首页 > 最新文献

Process Studies最新文献

英文 中文
Pluriform Love: An Open and Relational Theology of Well-Being 多元的爱:一个开放和关系的幸福神学
Pub Date : 2023-11-01 DOI: 10.5406/21543682.52.2.10
John M. Sweeney
In this book, Thomas Oord continues his ongoing explorations of, to borrow the title of Daniel Day Williams's classic work, The Spirit and the Forms of Love. In previous works—such as Defining Love: Philosophical, Scientific, and Theological Investigations; The Science of Love: The Wisdom of Well Being; and The Uncontrolling Love of God: An Open and Relational Account of Providence—Oord has explored the importance of love in a variety of contexts. Pluriform Love focuses on the ways in which love has been portrayed in much of the classical Christian tradition, both in traditional Christian theology and in the various biblical words for love (eros, agape, hesed, etc.).Chapter 1 presents the case that, for the most part, in Christian theology love has been ignored, misrepresented, or worse. All this downplaying of love has occurred despite the many, obvious scriptural references to love: Corinthians 13, The Great Commandments, “God is love” (1 John 4.8, 16), and so forth. In chapter 2, Oord presents and explains his definition of love as follows: “To love is to act intentionally, in relational response to God and others, to promote overall well-being.” Oord regularly refers to this definition in showing how traditional Christian views of love have met the criteria implicit in the definition.Chapters 3–6 provide critiques, both positive and negative, of various figures and perspectives in traditional Christian theology with regard to their views on the role of love. For example, in chapter 3, Anders Nygren's views on agape are evaluated, and in chapter 6, Augustine's views on eros are examined.In Chapters 7–9 Oord presents his constructive proposals for recovering the role of love as the primary attribute of the divine. Among these proposals are open and relational theology, essential kenosis, amipotence, and essential hesed, all of which lead to a theology of pluriform love.Oord has been, and remains, a leading figure in the open and relational theology movement. In this book, he describes open and relational theology as a broad movement that includes within it a variety of forms: process, feminism, free will theism, personalism, and more. While there are differences in detail, there are some commonalities among the various open and relational theologies, such as (1) a concern for an open future (the future is not predetermined by the divine or any other creatures), (2) an experiential relationship between the divine and the rest of creation—the divine influences creation and creation influences the divine, and (3) the belief that love is the most important characteristic of the divine.Essential kenosis involves the notion that the divine is both self-giving of its love and other-empowering in its actions and intentions, and that both self-giving and other-empowering are inherent traits of the divine and divine love. God does not choose to be loving; God cannot help but be loving. Essential kenosis shows itself in God's uncontrolling love.Amipotence
在这本书中,托马斯·奥德继续他正在进行的探索,借用丹尼尔·戴·威廉姆斯经典作品的标题,爱的精神和形式。在之前的作品中,如《定义爱:哲学、科学和神学研究》;爱的科学:幸福的智慧和《神的无节制之爱:对神的开放和关系的描述》一书探讨了爱在各种情况下的重要性。《多元形式的爱》聚焦于许多古典基督教传统中对爱的描绘方式,无论是在传统的基督教神学中,还是在各种关于爱的圣经词汇中(eros, agape, hesed等)。第一章提出的情况下,在大多数情况下,在基督教神学的爱被忽视,歪曲,或更糟。所有这些对爱的轻视都发生了,尽管圣经中有许多明显的关于爱的引用:哥林多前书13章,大诫命,“神就是爱”(约翰一书4.8,16)等等。在第二章中,奥德提出并解释了他对爱的定义:“爱是有意识地行动,以对上帝和他人的关系作出反应,促进整体福祉。”奥德经常引用这个定义来说明传统基督教的爱情观是如何符合定义中隐含的标准的。第3-6章提供了对传统基督教神学中关于爱的角色的各种人物和观点的批评,既有积极的也有消极的。例如,在第三章中,对安德斯·尼格伦关于爱的观点进行了评价,在第六章中,对奥古斯丁关于爱神的观点进行了考察。在第7-9章中,奥德提出了他的建设性建议,以恢复爱的角色,作为神的主要属性。在这些建议是开放的和关系的神学,本质的kenosis,无力,和本质的hesed,所有这一切导致神学的多元化的爱。奥德一直是,并且仍然是开放和关系神学运动的领军人物。在这本书中,他将开放和关系神学描述为一个广泛的运动,其中包括各种形式:过程,女权主义,自由意志有神论,个人主义等等。虽然在细节上存在差异,但在各种开放的和关系的神学中有一些共同点,例如(1)对开放的未来的关注(未来不是由神或任何其他生物预先决定的),(2)神和其他创造物之间的经验关系——神影响创造物,创造物影响神,(3)相信爱是神最重要的特征。本质的克诺西斯包含了这样一个概念,即神性在其爱中是自我奉献的,在其行为和意图中是赋予他人力量的,而自我奉献和赋予他人力量都是神性和神性之爱的内在特征。神并没有选择去爱;上帝不能不慈爱。本质上,神的爱是神不加控制的。神的全能是神在处理神的全能或神是“全能的”问题时提出的一个建议。为了与他对不受控制的爱的强调保持一致,奥德建议将爱的拉丁语前缀“ami”与拉丁语词根“potent”结合起来,后者是潜在或效力的意思;因此,“无能为力”指的是神圣的不受控制的爱所能产生的所有力量。必不可少的hesed是用来描述神圣的坚定的爱,必然地,对所有的创造,包括人类。神性不能离开或抛弃创造物,但将始终参与自我给予和赋予他人力量的关系。这里有两点需要注意:首先,既然奥德讨论的是传统的基督教神学,而且传统一直由男性主导,那么上帝在历史上的大部分讨论中都是男性就不足为奇了。女性主义神学家最近的作品在脚注中被引用,可以在Pluriform Love的广泛参考书目中找到。其次,对于那些相信上帝的全能(全能)和上帝的绝对独立(唯意志论)是最重要的神圣属性的人来说,上帝的建设性建议(本质的kenosis,本质的hesed,无力等)可能不会被很好地接受。说上帝必须爱,除了爱别无选择,这似乎是一个传统神学家可能不欣赏的限制。我在不同的环境中教授哲学和神学二十多年的经验表明,许多(也许是大多数)人发现改变他们对上帝的信仰是最困难的。相信一个全能的存在是完全控制的,他选择什么时候创造奇迹,“祝福”谁,等等,是非常强大的。许多人宁愿放弃对上帝的信仰,也不愿改变他们对上帝的传统信仰,即使他们在个人生活中遇到了邪恶和苦难的问题。
{"title":"Pluriform Love: An Open and Relational Theology of Well-Being","authors":"John M. Sweeney","doi":"10.5406/21543682.52.2.10","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21543682.52.2.10","url":null,"abstract":"In this book, Thomas Oord continues his ongoing explorations of, to borrow the title of Daniel Day Williams's classic work, The Spirit and the Forms of Love. In previous works—such as Defining Love: Philosophical, Scientific, and Theological Investigations; The Science of Love: The Wisdom of Well Being; and The Uncontrolling Love of God: An Open and Relational Account of Providence—Oord has explored the importance of love in a variety of contexts. Pluriform Love focuses on the ways in which love has been portrayed in much of the classical Christian tradition, both in traditional Christian theology and in the various biblical words for love (eros, agape, hesed, etc.).Chapter 1 presents the case that, for the most part, in Christian theology love has been ignored, misrepresented, or worse. All this downplaying of love has occurred despite the many, obvious scriptural references to love: Corinthians 13, The Great Commandments, “God is love” (1 John 4.8, 16), and so forth. In chapter 2, Oord presents and explains his definition of love as follows: “To love is to act intentionally, in relational response to God and others, to promote overall well-being.” Oord regularly refers to this definition in showing how traditional Christian views of love have met the criteria implicit in the definition.Chapters 3–6 provide critiques, both positive and negative, of various figures and perspectives in traditional Christian theology with regard to their views on the role of love. For example, in chapter 3, Anders Nygren's views on agape are evaluated, and in chapter 6, Augustine's views on eros are examined.In Chapters 7–9 Oord presents his constructive proposals for recovering the role of love as the primary attribute of the divine. Among these proposals are open and relational theology, essential kenosis, amipotence, and essential hesed, all of which lead to a theology of pluriform love.Oord has been, and remains, a leading figure in the open and relational theology movement. In this book, he describes open and relational theology as a broad movement that includes within it a variety of forms: process, feminism, free will theism, personalism, and more. While there are differences in detail, there are some commonalities among the various open and relational theologies, such as (1) a concern for an open future (the future is not predetermined by the divine or any other creatures), (2) an experiential relationship between the divine and the rest of creation—the divine influences creation and creation influences the divine, and (3) the belief that love is the most important characteristic of the divine.Essential kenosis involves the notion that the divine is both self-giving of its love and other-empowering in its actions and intentions, and that both self-giving and other-empowering are inherent traits of the divine and divine love. God does not choose to be loving; God cannot help but be loving. Essential kenosis shows itself in God's uncontrolling love.Amipotence","PeriodicalId":315123,"journal":{"name":"Process Studies","volume":"16 3","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135565743","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Standing Firm in the Flux: On Whitehead's Eternal Objects 在变化中站稳脚跟:论怀特海的永恒之物
Pub Date : 2023-11-01 DOI: 10.5406/21543682.52.2.02
Matthew David Segall
Abstract Alfred North Whitehead's first book as a professor of philosophy at Harvard University, Science and the Modern World, is not only a historical treatment of the rise and fall of scientific materialism. It also marks his turn to metaphysics in search of an alternative cosmological scheme that would replace matter in motion with organic process as that which is generic in Nature. Among the metaphysical innovations introduced in this book are the somewhat enigmatic “eternal objects.” The publication of the first and second volumes of Whitehead's Harvard Lectures on the philosophical presuppositions (HL1) and general metaphysical problems (HL2) of science provides students of his corpus with an opportunity to catch the thinker in the act of creating his concepts. In searching through student notes for glimpses of what Whitehead really meant, I have kept in mind his admonition that “no thinker thinks twice” (PR 29). Whitehead never ceased philosophizing, and surely he intended for us to continue thinking with but beyond the letter of his ideas. In this spirit and in light of HL1 and HL2, this article seeks to elucidate the role of eternal objects as a category of existence in Whitehead's Philosophy of Organism, with the goal not simply of textual exegesis, but of showing how the meaning of the fifth category of existence (as he refers to eternal objects in PR) is exemplified in the gradual ingression of the idea in Whitehead's imagination. My aim is to sustain the effort at constructive thought he began, making his speculative hypothesis as explicit as possible so as to better prepare it for critical improvement (PR xiv).
怀特黑德(Alfred North Whitehead)作为哈佛大学哲学教授的第一本书《科学与现代世界》(Science and Modern World),不仅是对科学唯物主义兴衰的历史论述。这也标志着他转向形而上学,寻找另一种宇宙学方案,用自然中普遍存在的有机过程取代运动中的物质。在这本书中引入的形而上学创新中,有一个有点神秘的“永恒的对象”。怀特黑德的《哈佛大学哲学前提讲座》(h1)和《科学的一般形而上学问题讲座》(HL2)的第一卷和第二卷的出版,为学习他的语料库的学生提供了一个捕捉这位思想家创造概念的机会。在翻阅学生笔记,寻找怀特黑德真正意思的一瞥时,我一直牢记着他的告诫:“没有思想家会三思而后行”(PR 29)。怀特海从来没有停止过他的哲学思考,他当然是想让我们继续思考,但要超越他的思想。本着这种精神,并根据HL1和HL2,本文试图阐明永恒对象作为存在范畴在怀特黑德的《有机体哲学》中的作用,其目的不仅仅是文本注释,而是展示第五种存在范畴的意义(正如他在PR中所指的永恒对象)是如何在怀特黑德的想象中逐渐渗入的。我的目标是维持他开始的建设性思想的努力,使他的推测假设尽可能明确,以便更好地为关键改进做好准备(PR xiv)。
{"title":"Standing Firm in the Flux: On Whitehead's Eternal Objects","authors":"Matthew David Segall","doi":"10.5406/21543682.52.2.02","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21543682.52.2.02","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Alfred North Whitehead's first book as a professor of philosophy at Harvard University, Science and the Modern World, is not only a historical treatment of the rise and fall of scientific materialism. It also marks his turn to metaphysics in search of an alternative cosmological scheme that would replace matter in motion with organic process as that which is generic in Nature. Among the metaphysical innovations introduced in this book are the somewhat enigmatic “eternal objects.” The publication of the first and second volumes of Whitehead's Harvard Lectures on the philosophical presuppositions (HL1) and general metaphysical problems (HL2) of science provides students of his corpus with an opportunity to catch the thinker in the act of creating his concepts. In searching through student notes for glimpses of what Whitehead really meant, I have kept in mind his admonition that “no thinker thinks twice” (PR 29). Whitehead never ceased philosophizing, and surely he intended for us to continue thinking with but beyond the letter of his ideas. In this spirit and in light of HL1 and HL2, this article seeks to elucidate the role of eternal objects as a category of existence in Whitehead's Philosophy of Organism, with the goal not simply of textual exegesis, but of showing how the meaning of the fifth category of existence (as he refers to eternal objects in PR) is exemplified in the gradual ingression of the idea in Whitehead's imagination. My aim is to sustain the effort at constructive thought he began, making his speculative hypothesis as explicit as possible so as to better prepare it for critical improvement (PR xiv).","PeriodicalId":315123,"journal":{"name":"Process Studies","volume":"11 2","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135565482","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Locating Freedom in Bergson's Time and Free Will 在柏格森的《时间与自由意志》中寻找自由
Pub Date : 2023-11-01 DOI: 10.5406/21543682.52.2.07
Brian Claude Macallan
Abstract The question of the nature of free will remains a perennial challenge for philosophy. The French philosopher Henri Bergson was one who sought to address this challenge. He argued that traditional conceptions of the free-will debate would not suffice. He suggested that both determinist and libertarian accounts fall foul of spatializing tendencies. Bergson's first major work, Time and Free Will, sought to ground his understanding of freedom, in contrast to traditional understandings, in the concept of duration. Bergson, however, actively resisted attempts to define clearly freedom, which he believed ultimately leads to a spatializing of freedom. By attending to Bergson's concept of duration in Time and Free Will, and how this concept relates to freedom, it becomes possible to articulate a positive conception of freedom. This becomes important when arguing for the validity of Bergson's ideas in the current climate. Thus, a positive conception of freedom for Bergson can be “defined” as “the creation of the new within the flow of duration.” It is, however, not something that can be defined, but is something that can be located.
自由意志的本质问题一直是哲学面临的一个长期挑战。法国哲学家亨利·柏格森(Henri Bergson)就是试图解决这一挑战的人之一。他认为自由意志辩论的传统观念是不够的。他认为,决定论和自由意志主义的解释都与空间化倾向相冲突。柏格森的第一部主要作品《时间与自由意志》(Time and Free Will)试图将他对自由的理解建立在持续时间概念的基础上,与传统的理解形成对比。然而,柏格森积极抵制给自由下明确定义的尝试,他认为这最终会导致自由的空间化。通过关注柏格森在《时间与自由意志》中关于持续时间的概念,以及这个概念如何与自由联系起来,就有可能清晰地表达出一个积极的自由概念。在当前的气候下,争论柏格森思想的有效性时,这一点变得很重要。因此,对于柏格森来说,一个积极的自由概念可以被“定义”为“在持续时间的流动中创造新的东西”。然而,它不是可以定义的东西,而是可以定位的东西。
{"title":"Locating Freedom in Bergson's <i>Time and Free Will</i>","authors":"Brian Claude Macallan","doi":"10.5406/21543682.52.2.07","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21543682.52.2.07","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract The question of the nature of free will remains a perennial challenge for philosophy. The French philosopher Henri Bergson was one who sought to address this challenge. He argued that traditional conceptions of the free-will debate would not suffice. He suggested that both determinist and libertarian accounts fall foul of spatializing tendencies. Bergson's first major work, Time and Free Will, sought to ground his understanding of freedom, in contrast to traditional understandings, in the concept of duration. Bergson, however, actively resisted attempts to define clearly freedom, which he believed ultimately leads to a spatializing of freedom. By attending to Bergson's concept of duration in Time and Free Will, and how this concept relates to freedom, it becomes possible to articulate a positive conception of freedom. This becomes important when arguing for the validity of Bergson's ideas in the current climate. Thus, a positive conception of freedom for Bergson can be “defined” as “the creation of the new within the flow of duration.” It is, however, not something that can be defined, but is something that can be located.","PeriodicalId":315123,"journal":{"name":"Process Studies","volume":"16 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135565745","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Path to Understanding: Relation and Solidarity in Whitehead's Metaphysics 理解之路:怀特海形而上学中的关系与团结
Pub Date : 2023-11-01 DOI: 10.5406/21543682.52.2.06
Alessia Giacone
Abstract In this article, I will respond to questions regarding the ontological status of relations by exploring Whitehead's pivotal notion of solidarity, especially focusing on the recently published Harvard lectures. Particularly, I shall investigate how solidarity become a metaphysical law in the development of Whitehead's thought, also exploiting other Whiteheadian works of the same period, such as Science and the Modern World and Religion in the Making. I will attempt to show that the comprehension of an immediate brute fact necessarily requires its metaphysical interpretation as an item in a world with some systematic relation to it. I will thus provide my interpretation on solidarity through a comparison with Hegel's notion of Wirklichkeit.
在本文中,我将通过探索怀特黑德关于团结的关键概念来回答有关关系本体论地位的问题,特别是关注最近发表的哈佛讲座。特别是,我将研究团结如何在怀特黑德思想的发展中成为一种形而上学的规律,同时也利用怀特黑德在同一时期的其他作品,如《科学与现代世界》和《正在形成的宗教》。我将试图说明,要理解一个直接的、残酷的事实,就必须把它形而上学地解释为一个与它有系统关系的世界中的一个项目。因此,我将通过与黑格尔的“工作原理”概念的比较来提供我对团结的解释。
{"title":"The Path to Understanding: Relation and Solidarity in Whitehead's Metaphysics","authors":"Alessia Giacone","doi":"10.5406/21543682.52.2.06","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21543682.52.2.06","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract In this article, I will respond to questions regarding the ontological status of relations by exploring Whitehead's pivotal notion of solidarity, especially focusing on the recently published Harvard lectures. Particularly, I shall investigate how solidarity become a metaphysical law in the development of Whitehead's thought, also exploiting other Whiteheadian works of the same period, such as Science and the Modern World and Religion in the Making. I will attempt to show that the comprehension of an immediate brute fact necessarily requires its metaphysical interpretation as an item in a world with some systematic relation to it. I will thus provide my interpretation on solidarity through a comparison with Hegel's notion of Wirklichkeit.","PeriodicalId":315123,"journal":{"name":"Process Studies","volume":"14 6","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135565752","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Whitehead's Ethics: Fill in the Blanks Whitehead的伦理学:填空
Pub Date : 2023-11-01 DOI: 10.5406/21543682.52.2.03
Daniel Bella, Milan Stürmer
Abstract The recent publication of the stenographer's transcript of Whitehead's guest lecture on “social ethics” has shed new light on the relation between his metaphysics and ethics. Instead of including ethics in his philosophy, Whitehead treats it as a distinct, specialized science that does not share in the universality of metaphysics. The present article argues that an analysis of his lecture shows that a nonindividualist Whiteheadian ethics is possible without rupturing the coherence of Whitehead's system or contradicting the ontological or subjectivist principle. As part of a larger transition in Whitehead's thinking during the years 1925–1927, he reformulates the notion of the environment as inheritance and is therefore able to pose the question of the endurance of values at the level of society, which is the purview of ethics. Reconstructing the metaphysical background may provide a “stimulus to the imagination” for ethical debates today, especially in the field of environmental ethics.
摘要最近出版的怀特海“社会伦理”专题讲座速记稿,使人们对他的形而上学与伦理学之间的关系有了新的认识。怀特黑德没有将伦理学纳入他的哲学,而是将其视为一门独特的、专门的科学,不具有形而上学的普遍性。本文认为,对他的演讲的分析表明,一种非个人主义的怀特海伦理学是可能的,而不会破坏怀特海体系的连贯性,也不会与本体论或主观主义原则相矛盾。在1925-1927年间,怀特黑德的思想发生了更大的转变,他重新阐述了环境作为遗产的概念,因此能够提出价值观在社会层面上的持久性问题,这是伦理学的范围。重建形而上学的背景可以为今天的伦理辩论,特别是在环境伦理领域提供“想象的刺激”。
{"title":"Whitehead's Ethics: Fill in the Blanks","authors":"Daniel Bella, Milan Stürmer","doi":"10.5406/21543682.52.2.03","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21543682.52.2.03","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract The recent publication of the stenographer's transcript of Whitehead's guest lecture on “social ethics” has shed new light on the relation between his metaphysics and ethics. Instead of including ethics in his philosophy, Whitehead treats it as a distinct, specialized science that does not share in the universality of metaphysics. The present article argues that an analysis of his lecture shows that a nonindividualist Whiteheadian ethics is possible without rupturing the coherence of Whitehead's system or contradicting the ontological or subjectivist principle. As part of a larger transition in Whitehead's thinking during the years 1925–1927, he reformulates the notion of the environment as inheritance and is therefore able to pose the question of the endurance of values at the level of society, which is the purview of ethics. Reconstructing the metaphysical background may provide a “stimulus to the imagination” for ethical debates today, especially in the field of environmental ethics.","PeriodicalId":315123,"journal":{"name":"Process Studies","volume":"11 5","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135565479","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Starting With Whitehead: Raising Children to Thrive in Treacherous Times 从怀特海开始:在危险的时代培养孩子茁壮成长
Pub Date : 2023-11-01 DOI: 10.5406/21543682.52.2.08
Adam C. Scarfe
This book gives novel, vivid, rich, and profound expression to Whitehead's cyclical phases of Romance, Precision, and Generalization, belonging to the rhythm of learning, as he asserted in Aims of Education. As De Jonghe writes, Whitehead “described positive educational growth as an ongoing process involving three intertwined phases: the Romance of discovery, the development of Precision and mastery, and the emergence of Generalization when the realization of connectedness allows to take purposeful action and to raise new questions” (3). According to De Jonghe, for Whitehead, these interrelated and interweaving cycles represented “phases of the emergence of understanding as individuals experience educational events” (3).One main focus in the book is to apply many of the principles that are found in Whitehead's educational philosophy to the practice of schooling in order to assist children to be able to adapt to and “embrace change” (229) as well as “to learn and thrive, even in difficult times” (1). This includes not only the maintenance of one's well-being (and that of others), but the capability of persisting in crisis situations (e.g., geological, biomedical, ecological) that seem characteristic of our age, as well as being resilient in the face of the “challenging social conditions” (1) of the contemporary American context where there is much divisiveness surrounding education and educational policies. To these ends, De Jonghe examines “exemplary educational events characteristic of each of the three phases of learning,” and, from an analysis of them, draws conclusions and makes recommendations that provide “clarity on how to provide the best education for our children” (3).At the beginning of each chapter, De Jonghe relates interesting portraits, vignettes, or narratives of events of student learning. These are fictionalized simulacra inspired by real-life educational experiences that she and others have had with students. She examines them in depth with reference especially to Whitehead's educational philosophy but also to those of Dewey, Piaget, Noddings, Bruner, and so forth. Each case exhibits some important component of one or more of Whitehead's cyclical phases or stages of learning, the cases being arranged according to the general flow from the stage of Romance, to Precision, and on to Generalization, which help to form “the organizing structure of the book” (228). Roughly, the cases and their analyses in chapters 1 through 4 are chiefly about Romance (e.g., feeling, emotion, curiosity, imagination, art, and play), those in chapters 5 through 9 exhibit Precision (e.g., measurement, analysis, critical thinking, problem-solving, depth of learning, and mastery), and those in chapters 10 through 14 concern Generalization (e.g., restoration of the health of relationships, community, ecological interdependence, harmony, humor, and wisdom). Then De Jonghe shows how the educators in question, after some perplexity, obstruction, or unidentifi
这本书给怀特海的浪漫、精确和概括的循环阶段新颖、生动、丰富和深刻的表达,属于学习的节奏,正如他在《教育的目的》中所说的那样。正如德琼格所写,怀特黑德“将积极的教育成长描述为一个持续的过程,涉及三个相互交织的阶段:发现的浪漫,精确和掌握的发展,以及泛化的出现,当联系的实现允许采取有目的的行动并提出新的问题”(3)。这些相互关联和交织的循环代表了“个人经历教育事件时理解出现的各个阶段”(3)。本书的一个主要重点是将怀特黑德教育哲学中的许多原则应用到学校教育实践中,以帮助儿童能够适应和“拥抱变化”(229)以及“学习和成长”。这不仅包括维护自己(和他人)的福祉,还包括在危机情况下(例如,地质、生物医学、生态)坚持下去的能力,这些似乎是我们这个时代的特征,以及面对当代美国背景下“具有挑战性的社会条件”的弹性(1),其中围绕教育和教育政策存在很大分歧。为了达到这些目的,De Jonghe考察了“三个学习阶段中每个阶段的典型教育事件”,并从对它们的分析中得出结论并提出建议,以“明确如何为我们的孩子提供最好的教育”(3)。在每一章的开头,De Jonghe讲述了有趣的肖像、小插图或学生学习事件的叙述。这些是虚构的拟像,灵感来自她和其他人与学生的真实教育经历。她深入研究了他们,特别是参考怀特海的教育哲学,也参考了杜威、皮亚杰、诺丁斯、布鲁纳等人的教育哲学。每个案例都展示了Whitehead的一个或多个学习周期阶段或阶段的一些重要组成部分,这些案例按照从浪漫阶段到精确阶段再到概括阶段的一般流程进行排列,这有助于形成“本书的组织结构”(228)。粗略地说,第1章到第4章的案例及其分析主要是关于浪漫(例如,感觉,情感,好奇心,想象力,艺术和游戏),第5章到第9章的案例展示了精确性(例如,测量,分析,批判性思维,解决问题,学习深度和掌握),第10章到第14章的案例关注泛化(例如,恢复健康的关系,社区,生态相互依存,和谐,幽默和智慧)。然后,德·琼贺展示了在经历了一些困惑、阻碍或不明原因的学习过程窒息之后,这些教育者如何最终能够解开每个孩子的谜题,发现他们在学习背景下的内在动机或目的的一些关键方面,即“每个孩子如何作为一个个体脱颖而出……”(4)在这篇文章中,怀特黑德写道,学习者是“一个有生命的有机体,靠自我发展的冲动而成长。这种冲动可以从机体外部受到刺激和引导,也可以被杀死。但是,尽管有你们的刺激和指导,但成长的创造性冲动来自于内在,并且是个体的强烈特征”(AE 39;重点补充道)。在一个不断变化的世界中,危机和悲剧不断发生,与个人生活过程的紧急情况相联系,内心的创造性冲动是个人自力更生或恢复力的最大来源。教育者应该支持、参与和利用每个学生内心的这种探索的创造性冲动,而不是通过强加给学生太多无关的、外在的要求(例如,惰性的知识、过于复杂的方法和/或学生没有发言权的课程和目标)来阻碍它。在德琼格看来,这种取向要求教育者“从儿童本身出发,而不是从社会为他们设定的目标出发”(16)。通过对每一个典型案例的分析,德琼赫对教育和学习的具体认识产生了启发,她为教师和家长提供了现实而实用的见解,以培养年轻人的好奇心、分析能力和智慧。 教育学、课程和政策的问题应该(很大程度上)遵循实际的教师-学生-班级互动,尽管紧密地落后于它,而不是先验地规定教师-学习者的经验应该是什么,应该如何展开,学生应该是谁或什么,以及/或他们应该如何学习。与“为特定的社会、政治或经济目的服务的外在动机的学习”(例如外在的意识形态目标)相反,De Jonghe补充说,虽然以学生的内在动机为导向的教学方法“可能会被用于积极(甚至是消极)的社会、政治或经济目的”,但它“不会屈从于这些目的”(15-16)。因此,这种教学方法可以说是帮助学习者培养批判性思维能力,以及独立于我们这个时代不断轰炸他们的强大但往往有害的社会,政治和经济话语的能力。通过关注学生在学习背景下的内在动机,教育者可以帮助“支持儿童成熟的想象力,在他们身上建立进行复杂探究所必需的认知技能,并[帮助学生]发展社会智慧,在多元化社会中作为全球公民过上丰富的生活”(22)。由于内在合意性的事实是实体具有内在价值这一概念的基础,反过来,一种专注于学生内在动机的教学法可以说是最尊重他们的内在价值,并有助于培养学生捍卫内在价值的能力。在本卷的末尾,在附录中,De Jonghe确定了过程关系哲学的一些主要原则。她还简要地指出了一些可能有助于我们探索过程关系哲学对最近科学理论的影响的关键来源。这不仅对那些根据怀特黑德的过程关系哲学“初试水”的人有帮助,而且还暗示,在学校教育的背景下,学习不仅仅是年轻人的事情。更确切地说,它是一个持续不断的生命探索过程,我们每个人,甚至是成年人、科学家,甚至是老年人,都参与其中,因为我们,在我们生活的背景下,都站起来面对,“敬畏自然之网的魔力”(228),世界是纯粹的奇迹。总的来说,通过对具体学习事件的实际关联和考察,以及其富有洞察力的建议,德琼贺这本受怀特黑德启发的书在教育哲学这一高度重要的领域是一股受欢迎的“新鲜空气”。
{"title":"Starting With Whitehead: Raising Children to Thrive in Treacherous Times","authors":"Adam C. Scarfe","doi":"10.5406/21543682.52.2.08","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21543682.52.2.08","url":null,"abstract":"This book gives novel, vivid, rich, and profound expression to Whitehead's cyclical phases of Romance, Precision, and Generalization, belonging to the rhythm of learning, as he asserted in Aims of Education. As De Jonghe writes, Whitehead “described positive educational growth as an ongoing process involving three intertwined phases: the Romance of discovery, the development of Precision and mastery, and the emergence of Generalization when the realization of connectedness allows to take purposeful action and to raise new questions” (3). According to De Jonghe, for Whitehead, these interrelated and interweaving cycles represented “phases of the emergence of understanding as individuals experience educational events” (3).One main focus in the book is to apply many of the principles that are found in Whitehead's educational philosophy to the practice of schooling in order to assist children to be able to adapt to and “embrace change” (229) as well as “to learn and thrive, even in difficult times” (1). This includes not only the maintenance of one's well-being (and that of others), but the capability of persisting in crisis situations (e.g., geological, biomedical, ecological) that seem characteristic of our age, as well as being resilient in the face of the “challenging social conditions” (1) of the contemporary American context where there is much divisiveness surrounding education and educational policies. To these ends, De Jonghe examines “exemplary educational events characteristic of each of the three phases of learning,” and, from an analysis of them, draws conclusions and makes recommendations that provide “clarity on how to provide the best education for our children” (3).At the beginning of each chapter, De Jonghe relates interesting portraits, vignettes, or narratives of events of student learning. These are fictionalized simulacra inspired by real-life educational experiences that she and others have had with students. She examines them in depth with reference especially to Whitehead's educational philosophy but also to those of Dewey, Piaget, Noddings, Bruner, and so forth. Each case exhibits some important component of one or more of Whitehead's cyclical phases or stages of learning, the cases being arranged according to the general flow from the stage of Romance, to Precision, and on to Generalization, which help to form “the organizing structure of the book” (228). Roughly, the cases and their analyses in chapters 1 through 4 are chiefly about Romance (e.g., feeling, emotion, curiosity, imagination, art, and play), those in chapters 5 through 9 exhibit Precision (e.g., measurement, analysis, critical thinking, problem-solving, depth of learning, and mastery), and those in chapters 10 through 14 concern Generalization (e.g., restoration of the health of relationships, community, ecological interdependence, harmony, humor, and wisdom). Then De Jonghe shows how the educators in question, after some perplexity, obstruction, or unidentifi","PeriodicalId":315123,"journal":{"name":"Process Studies","volume":"17 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135565740","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Open Future: Why Future Contingents Are All False 开放的未来:为什么未来偶然事件都是假的
Pub Date : 2023-11-01 DOI: 10.5406/21543682.52.2.09
Donald Wayne Viney
{"title":"The Open Future: Why Future Contingents Are All False","authors":"Donald Wayne Viney","doi":"10.5406/21543682.52.2.09","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21543682.52.2.09","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":315123,"journal":{"name":"Process Studies","volume":"16 4","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135565742","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
From a Philosophy of Evolution to a Philosophy of Organism 从进化哲学到有机体哲学
Pub Date : 2023-11-01 DOI: 10.5406/21543682.52.2.04
Paul A. Bogaard
Abstract In this article, Whitehead's transition from a Philosophy of Evolution to a Philosophy of Organism is studied primarily on the basis of the evidence provided by the first two volumes of The Harvard Lectures of Alfred North Whitehead, especially the second volume that deals with the period 1925–1927 and that is subtitled General Metaphysical Problems of Science.
在本文中,怀特海从进化哲学到有机体哲学的转变主要是在阿尔弗雷德·诺斯·怀特海的哈佛讲座前两卷提供的证据的基础上进行研究的,特别是第二卷,涉及1925-1927年期间,副标题为科学的一般形而上学问题。
{"title":"From a Philosophy of Evolution to a Philosophy of Organism","authors":"Paul A. Bogaard","doi":"10.5406/21543682.52.2.04","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21543682.52.2.04","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract In this article, Whitehead's transition from a Philosophy of Evolution to a Philosophy of Organism is studied primarily on the basis of the evidence provided by the first two volumes of The Harvard Lectures of Alfred North Whitehead, especially the second volume that deals with the period 1925–1927 and that is subtitled General Metaphysical Problems of Science.","PeriodicalId":315123,"journal":{"name":"Process Studies","volume":"11 4","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135565480","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Whitehead's 1925–1927 View of Function and Time 怀特海1925-1927年的函数和时间观
Pub Date : 2023-11-01 DOI: 10.5406/21543682.52.2.05
Ronny Desmet
Abstract Whitehead's 1925–1927 Harvard lectures (HL2) are too rich in content to easily summarize. Consequently, I limit myself in the present article to giving an account pivoting around Whitehead's functional theory of reality and his epochal theory of time.
怀特黑德1925-1927年的哈佛讲座(HL2)内容过于丰富,难以概括。因此,在这篇文章中,我将自己限制在以怀特黑德的现实功能理论和他的时间划时代理论为中心进行叙述。
{"title":"Whitehead's 1925–1927 View of Function and Time","authors":"Ronny Desmet","doi":"10.5406/21543682.52.2.05","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21543682.52.2.05","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Whitehead's 1925–1927 Harvard lectures (HL2) are too rich in content to easily summarize. Consequently, I limit myself in the present article to giving an account pivoting around Whitehead's functional theory of reality and his epochal theory of time.","PeriodicalId":315123,"journal":{"name":"Process Studies","volume":"16 2","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135565744","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Bateson's Process Ontology for Psychological Practice 贝特森的心理实践过程本体论
Pub Date : 2023-05-01 DOI: 10.5406/21543682.52.1.06
Julien Tempone-Wiltshire, Tra-ill Dowie
The work of Gregory Bateson offers a metaphysical basis for a “process psychology,” that is, a view of psychological practice and research guided by an ontology of becoming—identifying change, difference, and relationship as the basic elements of a foundational metaphysics. This article explores the relevance of Bateson's recursive epistemology, his reconception of the Great Chain of Being, a first-principles approach to defining the nature of mind, and understandings of interaction and difference, pattern and symmetry, interpretation and context. Bateson's philosophical contributions will be drawn into relationship with Wittgenstein's philosophy of language as use, Melnyk's theory of causal levels of explanation, Korzybski's account of map and territory, the rejection of the heuristic rigidity of substantialist ontologies, and a cybernetics communication science-informed approach to contextual-bidirectionality of causality. We thereby arrive at an understanding of Bateson's process psychology that, given its ecological-systemic nature, is explanatorily applicable across the mind sciences. This process psychology equips us to answer the question: What is mind? Not by explanatory appeal to substantial entities contained within mind, but instead by recourse to the contextually relevant patterns for understanding mind to a particular purpose. We have thereby attended to the gulf between heuristics and fundamentals, between psychological models and an onto-epistemic account of reality. Insufficient attention has been given to characterizing the vital nature of Bateson's philosophical oeuvre to psychological practice. This article draws out Bateson's relevance to establishing foundational principles for a process psychology capable of reinvigorating psychological thought.
格雷戈里·贝特森的作品为“过程心理学”提供了形而上学的基础,也就是说,这是一种由生成本体论指导的心理学实践和研究观点——将变化、差异和关系作为基础形而上学的基本要素。本文探讨了贝特森递归认识论的相关性,他对存在大链的重新构想,定义心灵本质的第一原则方法,以及对相互作用和差异,模式和对称,解释和背景的理解。贝特森的哲学贡献将与维特根斯坦的语言使用哲学、梅尔尼克的因果层次解释理论、科尔日布斯基对地图和领域的描述、对实体主义本体论的启发性僵化的拒绝,以及对因果关系的语境双向性的控制论交流科学方法联系起来。因此,我们对贝特森的过程心理学有了一种理解,鉴于其生态系统的本质,它在解释上适用于所有的心理科学。这个过程心理学使我们能够回答这个问题:什么是精神?不是通过对心智中包含的实体的解释性呼吁,而是通过求助于上下文相关的模式来理解特定目的的心智。因此,我们注意到启发式和基本原理之间的鸿沟,心理模型和对现实的本体认知解释之间的鸿沟。人们对贝特森哲学作品对心理实践的重要性质的描述不够重视。本文指出了贝特森对建立过程心理学的基本原则的重要性,过程心理学能够使心理学思想重新焕发活力。
{"title":"Bateson's Process Ontology for Psychological Practice","authors":"Julien Tempone-Wiltshire, Tra-ill Dowie","doi":"10.5406/21543682.52.1.06","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5406/21543682.52.1.06","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000 The work of Gregory Bateson offers a metaphysical basis for a “process psychology,” that is, a view of psychological practice and research guided by an ontology of becoming—identifying change, difference, and relationship as the basic elements of a foundational metaphysics. This article explores the relevance of Bateson's recursive epistemology, his reconception of the Great Chain of Being, a first-principles approach to defining the nature of mind, and understandings of interaction and difference, pattern and symmetry, interpretation and context. Bateson's philosophical contributions will be drawn into relationship with Wittgenstein's philosophy of language as use, Melnyk's theory of causal levels of explanation, Korzybski's account of map and territory, the rejection of the heuristic rigidity of substantialist ontologies, and a cybernetics communication science-informed approach to contextual-bidirectionality of causality. We thereby arrive at an understanding of Bateson's process psychology that, given its ecological-systemic nature, is explanatorily applicable across the mind sciences. This process psychology equips us to answer the question: What is mind? Not by explanatory appeal to substantial entities contained within mind, but instead by recourse to the contextually relevant patterns for understanding mind to a particular purpose. We have thereby attended to the gulf between heuristics and fundamentals, between psychological models and an onto-epistemic account of reality. Insufficient attention has been given to characterizing the vital nature of Bateson's philosophical oeuvre to psychological practice. This article draws out Bateson's relevance to establishing foundational principles for a process psychology capable of reinvigorating psychological thought.","PeriodicalId":315123,"journal":{"name":"Process Studies","volume":"210 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-05-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"132110451","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
期刊
Process Studies
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1