首页 > 最新文献

Principia最新文献

英文 中文
On the metaphysics of (epistemological) logical anti-exceptionalism 论(认识论)逻辑反例外论的形而上学
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-07-08 DOI: 10.5007/1808-1711.2021.E80109
E. Erickson
A recent logical anti-exceptionalist trend proposes that logical theories are revisable in the same manner as scientific theories, either on grounds of the method of theory selection or on what counts as evidence for this revision. Given this approximation of logic and science, the present essay analyzes the commitments of both these varieties and argues that, as it currently stands, this kind of anti-exceptionalism is committed to scientific realism, that is, to realism about some unobservable entities evoked in logical theories. The essay argues that anti-exceptionalism cannot be separated into metaphysical and epistemological varieties, and proposed rather to label anti-exceptionalists views either broadly in terms of theory revision, or narrowly in terms of logic’s affinity with science.
最近的一种逻辑反例外主义趋势提出,逻辑理论可以以与科学理论相同的方式进行修正,无论是基于理论选择的方法,还是基于这种修正的证据。鉴于逻辑和科学的这种近似,本文分析了这两种变体的承诺,并认为,就目前而言,这种反例外主义致力于科学现实主义,即关于逻辑理论中唤起的一些不可观察实体的现实主义。本文认为,反例外论不能分为形而上学和认识论两种,并建议要么从理论修正的角度对反例外论观点进行宽泛的标记,要么从逻辑与科学的亲和力的角度对其进行狭义的标记。
{"title":"On the metaphysics of (epistemological) logical anti-exceptionalism","authors":"E. Erickson","doi":"10.5007/1808-1711.2021.E80109","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5007/1808-1711.2021.E80109","url":null,"abstract":"A recent logical anti-exceptionalist trend proposes that logical theories are revisable in the same manner as scientific theories, either on grounds of the method of theory selection or on what counts as evidence for this revision. Given this approximation of logic and science, the present essay analyzes the commitments of both these varieties and argues that, as it currently stands, this kind of anti-exceptionalism is committed to scientific realism, that is, to realism about some unobservable entities evoked in logical theories. The essay argues that anti-exceptionalism cannot be separated into metaphysical and epistemological varieties, and proposed rather to label anti-exceptionalists views either broadly in terms of theory revision, or narrowly in terms of logic’s affinity with science.","PeriodicalId":38561,"journal":{"name":"Principia","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-07-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46594084","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Kepler y el teorema fundamental de la óptica 开普勒和光学基本定理
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-07-08 DOI: 10.5007/1808-1711.2021.E71458
C. Cardona
En el artículo se ofrece un análisis de los argumentos que condujeron a Kepler a la defensa y demostración del teorema fundamental de la óptica. Según este teorema, un haz homocéntrico de luz que se ve obligado a atravesar una esfera transparente, siempre que la amplitud del haz no sea mayor, se concentra de nuevo en un punto al otro lado de la esfera. La demostración de Kepler se compara con la ofrecida por Malebranche años más tarde. Este teorema fue determinante para la consolidación de la óptica moderna.
本文分析了导致开普勒捍卫和证明光学基本定理的论点。根据这个定理,只要光束的振幅不较大,被迫穿过透明球体的同心光束就会再次集中在球体另一侧的一个点上。开普勒的演示与多年后Malebranche提供的演示进行了比较。这个定理是巩固现代光学的决定性因素。
{"title":"Kepler y el teorema fundamental de la óptica","authors":"C. Cardona","doi":"10.5007/1808-1711.2021.E71458","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5007/1808-1711.2021.E71458","url":null,"abstract":"En el artículo se ofrece un análisis de los argumentos que condujeron a Kepler a la defensa y demostración del teorema fundamental de la óptica. Según este teorema, un haz homocéntrico de luz que se ve obligado a atravesar una esfera transparente, siempre que la amplitud del haz no sea mayor, se concentra de nuevo en un punto al otro lado de la esfera. La demostración de Kepler se compara con la ofrecida por Malebranche años más tarde. Este teorema fue determinante para la consolidación de la óptica moderna.","PeriodicalId":38561,"journal":{"name":"Principia","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-07-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49151182","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Logical theory revision through data underdetermination: an anti-exceptionalist exercise 通过数据不确定性进行逻辑理论修正:一种反例外主义的实践
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-07-08 DOI: 10.5007/1808-1711.2021.E80110
Sanderson Molick
The anti-exceptionalist debate brought into play the problem of what are the relevant data for logical theories and how such data affects the validities accepted by a logical theory. In the present paper, I depart from Laudan's reticulated model of science to analyze one aspect of this problem, namely of the role of logical data within the process of revision of logical theories. For this, I argue that the ubiquitous nature of logical data is responsible for the proliferation of several distinct methodologies for logical theories. The resulting picture is coherent with the Laudanean view that agreement and disagreement between scientific theories take place at different levels. From this perspective, one is able to articulate other kinds of divergence that considers not only the inferential aspects of a given logical theory, but also the epistemic aims and the methodological choices that drive its development.
反例外论的争论引起了逻辑理论的相关数据是什么以及这些数据如何影响逻辑理论所接受的有效性的问题。在本文中,我从罗丹的科学网状模型出发,分析了这个问题的一个方面,即逻辑数据在逻辑理论修正过程中的作用。为此,我认为逻辑数据的普遍性是导致逻辑理论的几种不同方法激增的原因。由此产生的图像与Laudanean的观点一致,即科学理论之间的一致和分歧发生在不同的层面。从这个角度来看,人们能够阐明其他类型的分歧,这些分歧不仅考虑了给定逻辑理论的推理方面,还考虑了驱动其发展的认识目标和方法选择。
{"title":"Logical theory revision through data underdetermination: an anti-exceptionalist exercise","authors":"Sanderson Molick","doi":"10.5007/1808-1711.2021.E80110","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5007/1808-1711.2021.E80110","url":null,"abstract":"The anti-exceptionalist debate brought into play the problem of what are the relevant data for logical theories and how such data affects the validities accepted by a logical theory. In the present paper, I depart from Laudan's reticulated model of science to analyze one aspect of this problem, namely of the role of logical data within the process of revision of logical theories. For this, I argue that the ubiquitous nature of logical data is responsible for the proliferation of several distinct methodologies for logical theories. The resulting picture is coherent with the Laudanean view that agreement and disagreement between scientific theories take place at different levels. From this perspective, one is able to articulate other kinds of divergence that considers not only the inferential aspects of a given logical theory, but also the epistemic aims and the methodological choices that drive its development.","PeriodicalId":38561,"journal":{"name":"Principia","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-07-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49322853","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Individuals, Communities, and Groups in Thomas Kuhn’s Model of Scientific Development 托马斯·库恩科学发展模型中的个人、社区和群体
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-07-08 DOI: 10.5007/1808-1711.2021.E71002
Paulo Pirozelli
In The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Thomas Kuhn resorts to concepts from several disciplines in order to describe the general patterns of scientific development. This blend of disciplines can be explained in part by Kuhn's intellectual path, from physics to history and then to philosophy of science; but it also points to a deeper methodological problem, which is the question of what is the real unity of analysis in his model of science. The primary intention of this article is, thus, to give a solution to this difficulty. The answer, I believe, rests on identifying three fundamental units present in Kuhn's theory of scientific development. They are, respectively, the individual, responsible for producing evidence, spreading information, and choosing theories; the community, a set of scientists investigating a series of phenomena; and the groups, individuals with similar behavior but with looser institutional or social ties — a usually neglected category in Kuhnian literature, but equally fundamental for the final outcome of scientific debates. After investigating these categories in detail, I propose a way of integrating them into a general model for explaining the resolution of scientific controversies. Finally, I try to resolve the apparent conflict among disciplinary vocabularies by offering an account of the function of sociological, psychological, and epistemological concepts for describing controversies, and some of the methodologies appropriate for each of these tasks.
在《科学革命的结构》中,托马斯·库恩运用了几个学科的概念来描述科学发展的一般模式。这种学科的融合可以部分解释为库恩的思想道路,从物理学到历史,再到科学哲学;但它也指向了一个更深层次的方法论问题,即在他的科学模型中,分析的真正统一性是什么。因此,这篇文章的主要目的是解决这一困难。我认为,答案在于确定库恩科学发展理论中存在的三个基本单元。他们分别是个人,负责提供证据、传播信息和选择理论;社区,一群研究一系列现象的科学家;以及群体,具有相似行为但制度或社会联系较松散的个人——这在Kuhnian文献中通常被忽视,但对科学辩论的最终结果同样重要。在详细研究了这些类别之后,我提出了一种将它们整合到一个通用模型中的方法,以解释科学争议的解决方法。最后,我试图通过描述社会学、心理学和认识论概念在描述争议方面的功能,以及适用于每项任务的一些方法,来解决学科词汇之间的明显冲突。
{"title":"Individuals, Communities, and Groups in Thomas Kuhn’s Model of Scientific Development","authors":"Paulo Pirozelli","doi":"10.5007/1808-1711.2021.E71002","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5007/1808-1711.2021.E71002","url":null,"abstract":"In The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Thomas Kuhn resorts to concepts from several disciplines in order to describe the general patterns of scientific development. This blend of disciplines can be explained in part by Kuhn's intellectual path, from physics to history and then to philosophy of science; but it also points to a deeper methodological problem, which is the question of what is the real unity of analysis in his model of science. The primary intention of this article is, thus, to give a solution to this difficulty. The answer, I believe, rests on identifying three fundamental units present in Kuhn's theory of scientific development. They are, respectively, the individual, responsible for producing evidence, spreading information, and choosing theories; the community, a set of scientists investigating a series of phenomena; and the groups, individuals with similar behavior but with looser institutional or social ties — a usually neglected category in Kuhnian literature, but equally fundamental for the final outcome of scientific debates. After investigating these categories in detail, I propose a way of integrating them into a general model for explaining the resolution of scientific controversies. Finally, I try to resolve the apparent conflict among disciplinary vocabularies by offering an account of the function of sociological, psychological, and epistemological concepts for describing controversies, and some of the methodologies appropriate for each of these tasks.","PeriodicalId":38561,"journal":{"name":"Principia","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-07-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43037723","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Actitud de La Obra de Arte 艺术作品的态度
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-07-08 DOI: 10.5007/1808-1711.2021.E71267
Malena León
En este artículo elaboramos una propuesta sobre el significado de las obras de arte que se apoya en la perspectiva de Dennett acerca de la naturaleza de la intencionalidad de los fenómenos mentales. De acuerdo a ella, la intencionalidad que estos exhiben no es original, sino derivada. Adoptar la perspectiva de la intencionalidad derivada implica que ya no será posible sostener que el significado de una obra de arte esté vinculado al acto creativo que le dio origen o que esté determinado por las intenciones que tuvo su autor al crearlas, como han sostenido las teorías intencionalistas. Ahora bien, creemos que hay un aspecto de estas que no es incompatible con la perspectiva de intencionalidad derivada. Se trata del hecho de que parte del significado de la obra de arte está dado por las interpretaciones que surgen sólo cuando se asume que la misma fue producida por un agente con el propósito de transmitir algo. Llamaremos a esta estrategia interpretativa actitud de la obra de arte y defenderemos que debe ser entendida como un subtipo de la actitud intencional. Esta estrategia interpretativa forma parte de una propuesta que intenta explicar el significado de las obras de arte como siendo parcialmente indeterminado, relativo a una historia (y no a un origen fundacional) y dependiente de la atribución interpretativa.
在这篇文章中,我们提出了一个关于艺术作品意义的建议,这是基于丹尼特关于心理现象意向性本质的观点。根据她的说法,这些表现出来的意向性不是原创的,而是派生的。采取派生意图的角度意味着它不可能维持了艺术作品的含义可能与创造性行为决定了他或他的意图而有其持续的创建,正如intencionalistas理论。然而,我们认为,其中有一个方面与派生意向性的观点并非不相容。它是关于这样一个事实,即一件艺术品的部分意义是由解释给出的,只有当它被假定是由一个代理人为了传达某物而产生时,才会出现解释。我们将这种解释策略称为艺术作品的态度,并认为它应该被理解为意图态度的子类型。这种解释策略是一种建议的一部分,该建议试图将艺术作品的意义解释为部分不确定的,与历史(而不是基础起源)相关,并依赖于解释归因。
{"title":"Actitud de La Obra de Arte","authors":"Malena León","doi":"10.5007/1808-1711.2021.E71267","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5007/1808-1711.2021.E71267","url":null,"abstract":"En este artículo elaboramos una propuesta sobre el significado de las obras de arte que se apoya en la perspectiva de Dennett acerca de la naturaleza de la intencionalidad de los fenómenos mentales. De acuerdo a ella, la intencionalidad que estos exhiben no es original, sino derivada. Adoptar la perspectiva de la intencionalidad derivada implica que ya no será posible sostener que el significado de una obra de arte esté vinculado al acto creativo que le dio origen o que esté determinado por las intenciones que tuvo su autor al crearlas, como han sostenido las teorías intencionalistas. Ahora bien, creemos que hay un aspecto de estas que no es incompatible con la perspectiva de intencionalidad derivada. Se trata del hecho de que parte del significado de la obra de arte está dado por las interpretaciones que surgen sólo cuando se asume que la misma fue producida por un agente con el propósito de transmitir algo. Llamaremos a esta estrategia interpretativa actitud de la obra de arte y defenderemos que debe ser entendida como un subtipo de la actitud intencional. Esta estrategia interpretativa forma parte de una propuesta que intenta explicar el significado de las obras de arte como siendo parcialmente indeterminado, relativo a una historia (y no a un origen fundacional) y dependiente de la atribución interpretativa.","PeriodicalId":38561,"journal":{"name":"Principia","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-07-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48848340","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Much Ado About the Many 多此一举
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-07-08 DOI: 10.5007/1808-1711.2021.E70853
Jonathan Mai
English distinguishes between singular quantifiers like "a donkey" and plural quantifiers like "some donkeys". Pluralists hold that plural quantifiers range in an unusual, irreducibly plural, way over common objects, namely individuals from first-order domains and not over set-like objects. The favoured framework of pluralism is plural first-order logic, PFO, an interpreted first-order language that is capable of expressing plural quantification. Pluralists argue for their position by claiming that the standard formal theory based on PFO is both ontologically neutral and really logic. These properties are supposed to yield many important applications concerning second-order logic and set theory that alternative theories supposedly cannot deliver. I will show that there are serious reasons for rejecting at least the claim of ontological innocence. Doubt about innocence arises on account of the fact that, when properly spelled out, the PFO-semantics for plural quantifiers is committed to set-like objects. The correctness of my worries presupposes the principle that for every plurality there is a coextensive set. Pluralists might reply that this principle leads straight to paradox. However, as I will argue, the true culprit of the paradox is the assumption that every definite condition determines a plurality.
英语区分单数量词,如“a donkey”和复数量词,如“some donkey”。复数主义者认为,复数量词以一种不寻常的、不可约复数的方式,适用于普通对象,即来自一阶域的个体,而不适用于类集合对象。多元主义的有利框架是多元一阶逻辑,即PFO,一种能够表达多元量化的一阶语言。多元主义者通过声称基于PFO的标准形式理论在本体论上是中立的,并且是真正的逻辑来论证他们的立场。这些性质被认为产生了许多关于二阶逻辑和集合论的重要应用,而替代理论被认为无法提供这些应用。我将证明,有一些严肃的理由,至少可以拒绝本体论的无罪主张。对无罪的怀疑产生于这样一个事实,即当正确地拼写时,复数量词的pfo语义被用于类集合对象。我的担忧之所以正确,是以这样一个原则为前提的:对于每一个复数,都有一个共延的集合。多元主义者可能会回答说,这个原则直接导致悖论。然而,正如我将要论证的那样,这个悖论的真正罪魁祸首是每一个确定的条件都决定了多元性的假设。
{"title":"Much Ado About the Many","authors":"Jonathan Mai","doi":"10.5007/1808-1711.2021.E70853","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5007/1808-1711.2021.E70853","url":null,"abstract":"English distinguishes between singular quantifiers like \"a donkey\" and plural quantifiers like \"some donkeys\". Pluralists hold that plural quantifiers range in an unusual, irreducibly plural, way over common objects, namely individuals from first-order domains and not over set-like objects. The favoured framework of pluralism is plural first-order logic, PFO, an interpreted first-order language that is capable of expressing plural quantification. Pluralists argue for their position by claiming that the standard formal theory based on PFO is both ontologically neutral and really logic. These properties are supposed to yield many important applications concerning second-order logic and set theory that alternative theories supposedly cannot deliver. I will show that there are serious reasons for rejecting at least the claim of ontological innocence. Doubt about innocence arises on account of the fact that, when properly spelled out, the PFO-semantics for plural quantifiers is committed to set-like objects. The correctness of my worries presupposes the principle that for every plurality there is a coextensive set. Pluralists might reply that this principle leads straight to paradox. However, as I will argue, the true culprit of the paradox is the assumption that every definite condition determines a plurality.","PeriodicalId":38561,"journal":{"name":"Principia","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-07-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43879410","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Introduction by The Guest Editor – 4th Filomena Workshop 客座编辑介绍-第四届菲洛梅娜研讨会
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-07-08 DOI: 10.5007/1808-1711.2021.E82665
Revista Principia
Introduction by The Guest Editor – 4th Filomena Workshop
客座编辑介绍-第四届菲洛梅娜研讨会
{"title":"Introduction by The Guest Editor – 4th Filomena Workshop","authors":"Revista Principia","doi":"10.5007/1808-1711.2021.E82665","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5007/1808-1711.2021.E82665","url":null,"abstract":"Introduction by The Guest Editor – 4th Filomena Workshop","PeriodicalId":38561,"journal":{"name":"Principia","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-07-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46387887","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Acciones, sistemas normativos o creencias ¿Dónde se fundamenta la violencia? 暴力的依据是什么?
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-07-08 DOI: 10.5007/1808-1711.2021.E73843
David Suárez-Rivero
En el presente artículo evalúo el concepto de violencia, explorando casos hipotéticos que permitan establecer cuáles son las condiciones o criterios que muestran cuándo una acción puede ser calificada como violenta. Frente a esto, parto de la idea de que una acción es violenta cuando rompe reglas o normas, las cuales son establecidas por sistemas sociales que se fundan en sistema de creencias. Concluyo, así, que hay que examinar los sistemas de creencias, donde se fundan los sistemas sociales, para erradicar todo tipo de acción que pueda romper reglas o normas. 
在这篇文章中,我评估了暴力的概念,探索了假设的案例,这些案例可以确定哪些条件或标准表明行动何时可以被归类为暴力。面对这一点,我的想法是,一种行为在违反规则或规范时是暴力的,这些规则或规范是由建立在信仰体系基础上的社会制度建立的。因此,我的结论是,必须审查社会制度建立的信仰制度,以消除可能违反规则或规范的一切行动。
{"title":"Acciones, sistemas normativos o creencias ¿Dónde se fundamenta la violencia?","authors":"David Suárez-Rivero","doi":"10.5007/1808-1711.2021.E73843","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5007/1808-1711.2021.E73843","url":null,"abstract":"En el presente artículo evalúo el concepto de violencia, explorando casos hipotéticos que permitan establecer cuáles son las condiciones o criterios que muestran cuándo una acción puede ser calificada como violenta. Frente a esto, parto de la idea de que una acción es violenta cuando rompe reglas o normas, las cuales son establecidas por sistemas sociales que se fundan en sistema de creencias. Concluyo, así, que hay que examinar los sistemas de creencias, donde se fundan los sistemas sociales, para erradicar todo tipo de acción que pueda romper reglas o normas. ","PeriodicalId":38561,"journal":{"name":"Principia","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-07-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44065552","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
COMENTÁRIOS DA NARRATIVA DE ATOS 13. 14-41; 14. 14-18; 17. 22-34; 22. 1-24 PELA PERSPECTIVA TEÓRICA DE GÉRARD GENETTE 对使徒行传第13章叙述的评论。14 -41;14. 14 -18;17. 22 -34;22. gerard GENETTE的理论视角1-24
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-04-07 DOI: 10.12957/PRINCIPIA.2020.58996
L. Oliveira
Gérard Genette conceitua a narrativa como a representação de um acontecimento ou de vários acontecimentos, considerados reais ou fictícios, por meio da linguagem e, principalmente, da linguagem escrita (GENETTE, 2011, p. 265). A estrutura da narrativa, em Genette, é analisada tendo por referências três categorias, que são fundamentadas no(a): tempo, modo e voz. Assim é que o presente artigo tem por escopo tecer comentários de alguns excertos do livro de Atos dos Apóstolos pelo viés teórico de Gérard Genette.
gerard Genette将叙事概念化为通过语言,特别是书面语言,对一个事件或几个事件的再现,被认为是真实的或虚构的(Genette, 2011, p. 265)。本文从时间、模式和声音三个方面对《热内特》的叙事结构进行了分析。因此,本文的目的是通过gerard Genette的理论偏见,对使徒行传的一些摘录进行评论。
{"title":"COMENTÁRIOS DA NARRATIVA DE ATOS 13. 14-41; 14. 14-18; 17. 22-34; 22. 1-24 PELA PERSPECTIVA TEÓRICA DE GÉRARD GENETTE","authors":"L. Oliveira","doi":"10.12957/PRINCIPIA.2020.58996","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.12957/PRINCIPIA.2020.58996","url":null,"abstract":"Gérard Genette conceitua a narrativa como a representação de um acontecimento ou de vários acontecimentos, considerados reais ou fictícios, por meio da linguagem e, principalmente, da linguagem escrita (GENETTE, 2011, p. 265). A estrutura da narrativa, em Genette, é analisada tendo por referências três categorias, que são fundamentadas no(a): tempo, modo e voz. Assim é que o presente artigo tem por escopo tecer comentários de alguns excertos do livro de Atos dos Apóstolos pelo viés teórico de Gérard Genette.","PeriodicalId":38561,"journal":{"name":"Principia","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-04-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"90888328","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
O GRAFEMA DAS ESCRITAS NÃO-FONÉTICAS: HIEROGLIFO, PICTOGRAMA, LOGOGRAMA, IDEOGRAMA? 非语音文字的字母组合:象形文字、象形文字、符号文字、表意文字?
Q3 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2021-04-07 DOI: 10.12957/PRINCIPIA.2020.58991
Elisa Figueira de Souza Corrêa
Este artigo examina quatro termos diferentes comumente utilizados para se referir aos grafemas de escritas não-fonéticas: pictograma, hieroglifo, logograma e ideograma. Faz-se a revisão das definições mais comuns a fim de estabelecer diferenças e semelhanças entre os termos e, na fixação de limites, defende-se a continuação da terminologia “ideograma” para os caracteres chineses em uso, mormente, na China e Japão, para marcar suas próprias peculiaridades.
这篇文章探讨了四个不同的术语,通常用于指非语音书写的字素:象形文字、象形文字、符号和表意文字。本文回顾了最常见的定义,以确定术语之间的异同,并在确定界限时,为继续使用“表意文字”术语进行辩护,特别是在中国和日本使用的汉字,以标记它们自己的特点。
{"title":"O GRAFEMA DAS ESCRITAS NÃO-FONÉTICAS: HIEROGLIFO, PICTOGRAMA, LOGOGRAMA, IDEOGRAMA?","authors":"Elisa Figueira de Souza Corrêa","doi":"10.12957/PRINCIPIA.2020.58991","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.12957/PRINCIPIA.2020.58991","url":null,"abstract":"Este artigo examina quatro termos diferentes comumente utilizados para se referir aos grafemas de escritas não-fonéticas: pictograma, hieroglifo, logograma e ideograma. Faz-se a revisão das definições mais comuns a fim de estabelecer diferenças e semelhanças entre os termos e, na fixação de limites, defende-se a continuação da terminologia “ideograma” para os caracteres chineses em uso, mormente, na China e Japão, para marcar suas próprias peculiaridades.","PeriodicalId":38561,"journal":{"name":"Principia","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-04-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"80344532","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Principia
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1