首页 > 最新文献

Journal of Medical Ethics最新文献

英文 中文
Designing AI for mental health diagnosis: responding to critics. 为心理健康诊断设计人工智能:回应批评者。
IF 3.3 2区 哲学 Q1 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-08-21 DOI: 10.1136/jme-2024-110244
Edmund Terem Ugar, Ntsumi Malele
{"title":"Designing AI for mental health diagnosis: responding to critics.","authors":"Edmund Terem Ugar, Ntsumi Malele","doi":"10.1136/jme-2024-110244","DOIUrl":"10.1136/jme-2024-110244","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":16317,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Medical Ethics","volume":" ","pages":"604-605"},"PeriodicalIF":3.3,"publicationDate":"2024-08-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141558958","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The unnecessary 'more'-compared to ROPA: a reply to Mangione. 不必要的 "更多"--与 ROPA 相比:回复 Mangione。
IF 3.3 2区 哲学 Q1 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-08-12 DOI: 10.1136/jme-2024-110285
Jolie Zhou

In her recent paper, Emanuele Mangione proposes combining maternal spindle transfer (MST) and reciprocal effortless in vitro fertilisation (ReIVF) to enable both females to have genetic and gestational ties with the same child, which can particularly benefit lesbian couples. This response rejects Mangione's proposal for the reason that the additional biological ties created by MST+ReIVF, compared with the reception of oocytes from partner (ROPA), are unnecessary. ROPA is currently the most effective method for redistributing biological ties within lesbian couples, allowing one member to provide the egg and the other to carry the fetus. The additional biological ties created by MST+ReIVF are quantitatively too small to significantly enhance parental bonding or couple relationships, and their potential harms to both prospective parents and children outweigh any minor benefits. Furthermore, like ROPA, MST+ReIVF fails to address deeper feminist concerns. Therefore, I propose a new idea: combining in vitro gametogenesis with ectogenesis, which can offer far more reproductive choices and greater potential to address deeper feminist concerns than MST+ReIVF.

Emanuele Mangione 在其最近的论文中提出,将母体纺锤体移植(MST)与互惠不费力体外受精(ReIVF)相结合,可使女性双方与同一个孩子拥有遗传和妊娠联系,这对女同性恋夫妇尤其有利。本答复反对曼乔内的建议,理由是与接受伴侣的卵细胞(ROPA)相比,MST+ReIVF 所产生的额外的生物学联系是不必要的。目前,ROPA 是重新分配女同性恋夫妇之间生物联系的最有效方法,它允许一方提供卵子,另一方怀上胎儿。MST+ReIVF 所产生的额外生物联系在数量上太小,无法显著增强父母的亲子关系或夫妻关系,其对准父母和子女的潜在伤害超过了任何微小的益处。此外,与《生殖健康法案》一样,MST+ReIVF 也未能解决更深层次的女权主义问题。因此,我提出了一个新的想法:将体外配子与异位生殖结合起来,这样可以提供比 MST+ReIVF 更多的生殖选择,也更有可能解决更深层次的女权主义问题。
{"title":"The unnecessary 'more'-compared to ROPA: a reply to Mangione.","authors":"Jolie Zhou","doi":"10.1136/jme-2024-110285","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1136/jme-2024-110285","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>In her recent paper, Emanuele Mangione proposes combining maternal spindle transfer (MST) and reciprocal effortless in vitro fertilisation (ReIVF) to enable both females to have genetic and gestational ties with the same child, which can particularly benefit lesbian couples. This response rejects Mangione's proposal for the reason that the additional biological ties created by MST+ReIVF, compared with the reception of oocytes from partner (ROPA), are unnecessary. ROPA is currently the most effective method for redistributing biological ties within lesbian couples, allowing one member to provide the egg and the other to carry the fetus. The additional biological ties created by MST+ReIVF are quantitatively too small to significantly enhance parental bonding or couple relationships, and their potential harms to both prospective parents and children outweigh any minor benefits. Furthermore, like ROPA, MST+ReIVF fails to address deeper feminist concerns. Therefore, I propose a new idea: combining in vitro gametogenesis with ectogenesis, which can offer far more reproductive choices and greater potential to address deeper feminist concerns than MST+ReIVF.</p>","PeriodicalId":16317,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Medical Ethics","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":3.3,"publicationDate":"2024-08-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141971258","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Epistemic injustice, healthcare disparities and the missing pipeline: reflections on the exclusion of disabled scholars from health research. 认识论上的不公正、医疗保健差距和缺失的管道:关于残疾学者被排除在健康研究之外的思考。
IF 3.3 2区 哲学 Q1 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-08-08 DOI: 10.1136/jme-2023-109837
Joanne Hunt, Charlotte Blease

People with disabilities are subject to multiple forms of health-related and wider social disparities; carefully focused research is required to inform more inclusive, safe and effective healthcare practice and policy. Through lived experience, disabled people are well positioned to identify and persistently pursue problems and opportunities within existing health provisions that may be overlooked by a largely non-disabled research community. Thus, the academy can play an important role in shining a light on the perspectives and insights from within the disability community, and combined with policy decisions, these perspectives and insights have a better opportunity to become integrated into the fabric of public life, within healthcare and beyond. However, despite the potential benefits that could be yielded by greater inclusivity, in this paper we describe barriers within the UK academy confronting disabled people who wish to embark on health research. We do this by drawing on published findings, and via the lived experience of the first author, who has struggled for over 3 years to find an accessible PhD programme as a person with energy limiting conditions who is largely confined to the home in the UK. First, we situate the discussion in the wider perspective of epistemic injustice in health research. Second, we consider evidence of epistemic injustice among disabled researchers, focusing primarily on what philosophers Kidd and Carel (2017, p 184) describe as 'strategies of exclusion'. Third, we offer recommendations for overcoming these barriers to improve the pipeline of researchers with disabilities in the academy.

残疾人在健康方面存在多种形式的差异,在更广泛的社会范围内也存在差异;需要开展重点明确的研究,为更具包容性、安全和有效的医疗保健实践和政策提供信息。通过生活经验,残疾人能够很好地发现并坚持不懈地寻求现有医疗服务中存在的问题和机遇,而这些问题和机遇可能会被大部分非残疾人研究团体所忽视。因此,学术界可以发挥重要作用,揭示来自残疾人群体的观点和见解,并与政策决策相结合,使这些观点和见解有更好的机会融入医疗保健内外的公共生活结构中。然而,尽管更大的包容性可以带来潜在的益处,但在本文中,我们将描述英国学术界中希望从事健康研究的残障人士所面临的障碍。第一位作者是一位精力受限者,在英国大部分时间只能待在家里,三年多来,她一直在努力寻找一个无障碍的博士项目。首先,我们将讨论置于健康研究中的认识论不公正这一更广阔的视角中。其次,我们考虑了残疾研究人员认识论不公正的证据,主要关注哲学家基德和卡瑞尔(Kidd and Carel, 2017, p 184)所描述的 "排斥策略"。第三,我们提出了克服这些障碍的建议,以改善残疾研究人员在学术界的发展渠道。
{"title":"Epistemic injustice, healthcare disparities and the missing pipeline: reflections on the exclusion of disabled scholars from health research.","authors":"Joanne Hunt, Charlotte Blease","doi":"10.1136/jme-2023-109837","DOIUrl":"10.1136/jme-2023-109837","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>People with disabilities are subject to multiple forms of health-related and wider social disparities; carefully focused research is required to inform more inclusive, safe and effective healthcare practice and policy. Through lived experience, disabled people are well positioned to identify and persistently pursue problems and opportunities within existing health provisions that may be overlooked by a largely non-disabled research community. Thus, the academy can play an important role in shining a light on the perspectives and insights from within the disability community, and combined with policy decisions, these perspectives and insights have a better opportunity to become integrated into the fabric of public life, within healthcare and beyond. However, despite the potential benefits that could be yielded by greater inclusivity, in this paper we describe barriers within the UK academy confronting disabled people who wish to embark on health research. We do this by drawing on published findings, and via the lived experience of the first author, who has struggled for over 3 years to find an accessible PhD programme as a person with energy limiting conditions who is largely confined to the home in the UK. First, we situate the discussion in the wider perspective of epistemic injustice in health research. Second, we consider evidence of epistemic injustice among disabled researchers, focusing primarily on what philosophers Kidd and Carel (2017, p 184) describe as 'strategies of exclusion'. Third, we offer recommendations for overcoming these barriers to improve the pipeline of researchers with disabilities in the academy.</p>","PeriodicalId":16317,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Medical Ethics","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":3.3,"publicationDate":"2024-08-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141086569","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Non-voluntary BCI explantation: assessing possible neurorights violations in light of contrasting mental ontologies. 非自愿的生物识别(BCI)植入:根据不同的精神本体论评估可能的神经权侵犯。
IF 3.3 2区 哲学 Q1 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-08-08 DOI: 10.1136/jme-2023-109830
Guido Cassinadri, Marcello Ienca

In research involving patients with implantable brain-computer interfaces (BCIs), there is a regulatory gap concerning post-trial responsibilities and duties of sponsors and investigators towards implanted patients. In this article, we analyse the case of patient R, who underwent non-voluntary explantation of an implanted BCI, causing a discontinuation in her sense of agency and self. To clarify the post-trial duties and responsibilities involved in this case, we first define the ontological status of the BCI using both externalist (EXT) and internalist (INT) theories of cognition. We then give particular focus to the theories of extended and embedded cognition, hence considering the BCI either as a constitutive component of the patient's mind or as a causal supporter of her brain-based cognitive capacities. We argue that patient R can legitimately be considered both as an embedded and extended cognitive agent. Then, we analyse whether the non-voluntary explantation violated patient R's (neuro)rights to cognitive liberty, mental integrity, psychological continuity and mental privacy. We analyse whether and how different mental ontologies may imply morally relevant differences in interpreting these prima facie neurorights violations and the correlational duties of sponsors and investigators. We conclude that both mental ontologies support the identification of emerging neurorights of the patient and give rise to post-trial obligations of sponsors and investigators to provide for continuous technical maintenance of implanted BCIs that play a significant role in patients' agency and sense of self. However, we suggest that externalist mental ontologies better capture patient R's self-conception and support the identification of a more granular form of mental harm and associated neurorights violation, thus eliciting stricter post-trial obligations.

在涉及植入式脑机接口(BCI)患者的研究中,赞助商和研究人员在试验后对植入患者的责任和义务方面存在监管空白。在本文中,我们分析了患者 R 的案例,她在非自愿的情况下拆除了植入的 BCI,导致其代理感和自我意识中断。为了澄清该案例中涉及的审判后义务和责任,我们首先使用外部主义(EXT)和内部主义(INT)认知理论定义了 BCI 的本体论地位。然后,我们特别关注扩展认知理论和嵌入认知理论,从而将 BCI 视为患者心智的构成部分或其大脑认知能力的因果支持者。我们认为,患者 R 既可以被视为嵌入式认知主体,也可以被视为扩展认知主体。然后,我们分析了非自愿切除是否侵犯了患者 R 的(神经)认知自由权、精神完整性、心理连续性和精神隐私权。我们分析了不同的精神本体论在解释这些表面上侵犯神经权利的行为以及赞助者和研究者的相关责任时,是否以及如何意味着道德上的相关差异。我们的结论是,这两种精神本体论都支持对患者新出现的神经权利的识别,并使赞助商和研究人员承担试验后义务,为植入式生物识别装置提供持续的技术维护,因为这些装置在患者的代理和自我意识中发挥着重要作用。然而,我们认为外部主义精神本体论能更好地捕捉患者 R 的自我感知,并支持识别更细化的精神伤害形式和相关的神经权利侵犯,从而引起更严格的试验后义务。
{"title":"Non-voluntary BCI explantation: assessing possible neurorights violations in light of contrasting mental ontologies.","authors":"Guido Cassinadri, Marcello Ienca","doi":"10.1136/jme-2023-109830","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1136/jme-2023-109830","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>In research involving patients with implantable brain-computer interfaces (BCIs), there is a regulatory gap concerning post-trial responsibilities and duties of sponsors and investigators towards implanted patients. In this article, we analyse the case of patient R, who underwent non-voluntary explantation of an implanted BCI, causing a discontinuation in her sense of agency and self. To clarify the post-trial duties and responsibilities involved in this case, we first define the ontological status of the BCI using both externalist (EXT) and internalist (INT) theories of cognition. We then give particular focus to the theories of extended and embedded cognition, hence considering the BCI either as a constitutive component of the patient's mind or as a causal supporter of her brain-based cognitive capacities. We argue that patient R can legitimately be considered both as an embedded and extended cognitive agent. Then, we analyse whether the non-voluntary explantation violated patient R's (neuro)rights to cognitive liberty, mental integrity, psychological continuity and mental privacy. We analyse whether and how different mental ontologies may imply morally relevant differences in interpreting these prima facie neurorights violations and the correlational duties of sponsors and investigators. We conclude that both mental ontologies support the identification of emerging neurorights of the patient and give rise to post-trial obligations of sponsors and investigators to provide for continuous technical maintenance of implanted BCIs that play a significant role in patients' agency and sense of self. However, we suggest that externalist mental ontologies better capture patient R's self-conception and support the identification of a more granular form of mental harm and associated neurorights violation, thus eliciting stricter post-trial obligations.</p>","PeriodicalId":16317,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Medical Ethics","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":3.3,"publicationDate":"2024-08-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141906788","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Treating infertility as a missing capability, not a disease: a capability approach. 将不孕症视为能力缺失而非疾病:能力方法。
IF 3.3 2区 哲学 Q1 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-08-08 DOI: 10.1136/jme-2024-109877
Michelle Jessica Bayefsky, Arthur Caplan

Infertility patients and patient advocates have long argued for classifying infertility as a disease, in the hopes that this recognition would improve coverage for and access to fertility treatment. However, for many fertility patients, including older women, single women and same-sex couples, infertility does not represent a true disease state. Therefore, while calling infertility a 'disease' may seem politically advantageous, it might actually exclude patients with 'social' or 'relational' infertility from treatment. What is needed is a new conceptual framing of infertility that better reflects the profound significance of being infertile for many people and the importance of addressing infertility in order to improve their lives. In this paper, we argue that the capability approach provides this moral underpinning. The capability approach is concerned with what people are able to do, and whether they are able to act in a way that is in keeping with their own values and goals. The ability to procreate and build a family is a fundamental capacity and can be a major part of self-fulfilment, regardless of sexual orientation or family arrangement. Since the capability approach asks us to conceive of equality in terms of equal capabilities, it provides a strong ethical impetus for society to help those who cannot conceive on their own to do so with assisted reproduction.

长期以来,不孕不育患者和患者权益倡导者一直主张将不孕不育归类为一种疾病,希望这种认识能够改善不孕不育治疗的覆盖面和可及性。然而,对于许多不孕不育患者来说,包括老年妇女、单身妇女和同性伴侣,不孕不育并不代表真正的疾病状态。因此,尽管将不孕症称为 "疾病 "似乎在政治上是有利的,但它实际上可能将 "社会性 "或 "关系性 "不孕症患者排除在治疗之外。我们需要的是对不孕不育症进行新的概念界定,以更好地反映不孕不育症对许多人的深远意义,以及解决不孕不育症问题以改善他们生活的重要性。在本文中,我们认为能力方法提供了这种道德基础。能力方法关注的是人们能够做什么,以及他们是否能够以符合自身价值观和目标的方式行事。无论性取向或家庭安排如何,生育和建立家庭的能力都是一种基本能力,也是自我实现的重要组成部分。由于能力方法要求我们从平等能力的角度来看待平等,因此它为社会提供了强大的道德动力,帮助那些无法自己怀孕的人通过辅助生育来实现这一目标。
{"title":"Treating infertility as a missing capability, not a disease: a capability approach.","authors":"Michelle Jessica Bayefsky, Arthur Caplan","doi":"10.1136/jme-2024-109877","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1136/jme-2024-109877","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Infertility patients and patient advocates have long argued for classifying infertility as a disease, in the hopes that this recognition would improve coverage for and access to fertility treatment. However, for many fertility patients, including older women, single women and same-sex couples, infertility does not represent a true disease state. Therefore, while calling infertility a 'disease' may seem politically advantageous, it might actually exclude patients with 'social' or 'relational' infertility from treatment. What is needed is a new conceptual framing of infertility that better reflects the profound significance of being infertile for many people and the importance of addressing infertility in order to improve their lives. In this paper, we argue that the capability approach provides this moral underpinning. The capability approach is concerned with what people are able to <i>do</i>, and whether they are able to act in a way that is in keeping with their own values and goals. The ability to procreate and build a family is a fundamental capacity and can be a major part of self-fulfilment, regardless of sexual orientation or family arrangement. Since the capability approach asks us to conceive of equality in terms of equal capabilities, it provides a strong ethical impetus for society to help those who cannot conceive on their own to do so with assisted reproduction.</p>","PeriodicalId":16317,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Medical Ethics","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":3.3,"publicationDate":"2024-08-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141906789","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Are clinicians ethically obligated to disclose their use of medical machine learning systems to patients? 临床医生是否有道德义务向患者披露他们使用医疗机器学习系统的情况?
IF 3.3 2区 哲学 Q1 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-08-07 DOI: 10.1136/jme-2024-109905
Joshua Hatherley

It is commonly accepted that clinicians are ethically obligated to disclose their use of medical machine learning systems to patients, and that failure to do so would amount to a moral fault for which clinicians ought to be held accountable. Call this 'the disclosure thesis.' Four main arguments have been, or could be, given to support the disclosure thesis in the ethics literature: the risk-based argument, the rights-based argument, the materiality argument and the autonomy argument. In this article, I argue that each of these four arguments are unconvincing, and therefore, that the disclosure thesis ought to be rejected. I suggest that mandating disclosure may also even risk harming patients by providing stakeholders with a way to avoid accountability for harm that results from improper applications or uses of these systems.

人们普遍认为,临床医生在道德上有义务向患者披露他们使用医疗机器学习系统的情况,如果不这样做,则构成道德过失,临床医生应对此负责。这就是 "披露论"。在伦理学文献中,支持披露论的论据主要有四个:基于风险的论据、基于权利的论据、实质性论据和自主性论据。在本文中,我认为这四个论点都不能令人信服,因此应该摒弃披露论。我认为,强制公开甚至可能会给患者带来伤害,因为利益相关者可以借此逃避因不当应用或使用这些系统而造成伤害的责任。
{"title":"Are clinicians ethically obligated to disclose their use of medical machine learning systems to patients?","authors":"Joshua Hatherley","doi":"10.1136/jme-2024-109905","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1136/jme-2024-109905","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>It is commonly accepted that clinicians are ethically obligated to disclose their use of medical machine learning systems to patients, and that failure to do so would amount to a moral fault for which clinicians ought to be held accountable. Call this 'the disclosure thesis.' Four main arguments have been, or could be, given to support the disclosure thesis in the ethics literature: the risk-based argument, the rights-based argument, the materiality argument and the autonomy argument. In this article, I argue that each of these four arguments are unconvincing, and therefore, that the disclosure thesis ought to be rejected. I suggest that mandating disclosure may also even risk harming patients by providing stakeholders with a way to avoid accountability for harm that results from improper applications or uses of these systems.</p>","PeriodicalId":16317,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Medical Ethics","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":3.3,"publicationDate":"2024-08-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141906787","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Birth's transformative shift: a response to Waleszczyński. 出生的转变:对 Waleszczyński 的回应。
IF 3.3 2区 哲学 Q1 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-08-05 DOI: 10.1136/jme-2024-110307
Prabhpal Singh

Waleszczyński critiques my argument for why the relationship between a pregnant person and any fetus they carry is not a relationship between a parent and a child. I argue Waleszczyński does not show that my 'argument from potentiality' is inadequate, and I provide further justification for why birth marks a transformative shift into a moral relationship.

瓦列兹钦斯基批评了我的论点,即为什么孕妇与胎儿之间的关系不是父母与子女之间的关系。我认为瓦莱辛斯基并没有证明我的 "潜能论证 "是不充分的,我还进一步说明了为什么出生标志着道德关系的转变。
{"title":"Birth's transformative shift: a response to Waleszczyński.","authors":"Prabhpal Singh","doi":"10.1136/jme-2024-110307","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1136/jme-2024-110307","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Waleszczyński critiques my argument for why the relationship between a pregnant person and any fetus they carry is not a relationship between a parent and a child. I argue Waleszczyński does not show that my 'argument from potentiality' is inadequate, and I provide further justification for why birth marks a transformative shift into a moral relationship.</p>","PeriodicalId":16317,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Medical Ethics","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":3.3,"publicationDate":"2024-08-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141893532","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
AI and XAI second opinion: the danger of false confirmation in human-AI collaboration. 人工智能和 XAI 第二意见:人类与人工智能合作中错误确认的危险。
IF 3.3 2区 哲学 Q1 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-07-29 DOI: 10.1136/jme-2024-110074
Rikard Rosenbacke, Åsa Melhus, Martin McKee, David Stuckler

Can AI substitute a human physician's second opinion? Recently the Journal of Medical Ethics published two contrasting views: Kempt and Nagel advocate for using artificial intelligence (AI) for a second opinion except when its conclusions significantly diverge from the initial physician's while Jongsma and Sand argue for a second human opinion irrespective of AI's concurrence or dissent. The crux of this debate hinges on the prevalence and impact of 'false confirmation'-a scenario where AI erroneously validates an incorrect human decision. These errors seem exceedingly difficult to detect, reminiscent of heuristics akin to confirmation bias. However, this debate has yet to engage with the emergence of explainable AI (XAI), which elaborates on why the AI tool reaches its diagnosis. To progress this debate, we outline a framework for conceptualising decision-making errors in physician-AI collaborations. We then review emerging evidence on the magnitude of false confirmation errors. Our simulations show that they are likely to be pervasive in clinical practice, decreasing diagnostic accuracy to between 5% and 30%. We conclude with a pragmatic approach to employing AI as a second opinion, emphasising the need for physicians to make clinical decisions before consulting AI; employing nudges to increase awareness of false confirmations and critically engaging with XAI explanations. This approach underscores the necessity for a cautious, evidence-based methodology when integrating AI into clinical decision-making.

人工智能能否取代人类医生的第二意见?最近,《医学伦理学杂志》发表了两种截然不同的观点:坎普特(Kempt)和纳格尔(Nagel)主张使用人工智能(AI)作为第二意见,除非人工智能的结论与最初医生的结论有明显差异;而琼斯马(Jongsma)和桑德(Sand)则主张无论人工智能是否同意,都应使用第二人类意见。这场争论的关键在于 "错误确认 "的普遍性和影响--即人工智能错误地验证了人类的错误决定。这些错误似乎极难发现,让人联想到类似确认偏差的启发式思维。然而,这场辩论还没有涉及到可解释人工智能(XAI)的出现,它阐述了人工智能工具得出诊断结果的原因。为了推进这一讨论,我们概述了一个框架,用于概念化医生-人工智能合作中的决策错误。然后,我们回顾了有关错误确认错误程度的新证据。我们的模拟结果表明,误诊可能在临床实践中普遍存在,会将诊断准确率降低到 5% 到 30%。最后,我们提出了将人工智能作为第二意见的务实方法,强调医生在咨询人工智能之前需要做出临床决定;采用提示以提高对错误确认的认识,并批判性地参与 XAI 解释。这种方法强调,在将人工智能纳入临床决策时,必须采用谨慎、循证的方法。
{"title":"AI and XAI second opinion: the danger of false confirmation in human-AI collaboration.","authors":"Rikard Rosenbacke, Åsa Melhus, Martin McKee, David Stuckler","doi":"10.1136/jme-2024-110074","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1136/jme-2024-110074","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Can AI substitute a human physician's second opinion? Recently the <i>Journal of Medical Ethics</i> published two contrasting views: Kempt and Nagel advocate for using artificial intelligence (AI) for a second opinion except when its conclusions significantly diverge from the initial physician's while Jongsma and Sand argue for a second human opinion irrespective of AI's concurrence or dissent. The crux of this debate hinges on the prevalence and impact of 'false confirmation'-a scenario where AI erroneously validates an incorrect human decision. These errors seem exceedingly difficult to detect, reminiscent of heuristics akin to confirmation bias. However, this debate has yet to engage with the emergence of explainable AI (XAI), which elaborates on why the AI tool reaches its diagnosis. To progress this debate, we outline a framework for conceptualising decision-making errors in physician-AI collaborations. We then review emerging evidence on the magnitude of false confirmation errors. Our simulations show that they are likely to be pervasive in clinical practice, decreasing diagnostic accuracy to between 5% and 30%. We conclude with a pragmatic approach to employing AI as a second opinion, emphasising the need for physicians to make clinical decisions before consulting AI; employing nudges to increase awareness of false confirmations and critically engaging with XAI explanations. This approach underscores the necessity for a cautious, evidence-based methodology when integrating AI into clinical decision-making.</p>","PeriodicalId":16317,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Medical Ethics","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":3.3,"publicationDate":"2024-07-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141792612","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Response: arguments to abolish the legal age limits of access to information about the gamete donor by donor offspring. 答复:主张取消对捐献者后代获取配子捐献者信息的法定年龄限制。
IF 3.3 2区 哲学 Q1 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-07-26 DOI: 10.1136/jme-2024-110230
Inge van Nistelrooij, Nicolette Woestenburg

The Journal of Medical Ethics previously published on the debate in the UK and the Netherlands concerning the legal age limits imposed on donor-conceived people for access to information about the identity of gamete and embryo donors. In that publication, three arguments were foregrounded against lowering these age limits as a general rule for all donor-conceived people. In this contribution, we engage with these arguments and argue why we think they are insufficient to maintain the age limits. In contrast, we argue for a more suited, contextual and relational ethical framework based on care ethics, which emphasises relational autonomy and its dynamic, contextual development. This framework, we argue, provides a comprehensive approach for the analysis we made of the question of age limits and was applied in research performed in the Netherlands, commissioned by the Dutch Minister of Health. The framework enabled us to weigh the multidisciplinary-legal, psychological, phenomenological and ethical-findings of our research.

医学伦理学杂志》曾就英国和荷兰对捐献者受孕者获取配子和胚胎捐献者身份信息的法定年龄限制进行过辩论。在那篇文章中,有三个论点反对降低这些年龄限制,将其作为适用于所有捐献受孕者的一般规则。在这篇论文中,我们对这些论点进行了讨论,并论证了为什么我们认为这些论点不足以维持年龄限制。与此相反,我们主张在护理伦理学的基础上建立一个更合适、更符合具体情况和更有关系的伦理学框架,该框架强调关系自主性及其动态的、符合具体情况的发展。我们认为,这一框架为我们分析年龄限制问题提供了一种全面的方法,并在荷兰卫生部委托荷兰进行的研究中得到了应用。该框架使我们能够权衡我们研究中的法律、心理、现象学和伦理等多学科发现。
{"title":"Response: arguments to abolish the legal age limits of access to information about the gamete donor by donor offspring.","authors":"Inge van Nistelrooij, Nicolette Woestenburg","doi":"10.1136/jme-2024-110230","DOIUrl":"10.1136/jme-2024-110230","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>The <i>Journal of Medical Ethics</i> previously published on the debate in the UK and the Netherlands concerning the legal age limits imposed on donor-conceived people for access to information about the identity of gamete and embryo donors. In that publication, three arguments were foregrounded against lowering these age limits as a general rule for all donor-conceived people. In this contribution, we engage with these arguments and argue why we think they are insufficient to maintain the age limits. In contrast, we argue for a more suited, contextual and relational ethical framework based on care ethics, which emphasises relational autonomy and its dynamic, contextual development. This framework, we argue, provides a comprehensive approach for the analysis we made of the question of age limits and was applied in research performed in the Netherlands, commissioned by the Dutch Minister of Health. The framework enabled us to weigh the multidisciplinary-legal, psychological, phenomenological and ethical-findings of our research.</p>","PeriodicalId":16317,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Medical Ethics","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":3.3,"publicationDate":"2024-07-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141766309","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Dynamic consent: a royal road to research consent? 动态同意:通往研究同意的皇家之路?
IF 3.3 2区 哲学 Q1 ETHICS Pub Date : 2024-07-24 DOI: 10.1136/jme-2024-110153
Andreas Bruns, Eva C Winkler

In recent years, the principle of informed consent has come under significant pressure with the rise of biobanks and data infrastructures for medical research. Study-specific consent is unfeasible in the context of biobank and data infrastructure research; and while broad consent facilitates research, it has been criticised as being insufficient to secure a truly informed consent. Dynamic consent has been promoted as a promising alternative approach that could help patients and research participants regain control over the use of their biospecimen and health data in medical research. Critical voices have focused mainly on concerns around its implementation; but little has been said about the argument that dynamic consent is morally superior to broad consent as a way to respect people's individual autonomy. In this paper, we identify two versions of this argument-an information-focused version and a control-focused version-and then argue that both fail to establish the moral superiority of dynamic over broad consent. In particular, we argue that since autonomous choices are a certain species of choices, it is neither obvious that dynamic consent would meaningfully enhance people's autonomy, nor that it is morally justifiable to act on every kind of consent choice enabled by dynamic consent.

近年来,随着用于医学研究的生物库和数据基础设施的兴起,知情同意原则受到了巨大压力。在生物库和数据基础设施研究的背景下,针对特定研究的同意是不可行的;虽然广泛的同意有利于研究,但也被批评为不足以确保真正的知情同意。动态同意被认为是一种很有前途的替代方法,可以帮助患者和研究参与者重新控制其生物样本和健康数据在医学研究中的使用。批评的声音主要集中在对其实施的担忧上;但对于动态同意在道义上优于广泛同意作为一种尊重个人自主权的方式这一论点,却鲜有人提及。在本文中,我们指出了这一论点的两个版本--以信息为中心的版本和以控制为中心的版本--然后认为这两个版本都不能证明动态同意在道德上优于广泛同意。特别是,我们认为,既然自主选择是一种特定的选择,那么动态同意既不能明显地有意义地提高人们的自主性,也不能说对动态同意所促成的每一种同意选择采取行动在道德上都是正当的。
{"title":"Dynamic consent: a royal road to research consent?","authors":"Andreas Bruns, Eva C Winkler","doi":"10.1136/jme-2024-110153","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1136/jme-2024-110153","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>In recent years, the principle of informed consent has come under significant pressure with the rise of biobanks and data infrastructures for medical research. Study-specific consent is unfeasible in the context of biobank and data infrastructure research; and while broad consent facilitates research, it has been criticised as being insufficient to secure a truly informed consent. Dynamic consent has been promoted as a promising alternative approach that could help patients and research participants regain control over the use of their biospecimen and health data in medical research. Critical voices have focused mainly on concerns around its implementation; but little has been said about the argument that dynamic consent is morally superior to broad consent as a way to respect people's individual autonomy. In this paper, we identify two versions of this argument-an information-focused version and a control-focused version-and then argue that both fail to establish the moral superiority of dynamic over broad consent. In particular, we argue that since autonomous choices are a certain species of choices, it is neither obvious that dynamic consent would meaningfully enhance people's autonomy, nor that it is morally justifiable to act on every kind of consent choice enabled by dynamic consent.</p>","PeriodicalId":16317,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Medical Ethics","volume":" ","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":3.3,"publicationDate":"2024-07-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"141759263","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Journal of Medical Ethics
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1