夫
Pub Date : 2024-03-10 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00153-y
Tsarina Doyle

This article is a critical response to Justin Remhof’s Nietzsche as Metaphysician. It contends that Remhof runs the question of whether Nietzsche is a metaphysician too closely with the related but separate question of what type of metaphysician he is. It is argued that Remhof is correct in claiming that Nietzsche is a metaphysician and that his metaphysics informs his wider philosophy. However, Remhof’s view that Nietzsche is a metaphysical constructivist is subject to criticism.

本文是对 Justin Remhof 的《作为形而上学家的尼采》的批判性回应。文章认为,雷姆霍夫将尼采是否是形而上学家的问题与尼采是哪种类型的形而上学家这一相关但独立的问题联系得过于紧密。文章认为,雷姆霍夫关于尼采是形而上学家的说法是正确的,他的形而上学为他更广泛的哲学提供了信息。然而,雷姆霍夫关于尼采是形而上学建构主义者的观点受到了批评。
{"title":"Nietzsche as metaphysician but which metaphysics? A response to Justin Remhof","authors":"Tsarina Doyle","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00153-y","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00153-y","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>This article is a critical response to Justin Remhof’s <i>Nietzsche as Metaphysician.</i> It contends that Remhof runs the question of whether Nietzsche is a metaphysician too closely with the related but separate question of what type of metaphysician he is. It is argued that Remhof is correct in claiming that Nietzsche is a metaphysician and that his metaphysics informs his wider philosophy. However, Remhof’s view that Nietzsche is a metaphysical constructivist is subject to criticism.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-03-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007/s44204-024-00153-y.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140255036","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Asian journal of philosophy
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1