首页 > 最新文献

Politics and Ethics Review最新文献

英文 中文
Ecological Democracy: Statist or Transnational? 生态民主:国家主义还是跨国主义?
Pub Date : 2006-10-01 DOI: 10.1177/1743453X0600200204
C. Gould
Robyn Eckersley’s book The Green State approaches political ecology from a helpfully critical perspective and presents some interesting arguments in favour of an ecologically aware yet still state-centered approach to dealing with global environmental problems. The brief analysis and critique that I undertake here will provide some opportunity to determine whether in fact political ecology can remain focused on the nation-state, however ‘green’, or whether we need a more fully transnational, or even global, approach to dealing with the weighty environmental issues that confront us. By way of appreciation, we can note Eckersley’s use of critical social theory, particularly Habermassian discourse theory, and conceptions of deliberative democracy to address political ecological issues. She brings a critical approach to bear on international relations theory as well, which she interprets in a social constructivist perspective. In dialectical fashion, her work (like that of several other theorists, including my own) seeks to mediate between liberal democratic and communitarian approaches, and she explores how this mediated position can be used to address ecological issues. As in my contemporaneous work Globalizing Democracy and Human Rights (2004), Eckersley attempts to give due weight to considerations of membership as well as to ‘being affected’ by decisions and policies in order to resolve the question of who gets to participate in which decisions in an increasingly global context. Further, although Eckersley’s concerns are primarily with ecological democracy, she briefly recognizes the need for economic democracy as well. She also adopts a social ontology similar to the one that I introduced in Marx’s Social Ontology (1978), which conceptualizes individuals as fundamentally socially related (or mutually constituting, as what I call ‘individuals-in relations’) and understands these individuals as internally rather than externally related to each other. Eckersley
罗宾·埃克斯利(Robyn Eckersley)的《绿色国家》(The Green State)一书从一种有益的批判性视角来探讨政治生态学,并提出了一些有趣的论点,支持一种具有生态意识但仍以国家为中心的方法来处理全球环境问题。我在这里进行的简短分析和批评将提供一些机会,以确定政治生态学实际上是否可以继续关注民族国家,无论“绿色”如何,或者我们是否需要一种更全面的跨国,甚至全球的方法来处理我们面临的沉重的环境问题。通过欣赏,我们可以注意到埃克斯利使用批判社会理论,特别是哈伯马西的话语理论,以及协商民主的概念来解决政治生态问题。她对国际关系理论也提出了一种批判的方法,她从社会建构主义的角度对其进行了解释。以辩证的方式,她的工作(像其他一些理论家,包括我自己的)寻求在自由民主和社区主义方法之间进行调解,她探索了如何利用这种调解立场来解决生态问题。在我同时期的著作《民主与人权全球化》(2004)中,埃克斯利试图对成员的考虑以及受决策和政策的“影响”给予应有的重视,以便在日益全球化的背景下解决谁可以参与哪些决策的问题。此外,尽管埃克斯利主要关注生态民主,但她也简要地认识到经济民主的必要性。她还采用了一种类似于我在马克思的《社会本体论》(1978)中介绍的社会本体论,将个人概念化为基本的社会关联(或相互构成,正如我所说的“关系中的个人”),并将这些个人理解为内部而不是外部相互关联。利
{"title":"Ecological Democracy: Statist or Transnational?","authors":"C. Gould","doi":"10.1177/1743453X0600200204","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1177/1743453X0600200204","url":null,"abstract":"Robyn Eckersley’s book The Green State approaches political ecology from a helpfully critical perspective and presents some interesting arguments in favour of an ecologically aware yet still state-centered approach to dealing with global environmental problems. The brief analysis and critique that I undertake here will provide some opportunity to determine whether in fact political ecology can remain focused on the nation-state, however ‘green’, or whether we need a more fully transnational, or even global, approach to dealing with the weighty environmental issues that confront us. By way of appreciation, we can note Eckersley’s use of critical social theory, particularly Habermassian discourse theory, and conceptions of deliberative democracy to address political ecological issues. She brings a critical approach to bear on international relations theory as well, which she interprets in a social constructivist perspective. In dialectical fashion, her work (like that of several other theorists, including my own) seeks to mediate between liberal democratic and communitarian approaches, and she explores how this mediated position can be used to address ecological issues. As in my contemporaneous work Globalizing Democracy and Human Rights (2004), Eckersley attempts to give due weight to considerations of membership as well as to ‘being affected’ by decisions and policies in order to resolve the question of who gets to participate in which decisions in an increasingly global context. Further, although Eckersley’s concerns are primarily with ecological democracy, she briefly recognizes the need for economic democracy as well. She also adopts a social ontology similar to the one that I introduced in Marx’s Social Ontology (1978), which conceptualizes individuals as fundamentally socially related (or mutually constituting, as what I call ‘individuals-in relations’) and understands these individuals as internally rather than externally related to each other. Eckersley","PeriodicalId":381236,"journal":{"name":"Politics and Ethics Review","volume":"16 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2006-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"132457204","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Greening the State 绿化国家
Pub Date : 2006-10-01 DOI: 10.1177/1743453X0600200203
J. Meadowcroft
Robyn Eckersley’s The Green State makes a notable contribution to green political theory as well as to more general debates about the evolution of the modern state, the future of democratic governance, and changing patterns of international interaction. The book’s argument is complex and multilayered, offering a normative vision of a ‘green state’ that has moved beyond existing democratic practices to embody the values of ‘ecological democracy’. Such a ‘transnational green democratic state’ is seen as constituting a critical link in a system of global ecological governance. The first part of Eckersley’s work explores three challenges to the project of greening the state. First, there is the ‘anarchic character’ of the existing state system, where insecurity and competition for resources drive states to engage in environmentally destructive behaviour. Second, there is ‘capitalist accumulation’ which leads states to endorse environmentally perverse growth-oriented policies. And third, there are the ‘democratic deficits’ of the liberal democratic state, particularly the ascendance of instrumental rationality and those liberal ‘dogmas’ that impede the protection of environmental goods. In each case Eckersley argues that it is possible to overcome these difficulties, and to transform existing realities. The normative theory of the green state is presented in more detail in the second half of the book, with an examination of the nature of ‘ecological democracy’, the role of civil society and the green public sphere, the evolution of transnational democracy, and the greening of sovereignty. Although the argument draws on many theoretical literatures – including work from international relations, liberal and neo-Marxist political theory, and environmental politics – the writings of Habermas play a particularly pivotal role. Central to Eckersley’s perspective is what she describes as the ‘ambit claim’ of ecological democracy – that all those affected by decisions about environmental risk (including people outside the territory over which the state holds
Robyn Eckersley的《绿色国家》对绿色政治理论做出了显著的贡献,也对现代国家的演变、民主治理的未来以及不断变化的国际互动模式进行了更广泛的讨论。这本书的论点是复杂和多层次的,提供了一个规范的“绿色国家”的愿景,超越了现有的民主实践,体现了“生态民主”的价值观。这种“跨国绿色民主国家”被视为构成全球生态治理体系的关键环节。埃克斯利作品的第一部分探讨了绿化国家项目面临的三个挑战。首先,现有国家体系具有“无政府性质”,不安全感和对资源的竞争驱使国家从事破坏环境的行为。其次,“资本主义积累”导致国家支持不利于环境的增长导向政策。第三,自由民主国家的“民主赤字”,特别是工具理性的优势和那些阻碍保护环境产品的自由主义“教条”。埃克斯利认为,在每一种情况下,都有可能克服这些困难,改变现有的现实。绿色国家的规范理论在书的后半部分更详细地介绍,并考察了“生态民主”的本质、公民社会和绿色公共领域的作用、跨国民主的演变以及主权的绿化。尽管这一论点借鉴了许多理论文献——包括来自国际关系、自由主义和新马克思主义政治理论以及环境政治的著作——但哈贝马斯的著作发挥了特别关键的作用。埃克斯利观点的核心是她所描述的生态民主的“边界主张”——所有受环境风险决策影响的人(包括国家管辖范围以外的人)
{"title":"Greening the State","authors":"J. Meadowcroft","doi":"10.1177/1743453X0600200203","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1177/1743453X0600200203","url":null,"abstract":"Robyn Eckersley’s The Green State makes a notable contribution to green political theory as well as to more general debates about the evolution of the modern state, the future of democratic governance, and changing patterns of international interaction. The book’s argument is complex and multilayered, offering a normative vision of a ‘green state’ that has moved beyond existing democratic practices to embody the values of ‘ecological democracy’. Such a ‘transnational green democratic state’ is seen as constituting a critical link in a system of global ecological governance. The first part of Eckersley’s work explores three challenges to the project of greening the state. First, there is the ‘anarchic character’ of the existing state system, where insecurity and competition for resources drive states to engage in environmentally destructive behaviour. Second, there is ‘capitalist accumulation’ which leads states to endorse environmentally perverse growth-oriented policies. And third, there are the ‘democratic deficits’ of the liberal democratic state, particularly the ascendance of instrumental rationality and those liberal ‘dogmas’ that impede the protection of environmental goods. In each case Eckersley argues that it is possible to overcome these difficulties, and to transform existing realities. The normative theory of the green state is presented in more detail in the second half of the book, with an examination of the nature of ‘ecological democracy’, the role of civil society and the green public sphere, the evolution of transnational democracy, and the greening of sovereignty. Although the argument draws on many theoretical literatures – including work from international relations, liberal and neo-Marxist political theory, and environmental politics – the writings of Habermas play a particularly pivotal role. Central to Eckersley’s perspective is what she describes as the ‘ambit claim’ of ecological democracy – that all those affected by decisions about environmental risk (including people outside the territory over which the state holds","PeriodicalId":381236,"journal":{"name":"Politics and Ethics Review","volume":"24 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2006-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"122032024","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 20
Max Weber on Ethics and Politics 马克思·韦伯论伦理与政治
Pub Date : 2006-04-01 DOI: 10.1177/1743453X0600200103
Elizabeth Frazer
The relationship between politics and ethics is problematic. A good deal of modern political philosophy, especially but not only the Rawlsian programme, can be read as concentrating on setting ethical limits to politics. The philosophical justification of values such as equality and liberty, or the validation of concepts such as right or law, are intended to constrain political power. Typically, recent liberal philosophy seeks to prescribe the content of constitutional or basic law, as Rawls does; or to prescribe the procedures that should generate legislation, as Habermas does. An alternative interpretation can be put on this relationship – that politics seeks to realize ethical values and principles that have been justified philosophically. Here the emphasis is on the substance of policy. And some political philosophy duly focuses on what is politically possible, attending to the gap between that and what is philosophically justified. That is, some political theory we might say concentrates on the political limits to ethics. All these variations on the theme share a presumption that ‘politics’ and ‘ethics’ are independent of one another, two distinct activities or modes of reasoning. Each of them can be engaged in quite without reference to the other. Equally, an actor engaged in one might be thinking about the other. Nevertheless they stand, as we might say, in an external relationship to each other. Thinking which separates ethics and politics in this way also frequently (although it need not) contrasts the two respectively as prescriptive and descriptive, or normative and positive, or as concerned with matters of value as opposed to matters of fact. Politics, according to such views, is a series of processes, practices and arrangements concerning the power to govern – getting it, keeping it, squandering it, using it, opposing it, and so on; while ethics is a series of norms or prescriptions – ‘oughts’ – governing the generality of our conduct regarding other persons and the world. ‘Is’ and ‘ought’ are logically quite distinct from each other, although
政治和伦理之间的关系是有问题的。大量的现代政治哲学,尤其是但不仅仅是罗尔斯的纲领,可以被解读为专注于为政治设定伦理限制。对平等和自由等价值的哲学论证,或对权利或法律等概念的验证,都是为了约束政治权力。典型地,近代自由主义哲学试图规定宪法或基本法的内容,正如罗尔斯所做的那样;或者像哈贝马斯那样,规定应该产生立法的程序。对这种关系可以有另一种解释——政治寻求实现在哲学上被证明是合理的伦理价值和原则。这里强调的是政策的实质。一些政治哲学适当地关注什么是政治上可能的,注意到政治上可能的和哲学上合理的之间的差距。也就是说,我们可以说,一些政治理论集中于伦理的政治限制。所有这些主题的变化都有一个共同的假设,即“政治”和“伦理”是相互独立的,是两种不同的活动或推理模式。它们中的每一个都可以完全不依赖于另一个。同样,从事其中一种活动的演员可能会想到另一种活动。然而,我们可以说,它们彼此处于一种外在的关系中。以这种方式将伦理和政治分开的思维,也经常(虽然它不需要)将两者分别对比为规定性和描述性,或规范性和肯定性,或关注价值问题而不是事实问题。根据这种观点,政治是一系列关于治理权力的过程、实践和安排——获得权力、保持权力、浪费权力、使用权力、反对权力等等;而伦理则是一系列规范或处方——“应该”——支配着我们对待他人和世界的行为的普遍性。“是”和“应该”在逻辑上是截然不同的
{"title":"Max Weber on Ethics and Politics","authors":"Elizabeth Frazer","doi":"10.1177/1743453X0600200103","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1177/1743453X0600200103","url":null,"abstract":"The relationship between politics and ethics is problematic. A good deal of modern political philosophy, especially but not only the Rawlsian programme, can be read as concentrating on setting ethical limits to politics. The philosophical justification of values such as equality and liberty, or the validation of concepts such as right or law, are intended to constrain political power. Typically, recent liberal philosophy seeks to prescribe the content of constitutional or basic law, as Rawls does; or to prescribe the procedures that should generate legislation, as Habermas does. An alternative interpretation can be put on this relationship – that politics seeks to realize ethical values and principles that have been justified philosophically. Here the emphasis is on the substance of policy. And some political philosophy duly focuses on what is politically possible, attending to the gap between that and what is philosophically justified. That is, some political theory we might say concentrates on the political limits to ethics. All these variations on the theme share a presumption that ‘politics’ and ‘ethics’ are independent of one another, two distinct activities or modes of reasoning. Each of them can be engaged in quite without reference to the other. Equally, an actor engaged in one might be thinking about the other. Nevertheless they stand, as we might say, in an external relationship to each other. Thinking which separates ethics and politics in this way also frequently (although it need not) contrasts the two respectively as prescriptive and descriptive, or normative and positive, or as concerned with matters of value as opposed to matters of fact. Politics, according to such views, is a series of processes, practices and arrangements concerning the power to govern – getting it, keeping it, squandering it, using it, opposing it, and so on; while ethics is a series of norms or prescriptions – ‘oughts’ – governing the generality of our conduct regarding other persons and the world. ‘Is’ and ‘ought’ are logically quite distinct from each other, although","PeriodicalId":381236,"journal":{"name":"Politics and Ethics Review","volume":"93 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2006-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"123070709","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 8
Book Review: Political Theory of Global Justice: A Cosmopolitan Case for the World State 书评:《全球正义的政治理论:世界国家的世界性案例》
Pub Date : 2006-04-01 DOI: 10.1177/1743453X0600200109
Ramon Das
{"title":"Book Review: Political Theory of Global Justice: A Cosmopolitan Case for the World State","authors":"Ramon Das","doi":"10.1177/1743453X0600200109","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1177/1743453X0600200109","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":381236,"journal":{"name":"Politics and Ethics Review","volume":"11 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2006-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"129581383","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Notes on Contributors 投稿人说明
Pub Date : 2006-04-01 DOI: 10.1177/1743453x0600200101
{"title":"Notes on Contributors","authors":"","doi":"10.1177/1743453x0600200101","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1177/1743453x0600200101","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":381236,"journal":{"name":"Politics and Ethics Review","volume":"28 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2006-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"127980785","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Principlism, the Ethics of Virtue, and the Politics of Bioethics 原则主义、德性伦理与生命伦理政治
Pub Date : 2006-04-01 DOI: 10.1177/1743453X0600200106
L. Holt, B. Hilliard
Is bioethics up to the challenges facing modern medicine and twenty-first century American health care policy? Can bioethics adequately address existing and emerging dilemmas facing the global community? Until recently many observers, especially those working in the United States would have characterized such questions as misplaced, irrelevant, or even silly. After all, in its almost forty years of existence, both the philosophical underpinnings and practical applications of bioethics have enabled it to make significant strides in exploring, evaluating, and analyzing some of the most basic problems and dilemmas in medical care. Through various theoretical, methodological, and practical innovations bioethics has positively impacted the context in which individual patients and the public interact with health care professionals. This influence is reflected not only in the popularity of bioethics courses on university
生命伦理学是否能够应对现代医学和21世纪美国医疗保健政策所面临的挑战?生物伦理学能否充分解决全球社会面临的现有和新出现的困境?直到最近,许多观察家,尤其是在美国工作的观察家,还认为这些问题是放错地方的、不相干的,甚至是愚蠢的。毕竟,在其近四十年的存在中,生命伦理学的哲学基础和实际应用都使它在探索、评估和分析医疗保健中一些最基本的问题和困境方面取得了重大进展。通过各种理论、方法和实践创新,生物伦理学对个体患者和公众与卫生保健专业人员互动的环境产生了积极的影响。这种影响不仅体现在大学生物伦理学课程的普及上
{"title":"Principlism, the Ethics of Virtue, and the Politics of Bioethics","authors":"L. Holt, B. Hilliard","doi":"10.1177/1743453X0600200106","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1177/1743453X0600200106","url":null,"abstract":"Is bioethics up to the challenges facing modern medicine and twenty-first century American health care policy? Can bioethics adequately address existing and emerging dilemmas facing the global community? Until recently many observers, especially those working in the United States would have characterized such questions as misplaced, irrelevant, or even silly. After all, in its almost forty years of existence, both the philosophical underpinnings and practical applications of bioethics have enabled it to make significant strides in exploring, evaluating, and analyzing some of the most basic problems and dilemmas in medical care. Through various theoretical, methodological, and practical innovations bioethics has positively impacted the context in which individual patients and the public interact with health care professionals. This influence is reflected not only in the popularity of bioethics courses on university","PeriodicalId":381236,"journal":{"name":"Politics and Ethics Review","volume":"23 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2006-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"126282665","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Legitimacy in International Society Ian Clark ,Legitimacy in International Society(Oxford: University Press, 2005). 伊恩·克拉克,《国际社会的合法性》(牛津:大学出版社,2005)。
Pub Date : 2006-04-01 DOI: 10.3366/PER.2006.2.1.93
A. Lang
{"title":"Legitimacy in International Society Ian Clark ,Legitimacy in International Society(Oxford: University Press, 2005).","authors":"A. Lang","doi":"10.3366/PER.2006.2.1.93","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3366/PER.2006.2.1.93","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":381236,"journal":{"name":"Politics and Ethics Review","volume":"38 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2006-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"121116620","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 10
Political Theory of Global Justice: A Cosmopolitan Case for the World State Luis Cabrera ,Political Theory of Global Justice: A Cosmopolitan Case for the World State(London and New York: Routledge, 2004). 路易斯·卡布雷拉,《全球正义政治理论:世界国家的世界主义案例》(伦敦和纽约:劳特利奇出版社,2004)。
Pub Date : 2006-04-01 DOI: 10.3366/PER.2006.2.1.97
Ramon Das
{"title":"Political Theory of Global Justice: A Cosmopolitan Case for the World State Luis Cabrera ,Political Theory of Global Justice: A Cosmopolitan Case for the World State(London and New York: Routledge, 2004).","authors":"Ramon Das","doi":"10.3366/PER.2006.2.1.97","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.3366/PER.2006.2.1.97","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":381236,"journal":{"name":"Politics and Ethics Review","volume":"58 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2006-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"129806738","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 13
Normative War-Fighting and the New World Order 规范战争与世界新秩序
Pub Date : 2006-04-01 DOI: 10.1177/1743453X0600200104
B. Howe
Francis Fukuyama (1989, 1992) declaring the ‘end of history’ in 1989, and President George Bush (cited by Ross, 2002: 247), in a State of the Union Address in January of 1991, declaring a “New World Order ... to achieve the universal aspirations of mankind – peace and security, freedom and the rule of law” caused a great stir and helped revitalize debate in this area, but they were essentially referring to liberal tenets that were decades, or even centuries old. The basic liberal argument is that at some point the world radically changed, forcing a re-evaluation of the nature of international interaction. In the brave new liberal world, the logic of cooperation takes over from the logic of competition and survival of the fittest. The promotion of shared values and interests supersedes the pursuit of selfish national interest, morality is placed at the centre stage of statecraft, and the basic human concern for the well being of others makes progress possible. Liberal beliefs do not make war unthinkable, but do challenge traditional assumptions of when it is justifiable to wage war. There is no more dramatic manifestation of liberal leadership than so-called ‘normative war-fighting’ or militarized humanitarian intervention. J. L. Holzgrefe (Holzgrefe and Keohane, 2003: 18) defines humanitarian intervention as ‘the threat or use of force across state borders by a state (or group of states) aimed at preventing or ending widespread and grave violations of the fundamental human rights of individuals other than its own citizens, without the permission of the state within whose territory is applied’. The concept of normative war-fighting or militarized humanitarian intervention is herein used in the same way, but with an additional and deliberate emphasis on the role of the military and the decision-makers commanding their deployment. This paper assesses the degree to which the triumph of Western liberal states in the Cold War has led to a new kind of international system,
弗朗西斯·福山(1989,1992)在1989年宣布“历史的终结”,乔治·布什总统(罗斯引用,2002:247)在1991年1月的国情咨文中宣布“世界新秩序……“为了实现人类的普遍愿望- -和平与安全、自由和法治”引起了巨大的轰动,并帮助恢复了这一领域的辩论,但它们实质上指的是几十年甚至几百年前的自由主义原则。自由主义的基本论点是,在某个时刻,世界发生了根本性的变化,迫使人们重新评估国际互动的本质。在这个美丽的自由新世界里,合作的逻辑取代了竞争和适者生存的逻辑。促进共同的价值观和利益取代了对自私的国家利益的追求,道德被置于治国方略的中心,人类对他人福祉的基本关切使进步成为可能。自由主义信仰并没有让战争变得不可想象,但它确实挑战了关于什么时候发动战争是正当的传统假设。没有什么比所谓的“规范的战争”或军事化的人道主义干预更能体现自由主义的领导力了。J. L. Holzgrefe (Holzgrefe and Keohane, 2003: 18)将人道主义干预定义为“一个国家(或国家集团)在未经其领土范围内的国家许可的情况下,跨越国界威胁或使用武力,旨在防止或结束对其本国公民以外的个人的普遍和严重侵犯基本人权的行为”。规范的战争或军事化的人道主义干预的概念在这里也以同样的方式使用,但对军队和指挥其部署的决策者的作用作了额外和有意的强调。本文评估了西方自由主义国家在冷战中的胜利在多大程度上导致了一种新的国际体系,
{"title":"Normative War-Fighting and the New World Order","authors":"B. Howe","doi":"10.1177/1743453X0600200104","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1177/1743453X0600200104","url":null,"abstract":"Francis Fukuyama (1989, 1992) declaring the ‘end of history’ in 1989, and President George Bush (cited by Ross, 2002: 247), in a State of the Union Address in January of 1991, declaring a “New World Order ... to achieve the universal aspirations of mankind – peace and security, freedom and the rule of law” caused a great stir and helped revitalize debate in this area, but they were essentially referring to liberal tenets that were decades, or even centuries old. The basic liberal argument is that at some point the world radically changed, forcing a re-evaluation of the nature of international interaction. In the brave new liberal world, the logic of cooperation takes over from the logic of competition and survival of the fittest. The promotion of shared values and interests supersedes the pursuit of selfish national interest, morality is placed at the centre stage of statecraft, and the basic human concern for the well being of others makes progress possible. Liberal beliefs do not make war unthinkable, but do challenge traditional assumptions of when it is justifiable to wage war. There is no more dramatic manifestation of liberal leadership than so-called ‘normative war-fighting’ or militarized humanitarian intervention. J. L. Holzgrefe (Holzgrefe and Keohane, 2003: 18) defines humanitarian intervention as ‘the threat or use of force across state borders by a state (or group of states) aimed at preventing or ending widespread and grave violations of the fundamental human rights of individuals other than its own citizens, without the permission of the state within whose territory is applied’. The concept of normative war-fighting or militarized humanitarian intervention is herein used in the same way, but with an additional and deliberate emphasis on the role of the military and the decision-makers commanding their deployment. This paper assesses the degree to which the triumph of Western liberal states in the Cold War has led to a new kind of international system,","PeriodicalId":381236,"journal":{"name":"Politics and Ethics Review","volume":"185 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2006-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"115308766","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Compatriot Preference: Is There a Case? 同胞偏好:有这种情况吗?
Pub Date : 2006-04-01 DOI: 10.1177/1743453X0600200102
R. Vernon
Although broader ethnic or religious loyalties sometimes supervene, people all over the world attach special importance to the fate of their compatriots. How to measure the preferential factor is an intriguing question: perhaps we could measure the front-page space devoted to domestic and international matters respectively, or the extent of a foreign as opposed to a domestic disaster needed to cross the threshold of attention, or compare foreign-aid budgets with domestic welfare and social service expenditures. Some measures might yield a very high factor: perhaps compatriots are given a thousand times more weight, perhaps more, in some respects. But of course, even if compatriots were (implicitly) judged to be worth only (!) twice as much as others, we should still want to know why. Sometimes psychological reasons are given: it is argued, for example, that Rousseau was right to claim that human attachments weaken as they extend, that they must stop somewhere if they are to retain any motivating force and remain reliable (Orwin, 1996). We might, however, still want to know if we are justified in doing what we feel inclined to do. Moreover, Rousseau’s spatial model doesn’t fit the facts at all well. Quite often people give more weight to relatively large attachments than to relatively small ones; they send their children off to war, for example – a reminder of the important fact that compatriot preference needs to be justified in relation to smaller local attachments, as well as to whatever it is that global justice demands (Jones, 1999: 131-3; Moore, 2001: 47-50). That consideration has particular weight in light of views that partiality at the sub-national level is more readily justified than compatriot preference (Shue, 1988; Singer, 2004: 15-16). The enquiry attempted here is broader than some and narrower than others. It is broader than enquiries into the mutual obligations that arise within a society of a kind that we are assumed to admire: a liberal, liberal-democratic, republican, or egalitarian kind. Two refined recent treatments of compatriot preference have advanced excellent reasons for giving special weight to the mutual obligations
虽然有时会出现更广泛的种族或宗教忠诚,但世界各地的人们都特别重视同胞的命运。如何衡量优先因素是一个有趣的问题:也许我们可以分别衡量国内和国际事务的头版篇幅,或者衡量需要跨越关注门槛的外国灾难与国内灾难的程度,或者将外国援助预算与国内福利和社会服务支出进行比较。有些措施可能会产生一个非常高的因素:也许同胞被赋予一千倍的权重,也许更多,在某些方面。当然,即使我们的同胞(含蓄地)被认为价值仅是其他人的两倍,我们仍然应该想知道原因。有时会给出心理上的原因:例如,有人认为卢梭的观点是正确的,即人类的依恋随着扩展而减弱,如果要保留任何动力并保持可靠,它们必须在某个地方停止(Orwin, 1996)。然而,我们可能仍然想知道我们是否有理由去做我们想做的事情。此外,卢梭的空间模型与事实完全不符。人们往往更重视相对较大的依恋而不是相对较小的依恋;例如,他们把自己的孩子送去打仗——这提醒我们一个重要的事实,即同胞偏好需要在相对较小的地方依恋以及全球正义要求的任何方面得到证明(Jones, 1999: 131-3;摩尔,2001:47-50)。考虑到以下观点,即地方一级的偏袒比同胞偏好更容易被证明是合理的,这种考虑尤其重要(Shue, 1988;歌手,2004:15-16)。这里试图进行的调查比一些更广泛,比另一些更狭隘。它比我们所崇拜的那种社会(自由主义、自由民主主义、共和主义或平等主义)中产生的相互义务的探究更为广泛。最近两种对同胞偏好的精细化处理,为特别重视相互义务提供了极好的理由
{"title":"Compatriot Preference: Is There a Case?","authors":"R. Vernon","doi":"10.1177/1743453X0600200102","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1177/1743453X0600200102","url":null,"abstract":"Although broader ethnic or religious loyalties sometimes supervene, people all over the world attach special importance to the fate of their compatriots. How to measure the preferential factor is an intriguing question: perhaps we could measure the front-page space devoted to domestic and international matters respectively, or the extent of a foreign as opposed to a domestic disaster needed to cross the threshold of attention, or compare foreign-aid budgets with domestic welfare and social service expenditures. Some measures might yield a very high factor: perhaps compatriots are given a thousand times more weight, perhaps more, in some respects. But of course, even if compatriots were (implicitly) judged to be worth only (!) twice as much as others, we should still want to know why. Sometimes psychological reasons are given: it is argued, for example, that Rousseau was right to claim that human attachments weaken as they extend, that they must stop somewhere if they are to retain any motivating force and remain reliable (Orwin, 1996). We might, however, still want to know if we are justified in doing what we feel inclined to do. Moreover, Rousseau’s spatial model doesn’t fit the facts at all well. Quite often people give more weight to relatively large attachments than to relatively small ones; they send their children off to war, for example – a reminder of the important fact that compatriot preference needs to be justified in relation to smaller local attachments, as well as to whatever it is that global justice demands (Jones, 1999: 131-3; Moore, 2001: 47-50). That consideration has particular weight in light of views that partiality at the sub-national level is more readily justified than compatriot preference (Shue, 1988; Singer, 2004: 15-16). The enquiry attempted here is broader than some and narrower than others. It is broader than enquiries into the mutual obligations that arise within a society of a kind that we are assumed to admire: a liberal, liberal-democratic, republican, or egalitarian kind. Two refined recent treatments of compatriot preference have advanced excellent reasons for giving special weight to the mutual obligations","PeriodicalId":381236,"journal":{"name":"Politics and Ethics Review","volume":"35 2 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2006-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"128510742","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
期刊
Politics and Ethics Review
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1