首页 > 最新文献

Asian journal of philosophy最新文献

英文 中文
Sosa’s virtue account vs. responsibilism 索萨的美德论与责任论
Pub Date : 2024-06-03 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00170-x
Xingming Hu

I first present a brief interpretation of Sosa’s virtue epistemology by showing how it is arguably better than Goldman’s process reliabilism, why Sosa distinguishes between animal knowledge and reflective knowledge, and how Sosa’s recent account of knowing full well can deal with pragmatic encroachment. Then, I raise two worries about Sosa’s account: (a) Sosa’s claim that one might have animal knowledge without knowing reflectively or knowing full well implies that one’s true belief might manifest both competence and luck, which seems to pose a challenge to Sosa’s solution to the Gettier problem; (b) intellectual virtue or competence does not seem to be a necessary condition for knowledge: there are cases where one knows without possessing the relevant intellectual virtue or competence. Finally, I suggest a responsibilist account of knowledge and show how it can not only handle the cases that pose a problem for Sosa’s account but also explain our intuitions about different grades of knowledge.

我首先简要阐释了索萨的美德认识论,说明它如何可以说比戈德曼的过程可靠论更好,为什么索萨区分了动物性知识和反思性知识,以及索萨最近关于 "完全知道 "的论述如何能够应对实用主义的侵蚀。然后,我对索萨的论述提出两点担忧:(a) 索萨声称,一个人可能拥有动物知识而不反思性地知道或完全知道,这意味着一个人的真实信念可能同时体现出能力和运气,这似乎对索萨解决格蒂埃问题的方法提出了挑战;(b) 智力美德或能力似乎不是知识的必要条件:在有些情况下,一个人知道而不具备相关的智力美德或能力。最后,我提出了一个关于知识的责任主义解释,并说明它如何不仅能处理给索萨的解释带来问题的情况,而且还能解释我们对不同等级知识的直觉。
{"title":"Sosa’s virtue account vs. responsibilism","authors":"Xingming Hu","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00170-x","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00170-x","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>I first present a brief interpretation of Sosa’s virtue epistemology by showing how it is arguably better than Goldman’s process reliabilism, why Sosa distinguishes between animal knowledge and reflective knowledge, and how Sosa’s recent account of knowing full well can deal with pragmatic encroachment. Then, I raise two worries about Sosa’s account: (a) Sosa’s claim that one might have animal knowledge without knowing reflectively or knowing full well implies that one’s true belief might manifest <i>both</i> competence and luck, which seems to pose a challenge to Sosa’s solution to the Gettier problem; (b) intellectual virtue or competence does not seem to be a necessary condition for knowledge: there are cases where one knows without possessing the relevant intellectual virtue or competence. Finally, I suggest a responsibilist account of knowledge and show how it can not only handle the cases that pose a problem for Sosa’s account but also explain our intuitions about different grades of knowledge.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-06-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141271363","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
On Beall’s contradictory Christology and beyond 论比奥尔自相矛盾的基督论及其他
Pub Date : 2024-05-29 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00165-8
Filippo Casati, Naoya Fujikawa

According to Conciliar Christology, Christ has a divine nature and a human nature. This dual nature of Christ leads us to face many apparent inconsistencies: For example, it seems to follow that He is both immutable and mutable (and, therefore, not immutable). This long-standing issue in Christology has been called the fundamental problem of Christology. Recently, Jc Beall has proposed a novel approach to the fundamental problem: contradictory Christology, that is, Christology which takes those apparent inconsistencies as genuinely contradictory. This paper examines Beall’s contradictory Christology by comparing it with James Anderson’s version of consistent Christology. Such a comparison highlights an important assumption of Beall’s contradictory Christology, that is, the language used to state the fundamental problem is univocal. ‘Immutable’ is, thus, used in the same literal sense in both `Christ is immutable’ and `Christ is not immutable’. On the one hand, this assumption has a good reason given the human nature of Christ. On the other hand, we follow Anderson in showing that the view that `immutable’ is equivocal has a good reason too. For there is an established theological tradition according to which, when we speak about the divine, our language is analogical. In light of those considerations, this paper presents a semantic explication of how the predicates used to state the fundamental problem are both literal and analogical. The proposed semantics treats those predicates as cases of multiple denotations and shows that the apparent inconsistencies are genuinely contradictory, but in a different way from Beall’s contradictory Christology.

根据教会基督论,基督具有神性和人性。基督的这种双重性格使我们面临许多明显的矛盾:例如,祂似乎既是永恒不变的,又是可变的(因此不是永恒不变的)。基督论中的这一长期问题被称为基督论的基本问题。最近,比厄尔(Jc Beall)提出了一个解决这一根本问题的新方法:矛盾基督论,即把那些明显的不一致视为真正矛盾的基督论。本文通过比较比厄尔的矛盾基督论与詹姆斯-安德森(James Anderson)版本的一致基督论,对其进行了研究。这种比较凸显了比尔的矛盾基督论的一个重要假设,即阐述基本问题的语言是单一的。因此,在 "基督是永恒不变的 "和 "基督不是永恒不变的 "中,"永恒不变 "的字面意义是相同的。一方面,鉴于基督的人性,这一假设有其充分的理由。另一方面,我们追随安德森的观点,指出 "不可改变 "这一观点也有其合理性。因为有一种既定的神学传统认为,当我们谈论神性时,我们的语言是类比的。鉴于这些考虑,本文提出了一个语义学解释,说明用来陈述基本问题的谓词是如何既是字面的又是类比的。所提出的语义学将这些谓词视为多重指称的情况,并表明表面上的不一致确实是矛盾的,但其方式与比尔的矛盾基督论不同。
{"title":"On Beall’s contradictory Christology and beyond","authors":"Filippo Casati,&nbsp;Naoya Fujikawa","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00165-8","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00165-8","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>According to Conciliar Christology, Christ has a divine nature and a human nature. This dual nature of Christ leads us to face many apparent inconsistencies: For example, it seems to follow that He is both immutable and mutable (and, therefore, not immutable). This long-standing issue in Christology has been called the fundamental problem of Christology. Recently, Jc Beall has proposed a novel approach to the fundamental problem: <i>contradictory</i> Christology, that is, Christology which takes those apparent inconsistencies as genuinely contradictory. This paper examines Beall’s contradictory Christology by comparing it with James Anderson’s version of consistent Christology. Such a comparison highlights an important assumption of Beall’s contradictory Christology, that is, the language used to state the fundamental problem is <i>univocal</i>. ‘Immutable’ is, thus, used in the same <i>literal</i> sense in both `Christ is immutable’ and `Christ is not immutable’. On the one hand, this assumption has a good reason given the human nature of Christ. On the other hand, we follow Anderson in showing that the view that `immutable’ is <i>equivocal</i> has a good reason too. For there is an established theological tradition according to which, when we speak about the divine, our language is <i>analogical</i>. In light of those considerations, this paper presents a semantic explication of how the predicates used to state the fundamental problem are <i>both</i> literal and analogical. The proposed semantics treats those predicates as cases of multiple denotations and shows that the apparent inconsistencies are genuinely contradictory, but in a different way from Beall’s contradictory Christology.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007/s44204-024-00165-8.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142414972","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The truth conditions of sentences with referentially used definite descriptions 带有指代性定语描述的句子的真实条件
Pub Date : 2024-05-16 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00167-6
Wenqi Li

Keith Donnellan’s distinction between the attributive and referential uses of definite descriptions has spurred debates regarding the truth conditions of the utterance “the F is G” with definite descriptions used referentially. In this article, I present a semantic account of referential descriptions, grounded in the contextual factors of the utterance, including the speaker’s intention and presupposition as well as the interlocutor’s recognition of them. This account is called the IPR-semantic account, according to which the speaker’s intention (I) and presupposition (P) and the interlocutor’s recognition (R) jointly determine whether “the F” in an utterance “the F is G” is used referentially or attributively, and the meaning of “the F” is determined by whether it is used referentially or attributively. Moreover, I argue that the meaning of the referential description “the F” is the intended object e, embodied with a property H that has prompted the speaker to presuppose that e is F and to intend to use “the F” to refer to e, as well as the interlocutor to recognize the presupposition and intention. According to the IPR-semantic account, the utterance “the F is G” with “the F” used referentially expresses a singular proposition, namely, that e is G, and it is true if and only if the intended object e is G. Additionally, I argue that the IPR-semantic account not only surpasses some alternative semantic accounts but also outperforms Kripke’s pragmatic account.

Keith Donnellan 对定语描述的归属性使用和指称性使用所做的区分引发了关于 "the F is G "这一语句的真假条件的争论。在本文中,我提出了一种关于指称描述的语义解释,它以语篇的语境因素为基础,包括说话人的意图和预设以及对话者对它们的认识。根据这一观点,说话者的意图(I)和预设(P)以及对话者的认知(R)共同决定了 "F 是 G "语篇中的 "F "是指代性使用还是属性性使用,而 "F "的意义则取决于它是指代性使用还是属性性使用。此外,我还认为,"F "这一指称性描述的意义是意指的对象 e,它体现的属性 H 促使说话者预设 e 是 F,并打算用 "F "来指称 e,同时也促使对话者认识到这一预设和意图。根据 IPR 语义账户,"该 F 是 G"("该 F "是指代性地使用的)这一语篇表达了一个单数命题,即 e 是 G,并且当且仅当预期对象 e 是 G 时,该命题才为真。
{"title":"The truth conditions of sentences with referentially used definite descriptions","authors":"Wenqi Li","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00167-6","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00167-6","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Keith Donnellan’s distinction between the attributive and referential uses of definite descriptions has spurred debates regarding the truth conditions of the utterance “the F is G” with definite descriptions used referentially. In this article, I present a semantic account of referential descriptions, grounded in the contextual factors of the utterance, including the speaker’s intention and presupposition as well as the interlocutor’s recognition of them. This account is called the IPR-semantic account, according to which the speaker’s intention (I) and presupposition (P) and the interlocutor’s recognition (R) jointly determine whether “the F” in an utterance “the F is G” is used referentially or attributively, and the meaning of “the F” is determined by whether it is used referentially or attributively. Moreover, I argue that the meaning of the referential description “the F” is the intended object <i>e</i>, embodied with a property H that has prompted the speaker to presuppose that <i>e</i> is F and to intend to use “the F” to refer to <i>e</i>, as well as the interlocutor to recognize the presupposition and intention. According to the IPR-semantic account, the utterance “the F is G” with “the F” used referentially expresses a singular proposition, namely, that <i>e</i> is G, and it is true if and only if the intended object <i>e</i> is G. Additionally, I argue that the IPR-semantic account not only surpasses some alternative semantic accounts but also outperforms Kripke’s pragmatic account.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140969560","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Parfitian or Buddhist reductionism? Revisiting a debate about personal identity 帕菲特主义还是佛教还原论?重温关于个人身份的辩论
Pub Date : 2024-05-14 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00166-7
Javier Hidalgo

Derek Parfit influentially defends reductionism about persons, the view that a person’s existence just consists in the existence of a brain and body and the occurrence of a series of physical and mental events. Yet some critics, particularly Mark Johnston, have raised powerful objections to Parfit’s reductionism. In this paper, I defend reductionism against Johnston. In particular, I defend a radical form of reductionism that Buddhist philosophers developed. Buddhist reductionism can justify key features of Parfit’s position, such as the claims that personal identity is not what matters and can also be indeterminate. Furthermore, Buddhist reductionism can avoid Johnston’s objections to Parfit’s reductionism. I conclude that reductionists have good reasons to favor Buddhist reductionism over Parfit’s version.

德里克-帕菲特(Derek Parfit)为人的还原论辩护,认为人的存在仅仅是大脑和身体的存在,以及一系列生理和心理事件的发生。然而,一些批评家,尤其是马克-约翰斯顿(Mark Johnston),对帕菲特的还原论提出了强烈的反对意见。在本文中,我将针对约翰斯顿为还原论辩护。特别是,我为佛教哲学家所发展的一种激进形式的还原论辩护。佛教还原论可以证明帕菲特立场的关键特征是正确的,例如个人身份并不重要,而且也可以是不确定的。此外,佛教还原论可以避免约翰斯顿对帕菲特还原论的反对。我的结论是,还原论者有充分的理由支持佛教还原论,而不是帕菲特的版本。
{"title":"Parfitian or Buddhist reductionism? Revisiting a debate about personal identity","authors":"Javier Hidalgo","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00166-7","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00166-7","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Derek Parfit influentially defends reductionism about persons, the view that a person’s existence just consists in the existence of a brain and body and the occurrence of a series of physical and mental events. Yet some critics, particularly Mark Johnston, have raised powerful objections to Parfit’s reductionism. In this paper, I defend reductionism against Johnston. In particular, I defend a radical form of reductionism that Buddhist philosophers developed. Buddhist reductionism can justify key features of Parfit’s position, such as the claims that personal identity is not what matters and can also be indeterminate. Furthermore, Buddhist reductionism can avoid Johnston’s objections to Parfit’s reductionism. I conclude that reductionists have good reasons to favor Buddhist reductionism over Parfit’s version.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007/s44204-024-00166-7.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140979143","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Frankfurt’s concept of identification 法兰克福的认同概念
Pub Date : 2024-05-08 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00168-5
Chen Yajun

Harry Frankfurt had insightfully pointed out that an agent acts freely when he acts in accord with the mental states with which he identifies. The concept of identification rightly captures the ownership condition (something being one’s really own), which plays a significant role in the issues of freedom and moral responsibility. For Frankfurt, identification consists of one’s forming second-order volitions, endorsing first-order desires, and issuing in his actions wholeheartedly. An agent not only wants to φ but also fully embraces his desire to φ (and φ). Frankfurt’s official theory above encounters some serious problems, especially since it is believed that his concept of wholehearted identification is too strong to be necessary for freedom. In this paper, I propose that we can uncouple identification from wholeheartedness and thus get two different senses of identification: weak identification and strong identification. Then, I argue that this distinction does a better job than Frankfurt’s official theory. On the one hand, weak identification is enough for ownership and freedom and thus more promising than strong identification; on the other hand, this distinction has an attractive implication that it fits well with our intuition about the degree of freedom and responsibility.

哈里-法兰克福曾精辟地指出,当行为人的行为符合他所认同的心理状态时,他就是自由的。认同的概念正确地捕捉到了所有权条件(某物真正属于自己),这在自由和道德责任问题上起着重要作用。在法兰克福看来,认同包括一个人形成二阶意志,认可一阶欲望,并全心全意地付诸行动。行为者不仅希望φ,而且完全接受他对φ(和φ)的渴望。法兰克福的上述官方理论遇到了一些严重的问题,尤其是有人认为他的 "全心全意认同 "概念过于强烈,不是自由所必需的。在本文中,我提出我们可以将认同与全心全意脱钩,从而得到两种不同意义上的认同:弱认同和强认同。然后,我认为这种区分比法兰克福的官方理论做得更好。一方面,弱认同足以实现所有权和自由,因此比强认同更有前途;另一方面,这种区分具有一种诱人的含义,即它非常符合我们对自由和责任程度的直觉。
{"title":"Frankfurt’s concept of identification","authors":"Chen Yajun","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00168-5","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00168-5","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Harry Frankfurt had insightfully pointed out that an agent acts freely when he acts in accord with the mental states with which he identifies. The concept of identification rightly captures the ownership condition (something being one’s really own), which plays a significant role in the issues of freedom and moral responsibility. For Frankfurt, identification consists of one’s forming second-order volitions, endorsing first-order desires, and issuing in his actions wholeheartedly. An agent not only wants to φ but also fully embraces his desire to φ (and φ). Frankfurt’s official theory above encounters some serious problems, especially since it is believed that his concept of wholehearted identification is too strong to be necessary for freedom. In this paper, I propose that we can uncouple identification from wholeheartedness and thus get two different senses of identification: weak identification and strong identification. Then, I argue that this distinction does a better job than Frankfurt’s official theory. On the one hand, weak identification is enough for ownership and freedom and thus more promising than strong identification; on the other hand, this distinction has an attractive implication that it fits well with our intuition about the degree of freedom and responsibility.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141000905","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Contextual approaches to combating fake news: lessons from Thailand 根据具体情况打击假新闻:泰国的经验教训
Pub Date : 2024-05-01 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00162-x
Siraprapa Chavanayarn

The pervasive issue of fake news poses a formidable challenge to knowledge acquisition, further complicated by the difficulty in distinguishing it from legitimate information due to human epistemic limitations. This article argues for the necessity of adopting contextual strategies to effectively combat the spread of fake news. Through a focused examination of COVID-19-related fake news in Thailand, it explores how unique national characteristics can shape tailored approaches to mitigate this problem. The analysis draws on the theoretical insights of David Coady and Regina Rini, advocating for the integration of an open science framework to enhance transparency and public access to information. Despite the potential benefits of an open science culture, the persistence of epistemic vices among the populace may limit its effectiveness in reducing the acceptance of fake news. This article proposes that, instead of using law enforcement or fact-checking organizations, the Thai government and media entities play a critical role in addressing epistemic shortcomings and fostering epistemic virtues. However, it emphasizes that the effectiveness of these approaches is contingent upon their adaptability to the socio-cultural and epistemological context of Thailand. The discussion highlights the importance of recognizing and accommodating these contextual differences in devising strategies against the dissemination of fake news.

无处不在的假新闻问题给知识获取带来了巨大挑战,而由于人类认识论的局限性,很难将假新闻与合法信息区分开来,这使得问题变得更加复杂。本文论证了采用语境策略有效打击假新闻传播的必要性。通过对泰国与 COVID-19 相关的假新闻的重点研究,文章探讨了独特的国家特征如何形成有针对性的方法来缓解这一问题。分析借鉴了戴维-科迪(David Coady)和雷吉娜-里尼(Regina Rini)的理论见解,主张整合开放科学框架,以提高透明度和公众对信息的获取。尽管开放科学文化具有潜在的益处,但民众中持续存在的认识论恶习可能会限制其在减少假新闻接受度方面的有效性。本文建议,泰国政府和媒体实体在解决认识论缺陷和培养认识论美德方面发挥关键作用,而不是利用执法机构或事实核查组织。但讨论强调,这些方法的有效性取决于它们是否适应泰国的社会文化和认识论背景。讨论强调,在制定打击假新闻传播的战略时,必须认识到并适应这些背景差异。
{"title":"Contextual approaches to combating fake news: lessons from Thailand","authors":"Siraprapa Chavanayarn","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00162-x","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00162-x","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>The pervasive issue of fake news poses a formidable challenge to knowledge acquisition, further complicated by the difficulty in distinguishing it from legitimate information due to human epistemic limitations. This article argues for the necessity of adopting contextual strategies to effectively combat the spread of fake news. Through a focused examination of COVID-19-related fake news in Thailand, it explores how unique national characteristics can shape tailored approaches to mitigate this problem. The analysis draws on the theoretical insights of David Coady and Regina Rini, advocating for the integration of an open science framework to enhance transparency and public access to information. Despite the potential benefits of an open science culture, the persistence of epistemic vices among the populace may limit its effectiveness in reducing the acceptance of fake news. This article proposes that, instead of using law enforcement or fact-checking organizations, the Thai government and media entities play a critical role in addressing epistemic shortcomings and fostering epistemic virtues. However, it emphasizes that the effectiveness of these approaches is contingent upon their adaptability to the socio-cultural and epistemological context of Thailand. The discussion highlights the importance of recognizing and accommodating these contextual differences in devising strategies against the dissemination of fake news.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141053388","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The moving open future, temporal phenomenology, and temporal passage 移动的开放未来、时间现象学和时间流逝
Pub Date : 2024-05-01 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00157-8
Batoul Hodroj, Andrew J. Latham, Kristie Miller

Empirical evidence suggests that people naïvely represent time as dynamical (i.e. as containing robust temporal passage). Yet many contemporary B-theorists deny that it seems to us, in perceptual experience, as though time robustly passes. The question then arises as to why we represent time as dynamical if we do not have perceptual experiences which represent time as dynamical. We consider two hypotheses about why this might be: the temporally aperspectival replacement hypothesis and the moving open future hypothesis. We then empirically test the moving open future hypothesis. According to that hypothesis, we represent the past as objectively fixed and the future open. And we represent that this objective openness moves as events that were open become fixed, such that in doing so, we represent a privileged moving present. We found no evidence for the moving open future hypothesis, which suggests that further investigation of the temporally aperspectival replacement hypothesis is called for. Our results also shed further light on our understanding of the respects in which we represent the future to be open, which, in turn, has implications for our theorising about the open future.

经验证据表明,人们天真地认为时间是动态的(即包含稳健的时间流逝)。然而,许多当代 B 理论家否认,在我们的感知经验中,时间似乎是有力地流逝的。这就产生了一个问题:如果我们的知觉经验没有把时间表征为动态的,那么我们为什么要把时间表征为动态的?我们考虑了两种假设:时间上的非视角替代假设和移动的开放未来假设。然后,我们对移动的开放式未来假说进行了实证检验。根据这一假说,我们将过去客观地表述为固定的,而将未来表述为开放的。当开放的事件变成固定的事件时,这种客观的开放性就会发生移动,这样,我们就代表了一个具有特权的移动的现在。我们没有发现移动的开放未来假说的证据,这表明我们需要进一步研究时间非视角替换假说。我们的研究结果还进一步揭示了我们对未来开放性的理解,这反过来又对我们关于开放未来的理论研究产生了影响。
{"title":"The moving open future, temporal phenomenology, and temporal passage","authors":"Batoul Hodroj,&nbsp;Andrew J. Latham,&nbsp;Kristie Miller","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00157-8","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00157-8","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>Empirical evidence suggests that people naïvely represent time as dynamical (i.e. as containing robust temporal passage). Yet many contemporary B-theorists deny that it seems to us, in perceptual experience, as though time robustly passes. The question then arises as to why we represent time as dynamical if we do not have perceptual experiences which represent time as dynamical. We consider two hypotheses about why this might be: the temporally aperspectival replacement hypothesis and the moving open future hypothesis. We then empirically test the moving open future hypothesis. According to that hypothesis, we represent the past as objectively fixed and the future open. And we represent that this objective openness moves as events that were open become fixed, such that in doing so, we represent a privileged moving present. We found no evidence for the moving open future hypothesis, which suggests that further investigation of the temporally aperspectival replacement hypothesis is called for. Our results also shed further light on our understanding of the respects in which we represent the future to be open, which, in turn, has implications for our theorising about the open future.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-05-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007/s44204-024-00157-8.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141033302","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Legal proof: why knowledge matters and knowing does not 法律证明:为什么知识重要而知道不重要
Pub Date : 2024-04-30 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00163-w
Andy Mueller

I discuss the knowledge account of legal proof in Moss (2023) and develop an alternative. The unifying thread throughout this article are reflections on the beyond reasonable doubt (BRD) standard of proof.  In Section 1, I will introduce the details of Moss’s account and how she motivates it via the BRD standard. In Section 2, I will argue that there are important disanalogies between BRD and knowledge that undermine Moss’s argument. There is however another motivation for the knowledge account: combined with auxiliary claims, that is probabilistic knowledge and moral encroachment, it can provide a general solution to the puzzle of statistical evidence. Section 3 spells out the details. In Section 4, I suggest to combine the knowledge account with pragmatic encroachment, instead of moral encroachment, in order to stay clear of the thorny issues whether corporations have moral rights. In Section 5, I argue that the verdicts of Moss’s account in cases of false justified beliefs and non-luminous knowledge conflict with the BRD standard and thus call for abandoning the account. Based on the social function of the BRD standard, I suggest a replacement for the knowledge account that is also just as potent as a general solution for the puzzle of statistical evidence. While I will grant that knowledge is neither always necessary nor always sufficient for convictions, I will argue that the concept of knowledge nonetheless plays a significant and ineliminable role in legal decision-making.

我讨论了莫斯(2023 年)关于法律证明的知识论述,并提出了一个替代方案。本文的主线是对排除合理怀疑(BRD)证明标准的反思。 在第 1 节中,我将介绍莫斯论述的细节,以及她如何通过排除合理怀疑标准来推动论述。在第 2 节中,我将论证排除合理怀疑标准与知识之间存在重要的不相似性,从而削弱了莫斯的论证。然而,知识说还有另一个动机:结合辅助主张,即概率知识和道德侵蚀,知识说可以为统计证据之谜提供一个一般性的解决方案。第 3 节阐述了细节。在第 4 节中,我建议将知识论与实用主义侵占而非道德侵占结合起来,以避开公司是否拥有道德权利这一棘手问题。在第 5 节中,我认为莫斯的观点在虚假的正当信念和非明了知识的情况下与 BRD 标准相冲突,因此需要放弃该观点。基于 BRD 标准的社会功能,我提出了一种知识论的替代方案,它也同样是解决统计证据之谜的通用方案。虽然我承认知识对于定罪既不总是必要的,也不总是充分的,但我将论证知识的概念在法律决策中仍然发挥着重要的、不可磨灭的作用。
{"title":"Legal proof: why knowledge matters and knowing does not","authors":"Andy Mueller","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00163-w","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00163-w","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>I discuss the knowledge account of legal proof in Moss (2023) and develop an alternative. The unifying thread throughout this article are reflections on the beyond reasonable doubt (BRD) standard of proof.  In Section 1, I will introduce the details of Moss’s account and how she motivates it via the BRD standard. In Section 2, I will argue that there are important disanalogies between BRD and knowledge that undermine Moss’s argument. There is however another motivation for the knowledge account: combined with auxiliary claims, that is probabilistic knowledge and moral encroachment, it can provide a general solution to the puzzle of statistical evidence. Section 3 spells out the details. In Section 4, I suggest to combine the knowledge account with pragmatic encroachment, instead of moral encroachment, in order to stay clear of the thorny issues whether corporations have moral rights. In Section 5, I argue that the verdicts of Moss’s account in cases of false justified beliefs and non-luminous knowledge conflict with the BRD standard and thus call for abandoning the account. Based on the social function of the BRD standard, I suggest a replacement for the knowledge account that is also just as potent as a general solution for the puzzle of statistical evidence. While I will grant that knowledge is neither always necessary nor always sufficient for convictions, I will argue that the concept of knowledge nonetheless plays a significant and ineliminable role in legal decision-making.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-04-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007/s44204-024-00163-w.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142414981","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The significance of conceptualism in McDowell 麦克道尔概念主义的意义
Pub Date : 2024-04-30 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00161-y
Shao-An Hsu

To explain perceptual justification, McDowell proposes so-called “conceptualism,” the view that the content of experience is all conceptual. Tony Cheng, in his book, John McDowell on Worldly Subjectivity (2021), suggests that McDowell can do without conceptualism. To support his suggestion, Cheng makes several contentions against McDowell’s thesis of the co-extensiveness of conceptuality and rationality. In this commentary, I focus on two most crucial contentions Cheng makes: (i) conceptualism is an extra commitment for explaining perceptual justification and (ii) it can be replaced by a suitable structural constraint on non-conceptual content. First, I clarify McDowell’s co-extensiveness thesis and his conception of the conceptual. Then, based on my clarifications, I defend conceptualism against the two contentions.

为了解释知觉的合理性,麦克道尔提出了所谓的 "概念论",即认为经验的内容都是概念性的。托尼-郑(Tony Cheng)在其著作《约翰-麦克道尔论世俗主观性》(2021 年)中提出,麦克道尔可以不用概念论。为了支持他的建议,郑东明针对麦克道尔关于概念性与理性共存的论点提出了几个论点。在这篇评论中,我将重点论述程文所提出的两个最关键的论点:(i) 概念论是解释知觉合理性的额外承诺;(ii) 概念论可以被对非概念内容的适当结构性约束所取代。首先,我澄清了麦克道尔的共外延论和他的概念概念概念。然后,在澄清的基础上,我针对这两个论点为概念论辩护。
{"title":"The significance of conceptualism in McDowell","authors":"Shao-An Hsu","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00161-y","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00161-y","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>To explain perceptual justification, McDowell proposes so-called “conceptualism,” the view that the content of experience is all conceptual. Tony Cheng, in his book, <i>John McDowell on Worldly Subjectivity</i> (2021), suggests that McDowell can do without conceptualism. To support his suggestion, Cheng makes several contentions against McDowell’s thesis of the co-extensiveness of conceptuality and rationality. In this commentary, I focus on two most crucial contentions Cheng makes: (i) conceptualism is an extra commitment for explaining perceptual justification and (ii) it can be replaced by a suitable structural constraint on non-conceptual content. First, I clarify McDowell’s co-extensiveness thesis and his conception of the conceptual. Then, based on my clarifications, I defend conceptualism against the two contentions.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-04-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007/s44204-024-00161-y.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142414980","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Two in one: contradictory Christology without gluts? 二合一:自相矛盾的基督论,没有弊端?
Pub Date : 2024-04-22 DOI: 10.1007/s44204-024-00158-7
Franca d’Agostini

The central thesis of JC Beall’s paraconsistent Christology is that Christ, being human and divine, is a contradictory being, and a rational Christology can accept it, since logic nowadays does not exclude the possibility of true contradictions. In this paper, I move from Beall’s theory and I present an alternative view. I quote seven statements of the so-called ‘Athanasian Creed’ which synthesizes the results of conciliar Christology. The aim of the Creed is to combat monophysitism by stressing the duplicity and unity of Christ: two (incompatible) natures inseparably joined in only one person. I note that the two-in-one principle, so intended, may be seen as an ancestor of what has been called ‘conjunctive paraconsistency’, whereby there could be true contradictions but contradictories cannot be separately true. I specifically oppose this view to Beall’s idea of Christ’s human divinity (or divine humanity) as a glut, showing that in the conjunctive account, true contradictions do not require any overlapping or joint ascription of truth and falsity.

比厄尔(JC Beall)的准矛盾基督论的中心论点是,基督既是人又是神,是一个矛盾的存在,而理性的基督论可以接受这一点,因为当今的逻辑并不排除真实矛盾的可能性。在本文中,我从比厄尔的理论出发,提出了另一种观点。我引用了所谓的 "亚他那西信条 "中的七项声明,该信条综合了教会基督论的成果。信条的目的是通过强调基督的双重性和合一性:两个(互不相容的)本性不可分割地结合在一个人身上,来反对一元论。我注意到,二合一原则的本意可被视为所谓 "共轭准共性 "的祖先,即可能存在真正的矛盾,但矛盾不可能分别为真。我特别将这一观点与比厄尔关于基督的人类神性(或神圣人性)是一种 "麸质 "的观点对立起来,从而表明在 "连带 "论中,真正的矛盾并不需要任何重叠或共同的真假归属。
{"title":"Two in one: contradictory Christology without gluts?","authors":"Franca d’Agostini","doi":"10.1007/s44204-024-00158-7","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s44204-024-00158-7","url":null,"abstract":"<div><p>The central thesis of JC Beall’s paraconsistent Christology is that Christ, being human and divine, is a contradictory being, and a rational Christology can accept it, since logic nowadays does not exclude the possibility of true contradictions. In this paper, I move from Beall’s theory and I present an alternative view. I quote seven statements of the so-called ‘Athanasian Creed’ which synthesizes the results of conciliar Christology. The aim of the Creed is to combat monophysitism by stressing the duplicity and unity of Christ: two (incompatible) natures inseparably joined in only one person. I note that the two-in-one principle, so intended, may be seen as an ancestor of what has been called ‘conjunctive paraconsistency’, whereby there could be true contradictions but contradictories cannot be separately true. I specifically oppose this view to Beall’s idea of Christ’s human divinity (or divine humanity) as a glut, showing that in the conjunctive account, true contradictions do not require any overlapping or joint ascription of truth and falsity.</p></div>","PeriodicalId":93890,"journal":{"name":"Asian journal of philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2024-04-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007/s44204-024-00158-7.pdf","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140672912","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Asian journal of philosophy
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1