首页 > 最新文献

Conversations: The Journal of Cavellian Studies最新文献

英文 中文
Hegel and Cavell on Meaning and Sublation 黑格尔和卡维尔论意义和扬弃
Pub Date : 2022-03-03 DOI: 10.18192/cjcs.vi9.6247
A. Norris
Hegel is not an author who plays a starring role in Cavell’s work like that of Austin, Wittgenstein, or Emerson. Cavell mentions him rarely, and almost always in passing. This is hardly surprising. Given that Cavell draws as heavily as he does upon Kant, whom Hegel regularly attacks, and Kierkegaard, who regularly attacks Hegel, one might expect that Hegel’s more important claims and ideas would be uncongenial to Cavell, and incompatible with the main lines of his work. Moreover, Cavell’s early and lasting embrace of Romanticism would seem to preclude the embrace of an author who lambasts the leading Jena Romantic Friedrich von Schlegel as the purveyor of a corrosive amoral subjectivism. Appearances, however, can be deceiving, and in the essay that follows I demonstrate that there are good reasons to believe that Hegel has influenced Cavell considerably more than one might suppose.
黑格尔不像奥斯汀,维特根斯坦或爱默生那样在卡维尔的作品中扮演主角。卡维尔很少提到他,而且几乎总是顺带一提。这不足为奇。考虑到卡维尔对康德(黑格尔经常攻击康德)和克尔凯郭尔(克尔凯郭尔也经常攻击黑格尔)的借鉴,人们可能会认为,黑格尔更重要的主张和观点与卡维尔不一致,也不符合他作品的主线。此外,卡维尔对浪漫主义的早期和持久的拥抱似乎排除了对一位作家的拥抱,这位作家痛斥耶拿浪漫主义的领军人物弗里德里希·冯·施莱格尔是一种腐蚀性的非道德主观主义的提供者。然而,表象是具有欺骗性的,在接下来的文章中,我证明有充分的理由相信黑格尔对卡维尔的影响比人们想象的要大得多。
{"title":"Hegel and Cavell on Meaning and Sublation","authors":"A. Norris","doi":"10.18192/cjcs.vi9.6247","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.18192/cjcs.vi9.6247","url":null,"abstract":"Hegel is not an author who plays a starring role in Cavell’s work like that of Austin, Wittgenstein, or Emerson. Cavell mentions him rarely, and almost always in passing. This is hardly surprising. Given that Cavell draws as heavily as he does upon Kant, whom Hegel regularly attacks, and Kierkegaard, who regularly attacks Hegel, one might expect that Hegel’s more important claims and ideas would be uncongenial to Cavell, and incompatible with the main lines of his work. Moreover, Cavell’s early and lasting embrace of Romanticism would seem to preclude the embrace of an author who lambasts the leading Jena Romantic Friedrich von Schlegel as the purveyor of a corrosive amoral subjectivism. Appearances, however, can be deceiving, and in the essay that follows I demonstrate that there are good reasons to believe that Hegel has influenced Cavell considerably more than one might suppose.","PeriodicalId":342666,"journal":{"name":"Conversations: The Journal of Cavellian Studies","volume":"41 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2022-03-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"114286091","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Philosophy of Mind Becomes Aesthetics 心灵哲学变成了美学
Pub Date : 2022-03-03 DOI: 10.18192/cjcs.vi9.6250
Moses Estrada-Alvarez
That human (op)positions, contradiction and conflict, permeate our world is obvious; however, if, we (human beings) share a conceptual scheme, common to us all, how then we can agree and disagree, accept and reject, admit or repress, recognize and misrecognize so much in our worlds—between others and ourselves—is not obvious, or needs to be recounted. Notwithstanding, we want to reconsider our shared conceptual scheme—the necessities apart from which we cannot say what we ordinarily say, or even do. To be sure, the (op)positions result from these necessities. It is that sort of necessity, so to say, logic, or “what is common to us all,” that “we” want to describe, figure out or find out in ordinary language. To acknowledge a Cavellian insinuation: the necessities, being human, we must affirm and deny at once (i.e. the sense I sketch out from the epigraph above). In this essay, I claim that that is a dialectic inherent in ordinary language (in human forms of life).
人类的立场,矛盾和冲突,渗透到我们的世界是显而易见的;然而,如果我们(人类)有一个共同的概念体系,那么我们如何在我们的世界里——在他人和我们自己之间——同意和不同意、接受和拒绝、承认或压制、承认和误解这么多,就不那么明显了,或者需要重新叙述。尽管如此,我们还是想重新考虑一下我们共有的概念方案——没有这些必需品,我们就不能说我们通常所说的,甚至不能做我们通常所说的。当然,(op)职位是由这些必需品造成的。这种必然性,也就是所谓的逻辑,或“我们大家共有的东西”,正是“我们”想要用日常语言来描述、弄明白或发现的东西。要承认卡维尔式的暗示:作为人的必然性,我们必须同时肯定和否认(即我从上面的题词中概括出的意义)。在本文中,我认为这是日常语言(人类生活形式)中固有的辩证法。
{"title":"Philosophy of Mind Becomes Aesthetics","authors":"Moses Estrada-Alvarez","doi":"10.18192/cjcs.vi9.6250","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.18192/cjcs.vi9.6250","url":null,"abstract":"That human (op)positions, contradiction and conflict, permeate our world is obvious; however, if, we (human beings) share a conceptual scheme, common to us all, how then we can agree and disagree, accept and reject, admit or repress, recognize and misrecognize so much in our worlds—between others and ourselves—is not obvious, or needs to be recounted. Notwithstanding, we want to reconsider our shared conceptual scheme—the necessities apart from which we cannot say what we ordinarily say, or even do. To be sure, the (op)positions result from these necessities. It is that sort of necessity, so to say, logic, or “what is common to us all,” that “we” want to describe, figure out or find out in ordinary language. To acknowledge a Cavellian insinuation: the necessities, being human, we must affirm and deny at once (i.e. the sense I sketch out from the epigraph above). In this essay, I claim that that is a dialectic inherent in ordinary language (in human forms of life).","PeriodicalId":342666,"journal":{"name":"Conversations: The Journal of Cavellian Studies","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2022-03-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"130014606","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Cavell and the Achievement of Selfhood 卡维尔与自我的实现
Pub Date : 2022-03-03 DOI: 10.18192/cjcs.vi9.6244
Richard Eldridge
Here is a passage from the discussion of rhythm in music in Hegel’s Aesthetics that will, I suggest, help us to make sense of some important ideas in Cavell about the achievement of selfhood. This runs some risk of explicating the obscure, Cavell, by reference to the unintelligible, Hegel, but Hegel also helps us here specifically to focus on the ontology and ontogeny of selfhood.
这里有一段摘自黑格尔《美学》中关于音乐节奏的讨论我认为,这将有助于我们理解卡维尔关于自我成就的一些重要观点。这有可能解释卡维尔晦涩难懂的黑格尔,但黑格尔在这里也帮助我们特别关注自我的本体论和本体论。
{"title":"Cavell and the Achievement of Selfhood","authors":"Richard Eldridge","doi":"10.18192/cjcs.vi9.6244","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.18192/cjcs.vi9.6244","url":null,"abstract":"Here is a passage from the discussion of rhythm in music in Hegel’s Aesthetics that will, I suggest, help us to make sense of some important ideas in Cavell about the achievement of selfhood. This runs some risk of explicating the obscure, Cavell, by reference to the unintelligible, Hegel, but Hegel also helps us here specifically to focus on the ontology and ontogeny of selfhood.","PeriodicalId":342666,"journal":{"name":"Conversations: The Journal of Cavellian Studies","volume":"48 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2022-03-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"114061477","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Against “Finitude” 反对“界限”
Pub Date : 2022-03-03 DOI: 10.18192/cjcs.vi9.6245
R. Read
In this essay, I seek to follow and draw upon resources in Ludwig Wittgenstein (and in an important contemporary follower of his, Iain McGilchrist) in order to pose a radical question. I question here the conventional “wisdom” across philosophical traditions (and cleaved to equally strongly by Cavell and Derrida, and for that matter by Richard Dawkins and Donald Davidson), that says—or rather even, simply assumes—that we are finite beings.
在这篇文章中,我试图遵循和借鉴路德维希·维特根斯坦(以及他的一个重要的当代追随者,伊恩·麦吉尔克里斯特)的资源,以提出一个激进的问题。在这里,我对跨越哲学传统的传统“智慧”(卡维尔和德里达以及理查德·道金斯和唐纳德·戴维森同样强烈地支持这一点)提出质疑,即我们是有限的存在,或者更确切地说,只是假设。
{"title":"Against “Finitude”","authors":"R. Read","doi":"10.18192/cjcs.vi9.6245","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.18192/cjcs.vi9.6245","url":null,"abstract":"In this essay, I seek to follow and draw upon resources in Ludwig Wittgenstein (and in an important contemporary follower of his, Iain McGilchrist) in order to pose a radical question. I question here the conventional “wisdom” across philosophical traditions (and cleaved to equally strongly by Cavell and Derrida, and for that matter by Richard Dawkins and Donald Davidson), that says—or rather even, simply assumes—that we are finite beings.","PeriodicalId":342666,"journal":{"name":"Conversations: The Journal of Cavellian Studies","volume":"19 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2022-03-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"124307586","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Some Notes on Philosophy and Redemption 关于哲学与救赎的一些笔记
Pub Date : 2022-03-03 DOI: 10.18192/cjcs.vi9.6248
Martin Shuster
In an earlier essay, I once drew a comparison between Theodor W. Adorno’s remark that, “philosophy, which once appeared obsolete, sustains itself because the moment for its actualization has been lost,” and Stanley Cavell’s suggestion that Ludwig Wittgenstein’s “Investigations can be seen as a philosophy of culture, one that relates itself to its time as a time in which the continuation of philosophy is at stake.” In this essay, I’d like to compare Adorno’s remark to a different but related remark of Cavell’s, namely his thought that “philosophy ends in a recovery from a terminable loss.” He pursues this thought in remarks on Emerson, noting that “philosophy begins in loss, in finding yourself at a loss, as Wittgenstein more or less says.” Many different traditions—Marxism, American transcendentalism, ordinary language philosophy, just to name a few—animate these thoughts. This is not the place to detail and tease out the ramifications and significances of each; instead, I want to take this very short essay merely to raise a different point of relation than I raised before (in a deep way, then, this essay—and especially its short length—may be seen as a sort of afterword to my earlier remarks).
在早些时候的一篇文章中,我曾经比较过西奥多·阿多诺(Theodor W. Adorno)的评论,“哲学,曾经显得过时,维持自己,因为它的实现时刻已经失去了”,和斯坦利·卡维尔(Stanley Cavell)的建议,路德维希·维特根斯坦(Ludwig Wittgenstein)的“研究可以被视为一种文化哲学,一种将自己与时代联系起来的哲学,在这个时代,哲学的延续受到威胁。”在这篇文章中,我想将阿多诺的评论与卡维尔的另一个不同但相关的评论进行比较,即他认为“哲学结束于从一个不可终结的损失中恢复过来”。他在对爱默生的评论中追求这一思想,指出“哲学始于迷失,始于发现自己处于迷失之中,正如维特根斯坦或多或少所说的那样。”许多不同的传统——马克思主义、美国先验主义、普通语言哲学,仅举几例——激发了这些思想。这里不是详细梳理每一个分支和意义的地方;相反,我想用这篇很短的文章来提出一个与我之前提出的不同的关系点(从更深的角度来说,这篇文章——尤其是它的短长度——可以被看作是我之前评论的一种后记)。
{"title":"Some Notes on Philosophy and Redemption","authors":"Martin Shuster","doi":"10.18192/cjcs.vi9.6248","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.18192/cjcs.vi9.6248","url":null,"abstract":"In an earlier essay, I once drew a comparison between Theodor W. Adorno’s remark that, “philosophy, which once appeared obsolete, sustains itself because the moment for its actualization has been lost,” and Stanley Cavell’s suggestion that Ludwig Wittgenstein’s “Investigations can be seen as a philosophy of culture, one that relates itself to its time as a time in which the continuation of philosophy is at stake.” In this essay, I’d like to compare Adorno’s remark to a different but related remark of Cavell’s, namely his thought that “philosophy ends in a recovery from a terminable loss.” He pursues this thought in remarks on Emerson, noting that “philosophy begins in loss, in finding yourself at a loss, as Wittgenstein more or less says.” Many different traditions—Marxism, American transcendentalism, ordinary language philosophy, just to name a few—animate these thoughts. This is not the place to detail and tease out the ramifications and significances of each; instead, I want to take this very short essay merely to raise a different point of relation than I raised before (in a deep way, then, this essay—and especially its short length—may be seen as a sort of afterword to my earlier remarks).","PeriodicalId":342666,"journal":{"name":"Conversations: The Journal of Cavellian Studies","volume":"9 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2022-03-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"129355184","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Marriage as Madness 婚姻是疯狂的
Pub Date : 2020-12-28 DOI: 10.18192/cjcs.vi8.5792
Lucas Thompson
Aside from being one of the best books ever written on film, Stanley Cavell’s 1979 masterpiece Pursuits of Happiness: The Hollywood Comedy of Remarriage is surely also one of the best investigations we have into the institution of marriage. Here as elsewhere, Cavell has multiple targets in his sights. Along with mapping out a new subgenre within the screwball comedy and moving the then-newly christened discipline of film studies forward, his aims are also philosophical (searching for the ways in which these films “disquiet the foundations of our lives”), sociological (searching for cultural connections between the two waves of feminism), and matrimonial. Cavell is trying to discover what makes marriages work, and under what conditions a married pair might be able to find the “thirst for remarriage” that he takes as its essential element. Moving well beyond accounting for filmic portrayals of the married state, Pursuits is a virtuosic exploration of marriage itself, with countless insights to offer.
除了是有史以来最好的电影书籍之一,斯坦利·卡维尔1979年的杰作《追求幸福:好莱坞再婚喜剧》无疑也是我们对婚姻制度的最好调查之一。在这里和其他地方一样,卡维尔有多个目标。除了在怪诞喜剧中描绘出一个新的亚类型,并推动当时刚刚被命名的电影研究学科向前发展,他的目标还包括哲学(寻找这些电影“扰乱我们生活基础”的方式)、社会学(寻找两波女权主义浪潮之间的文化联系)和婚姻。卡维尔试图发现是什么让婚姻有效,以及在什么条件下,已婚夫妇可能会找到他认为是其基本要素的“对再婚的渴望”。《追求》远远超出了电影对婚姻状态的描述,它是对婚姻本身的一次精湛探索,提供了无数的见解。
{"title":"Marriage as Madness","authors":"Lucas Thompson","doi":"10.18192/cjcs.vi8.5792","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.18192/cjcs.vi8.5792","url":null,"abstract":"Aside from being one of the best books ever written on film, Stanley Cavell’s 1979 masterpiece Pursuits of Happiness: The Hollywood Comedy of Remarriage is surely also one of the best investigations we have into the institution of marriage. Here as elsewhere, Cavell has multiple targets in his sights. Along with mapping out a new subgenre within the screwball comedy and moving the then-newly christened discipline of film studies forward, his aims are also philosophical (searching for the ways in which these films “disquiet the foundations of our lives”), sociological (searching for cultural connections between the two waves of feminism), and matrimonial. Cavell is trying to discover what makes marriages work, and under what conditions a married pair might be able to find the “thirst for remarriage” that he takes as its essential element. Moving well beyond accounting for filmic portrayals of the married state, Pursuits is a virtuosic exploration of marriage itself, with countless insights to offer.","PeriodicalId":342666,"journal":{"name":"Conversations: The Journal of Cavellian Studies","volume":"4 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-12-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"114284230","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Getting to the Heart of It 进入它的核心
Pub Date : 2020-12-28 DOI: 10.18192/cjcs.vi8.5789
Brad Tabas
When I wrote the following pages, or rather the bulk of them, I was seated in cafés in Paris, intermittently employed as an adjunct professor, and engaged in a struggle to find my professional place and philosophical voice. I lived in this way for almost six years. At present I am a tenured professor at a prestigious French engineering school, seated at my desk and enjoying the sense of well-being and intellectual liberty that such a position provides.
当我写下面几页,或者更确切地说是大部分的时候,我正坐在巴黎的咖啡馆里,断断续续地担任兼职教授,努力寻找自己的专业位置和哲学声音。我就这样生活了将近六年。目前,我是法国一所著名工程学院的终身教授,坐在办公桌前,享受着这种职位带来的幸福感和思想自由。
{"title":"Getting to the Heart of It","authors":"Brad Tabas","doi":"10.18192/cjcs.vi8.5789","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.18192/cjcs.vi8.5789","url":null,"abstract":"When I wrote the following pages, or rather the bulk of them, I was seated in cafés in Paris, intermittently employed as an adjunct professor, and engaged in a struggle to find my professional place and philosophical voice. I lived in this way for almost six years. At present I am a tenured professor at a prestigious French engineering school, seated at my desk and enjoying the sense of well-being and intellectual liberty that such a position provides.","PeriodicalId":342666,"journal":{"name":"Conversations: The Journal of Cavellian Studies","volume":"86 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-12-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"123589103","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Mood of the World 世界的情绪
Pub Date : 2020-12-28 DOI: 10.18192/CJCS.VI8.5788
A. Norris
The phrase, “epistemology of moods,” appears in Stanley Cavell’s writings in the late 1970’s, as The Claim of Reason is published and Cavell begins the direct engagement with Emerson around which his work will pivot for the rest of his career. Indeed, it is as an “epistemologist of moods” that Emerson first appeals to Cavell in his own right, and not as merely a “second-hand Thoreau.” The phrase is an odd one. Most of us would not think that knowledge and mood are connected in the way it suggests: my foul mood may make it difficult for me to concentrate on, say, my taxes, but it does not appear to otherwise affect my ability to know how much or how little I owe—and the same could be said of Sextus’ honey, Descartes’ ball of wax, Price’s tomato, and Clarke’s block of cheese. The oddity of the phrase is, if anything, even more marked when coming from Cavell: though Cavell is deeply interested in questions of self-knowledge, and of our ability to speak for one another and in that sense know one another, he is not an epistemologist; and when he writes of epistemology he often uses phrases like traditional epistemology or classical epistemology that distance him from it. Cavell does not share the traditional epistemologist’s interest in determining what, if anything, might warrant our claims to knowledge of the empirical world or the existence of “other minds”; and “the truth of skepticism” that he announces and explores is not the truth of the claims of the epistemological skeptic regarding such matters. While the epistemologist seeks to assure himself of the certainty of his knowledge, Cavell seeks to understand our disappointment with the knowledge we have. What, then, does Cavell mean by this phrase? What is the epistemology of moods?
"情绪的认识论"这个词出现在斯坦利·卡维尔的作品中是在20世纪70年代末,当时《理性的主张》出版了卡维尔开始与爱默生直接接触他的作品将围绕这一点展开他接下来的职业生涯。事实上,正是作为一个“情绪的认识论家”,爱默生首先以自己的身份吸引了卡维尔,而不仅仅是作为一个“二手的梭罗”。这句话很奇怪。我们大多数人都不会认为知识和情绪以它所暗示的方式联系在一起:我糟糕的情绪可能使我难以集中精力,比如说,我的税收,但它似乎不会影响我知道自己欠多少钱的能力——塞克斯图斯的蜂蜜、笛卡尔的蜡球、普莱斯的番茄和克拉克的奶酪块也是如此。这句话的奇怪之处,如果有的话,当出自卡维尔之口时就更加明显了:尽管卡维尔对自我认识的问题,以及我们为彼此说话的能力以及在这种意义上相互了解的能力非常感兴趣,但他不是一个认识论家;当他写认识论的时候,他经常使用传统认识论或古典认识论这样的短语,使他与认识论保持距离。卡维尔不像传统的认识论家那样,对确定什么(如果有的话)可以保证我们对经验世界的知识或“其他心灵”的存在的主张感兴趣;他所宣布和探索的"怀疑主义的真理"并不是认识论怀疑论者关于这些问题的主张的真理。当认识论家试图确保自己知识的确定性时,卡维尔试图理解我们对现有知识的失望。那么,卡维尔用这个短语是什么意思呢?情绪的认识论是什么?
{"title":"The Mood of the World","authors":"A. Norris","doi":"10.18192/CJCS.VI8.5788","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.18192/CJCS.VI8.5788","url":null,"abstract":"The phrase, “epistemology of moods,” appears in Stanley Cavell’s writings in the late 1970’s, as The Claim of Reason is published and Cavell begins the direct engagement with Emerson around which his work will pivot for the rest of his career. Indeed, it is as an “epistemologist of moods” that Emerson first appeals to Cavell in his own right, and not as merely a “second-hand Thoreau.” The phrase is an odd one. Most of us would not think that knowledge and mood are connected in the way it suggests: my foul mood may make it difficult for me to concentrate on, say, my taxes, but it does not appear to otherwise affect my ability to know how much or how little I owe—and the same could be said of Sextus’ honey, Descartes’ ball of wax, Price’s tomato, and Clarke’s block of cheese. The oddity of the phrase is, if anything, even more marked when coming from Cavell: though Cavell is deeply interested in questions of self-knowledge, and of our ability to speak for one another and in that sense know one another, he is not an epistemologist; and when he writes of epistemology he often uses phrases like traditional epistemology or classical epistemology that distance him from it. Cavell does not share the traditional epistemologist’s interest in determining what, if anything, might warrant our claims to knowledge of the empirical world or the existence of “other minds”; and “the truth of skepticism” that he announces and explores is not the truth of the claims of the epistemological skeptic regarding such matters. While the epistemologist seeks to assure himself of the certainty of his knowledge, Cavell seeks to understand our disappointment with the knowledge we have. What, then, does Cavell mean by this phrase? What is the epistemology of moods?","PeriodicalId":342666,"journal":{"name":"Conversations: The Journal of Cavellian Studies","volume":"5 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-12-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"130268954","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Editorial Comment 社论评论
Pub Date : 2020-12-28 DOI: 10.18192/cjcs.vi8.5787
Sérgio Dias Branco, Amir Khan
The eighth issue of Conversations is open-themed. Nonetheless, the articles gathered here coalesce around issues of feeling it. This is perhaps not altogether anomalous as all good writing is in some capacity a matter of feeling. But beginning with Andrew Norris, we are invited to consider how Cavell’s moods inflect not simply his writing, but from there, his world and possibly the world. Managing to maintain attachments to professional philosophy after explicitly describing the world in a mooded way is perhaps amongst Cavell’s notable (even Heideggarian) achievements. Next, Brad Tabas reminds us that our place in the universe costs money, is expensive—and that philosophy requires coming to terms with a mood of cannibalism that accompanies the stark realization and possibility that my voice or mood negates another’s. Philosophy or thinking or what have you quite possibly eats itself. Michael McCreary notes a similar mood of failed catharsis in Dostoevsky’s Underground Man and by so doing, provides a sorely needed Cavellian commentary on the possibility of failed expression, of what happens when the costs of mooding the world results not in ordinary transcendence, but extraordinary rage. Charles Djordjevic looks to what one might perhaps term a Cavellian sense of “play” to deal with extraordinary railings. The move to take language on holiday, that is, is not indicative necessarily of Wittgensteinian error but perhaps a type of philosophical therapy afforded to human beings by virtue of (a Kierkegaardian) faith. Lucas Thompson more subtly exposes the lack of faith in contemporary treatment of Cavell’s philosophical work on film, exposing the naïve belief that takes Cavell to be naïve for not engaging forcefully enough in “ideology critique”; not only does Thompson champion Cavell’s genre of remarriage comedies in rebuttal, but he ably adds another film to the mix. Lastly, a welcome and spirited addendum concludes the issue in dialogic exchange. Two recently published Cavellian authors, Rex Butler and Catherine Wheatley, discuss how Cavell might be better integrated into a wider, more contentious, and certainly more mooded, world of gender and identity politics. 
《对话》第八期为开放主题。尽管如此,这里收集的文章都围绕着感受它的问题。这也许并不完全反常,因为所有优秀的作品在某种程度上都是一种情感问题。但从安德鲁·诺里斯开始,我们被邀请去思考卡维尔的情绪是如何影响的,不仅仅是他的作品,还有他的世界,可能还有整个世界。在以一种情绪化的方式明确地描述世界之后,设法保持对专业哲学的依恋,也许是卡维尔最显著的成就之一(甚至是海德格尔式的成就)。接下来,布拉德·塔巴斯提醒我们,我们在宇宙中的地位是要花钱的,是昂贵的,而这种哲学要求我们接受一种同类相食的情绪,这种情绪伴随着我的声音或情绪否定他人的鲜明认识和可能性。哲学,思想,或者其他的东西很可能会自我吞噬。迈克尔·麦克里在陀思妥耶夫斯基的《地下人》中提到了类似的宣泄失败的情绪,通过这样做,他提供了一种迫切需要的卡维尔式的评论,说明表达失败的可能性,当情绪世界的代价不是普通的超越,而是非凡的愤怒时,会发生什么。查尔斯·乔杰维奇(Charles Djordjevic)用一种人们可能称之为卡维尔式的“玩耍”来处理非凡的栏杆。也就是说,把语言当作假日的举动并不一定表明维特根斯坦的错误,而可能是一种哲学疗法,通过(克尔凯郭尔式的)信仰给予人类。卢卡斯·汤普森更巧妙地揭示了对卡维尔电影哲学著作的当代处理缺乏信心,揭示了naïve认为卡维尔是naïve的信念,认为他没有足够有力地参与“意识形态批判”;汤普森不仅在反驳中为卡维尔的再婚喜剧类型赢得了冠军,而且他还巧妙地为这一组合添加了另一部电影。最后,一份令人欢迎和振奋的增编在对话交流中结束了这个问题。雷克斯·巴特勒(Rex Butler)和凯瑟琳·惠特利(Catherine Wheatley)这两位最近出版的卡维尔主义作家讨论了如何更好地将卡维尔融入一个更广泛、更有争议、当然也更情绪化的性别和身份政治世界。
{"title":"Editorial Comment","authors":"Sérgio Dias Branco, Amir Khan","doi":"10.18192/cjcs.vi8.5787","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.18192/cjcs.vi8.5787","url":null,"abstract":"The eighth issue of Conversations is open-themed. Nonetheless, the articles gathered here coalesce around issues of feeling it. This is perhaps not altogether anomalous as all good writing is in some capacity a matter of feeling. But beginning with Andrew Norris, we are invited to consider how Cavell’s moods inflect not simply his writing, but from there, his world and possibly the world. Managing to maintain attachments to professional philosophy after explicitly describing the world in a mooded way is perhaps amongst Cavell’s notable (even Heideggarian) achievements. Next, Brad Tabas reminds us that our place in the universe costs money, is expensive—and that philosophy requires coming to terms with a mood of cannibalism that accompanies the stark realization and possibility that my voice or mood negates another’s. Philosophy or thinking or what have you quite possibly eats itself. Michael McCreary notes a similar mood of failed catharsis in Dostoevsky’s Underground Man and by so doing, provides a sorely needed Cavellian commentary on the possibility of failed expression, of what happens when the costs of mooding the world results not in ordinary transcendence, but extraordinary rage. Charles Djordjevic looks to what one might perhaps term a Cavellian sense of “play” to deal with extraordinary railings. The move to take language on holiday, that is, is not indicative necessarily of Wittgensteinian error but perhaps a type of philosophical therapy afforded to human beings by virtue of (a Kierkegaardian) faith. Lucas Thompson more subtly exposes the lack of faith in contemporary treatment of Cavell’s philosophical work on film, exposing the naïve belief that takes Cavell to be naïve for not engaging forcefully enough in “ideology critique”; not only does Thompson champion Cavell’s genre of remarriage comedies in rebuttal, but he ably adds another film to the mix. Lastly, a welcome and spirited addendum concludes the issue in dialogic exchange. Two recently published Cavellian authors, Rex Butler and Catherine Wheatley, discuss how Cavell might be better integrated into a wider, more contentious, and certainly more mooded, world of gender and identity politics. ","PeriodicalId":342666,"journal":{"name":"Conversations: The Journal of Cavellian Studies","volume":"220 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-12-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"115527745","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Where Are Our Words? 我们的语言在哪里?
Pub Date : 2020-12-28 DOI: 10.18192/cjcs.vi8.5791
C. Djordjevic
This essay aims to offer a response to Cavell and his invitation for just such responses, as I read him. It offers a reading of later Wittgenstein based on a different mythology than Cavell’s modernist mythological one. Specifically, I aim to provide a myth that sees words in their metaphysical uses not as in exile, as a cast out of the garden of the everyday by the machinations of serpentine philosophers. Instead, I offer a myth that sees the metaphysical use as a holiday for our words, a form of unrestrained playfulness that is a facet of how we learn our ways about with them. In turn, this optimistic myth casts a philosopher not as an individual engaged in a tragically heroic, but ultimately futile, seeking of the “kingdom of the everyday” but as a person who has come to understand the axis of our real needs. I shall unfold such a myth later and hope to show that it gives us a means to dance. Pursuant to this, my mythology casts metaphysics not as an inherent flaw, a manifestation of our inability to live with our finitude, but as a playful response to it.
这篇文章的目的是回应卡维尔,以及他对这些回应的邀请,正如我所读到的。它提供了一种对后期维特根斯坦的解读,基于一种不同于卡维尔的现代主义神话。具体来说,我的目标是提供一种神话,在形而上学的用途中看到文字,而不是被流放,被蛇形哲学家的诡计从日常生活的花园中抛弃。相反,我提供了一个神话,将形而上学的使用视为我们语言的假期,一种无拘无束的玩耍形式,是我们如何学习使用语言的一个方面。反过来,这种乐观的神话把哲学家塑造成一个已经理解了我们真正需要的轴心的人,而不是一个从事悲剧英雄主义的人,但最终是徒劳的,寻求“日常王国”。我稍后将展开这样一个神话,并希望向大家展示它给我们提供了一种跳舞的方式。据此,我的神话不是把形而上学视为一种固有的缺陷,一种我们无法与有限共存的表现,而是对它的一种俏皮的回应。
{"title":"Where Are Our Words?","authors":"C. Djordjevic","doi":"10.18192/cjcs.vi8.5791","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.18192/cjcs.vi8.5791","url":null,"abstract":"This essay aims to offer a response to Cavell and his invitation for just such responses, as I read him. It offers a reading of later Wittgenstein based on a different mythology than Cavell’s modernist mythological one. Specifically, I aim to provide a myth that sees words in their metaphysical uses not as in exile, as a cast out of the garden of the everyday by the machinations of serpentine philosophers. Instead, I offer a myth that sees the metaphysical use as a holiday for our words, a form of unrestrained playfulness that is a facet of how we learn our ways about with them. In turn, this optimistic myth casts a philosopher not as an individual engaged in a tragically heroic, but ultimately futile, seeking of the “kingdom of the everyday” but as a person who has come to understand the axis of our real needs. I shall unfold such a myth later and hope to show that it gives us a means to dance. Pursuant to this, my mythology casts metaphysics not as an inherent flaw, a manifestation of our inability to live with our finitude, but as a playful response to it.","PeriodicalId":342666,"journal":{"name":"Conversations: The Journal of Cavellian Studies","volume":"55 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2020-12-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"128913117","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
期刊
Conversations: The Journal of Cavellian Studies
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1