首页 > 最新文献

HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science最新文献

英文 中文
Relativity Theory as a Theory of Principles: A Reading of Cassirer’s Zur Einstein’schen Relativitätstheorie 作为原理理论的相对论:解读卡西尔的《爱因斯坦的理论》Relativitätstheorie
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2023-06-01 DOI: 10.1086/726076
Marco Giovanelli
In his Zur Einstein’schen Relativitätstheorie, Ernst Cassirer presents relativity theory as the last manifestation of the tradition of the “physics of principles” that, starting from the nineteenth century, has progressively prevailed over that of the “physics of models.” In particular, according to Cassirer, the relativity principle plays a role similar to the energy principle in previous physics. In this article, I argue that this comparison represents the core of Cassirer’s neo-Kantian interpretation of relativity. Cassirer pointed out that before and after Kant, the history of physics presents significant instances in which the search for formal conditions that the laws of nature must satisfy preceded and made possible the direct search for such laws. In his earlier years, Cassirer seems to have regarded principles like the energy principle, the relativity principle, and the principle of least action as a constitutive but provisional form of a priori, imposing specific limitations on the form of the allowable laws of nature. Only in his later years, by attributing an autonomous status to these statements of principle, did Cassirer attribute a definitive but merely regulative meaning to the a priori. This does not impose specific requirements on natural laws but only a motivation to search for them.
恩斯特·卡西尔(Ernst Cassirer)在他的《爱因斯坦的理论Relativitätstheorie》(Zur Einstein’s schen)一书中,将相对论描述为“原理物理学”传统的最后表现。从19世纪开始,“原理物理学”传统逐渐压倒了“模型物理学”传统。特别是,根据卡西尔的说法,相对性原理在以前的物理学中扮演着类似于能量原理的角色。在本文中,我认为这种比较代表了卡西尔对相对论的新康德主义解释的核心。卡西尔指出,在康德之前和之后,物理学的历史都有一些重要的例子,在这些例子中,对自然规律必须满足的形式条件的探索先于对自然规律的直接探索,并使之成为可能。卡西尔早年似乎把能量原理、相对性原理和最小作用原理等原则视为先天的一种构成但暂时的形式,对可允许的自然法则的形式施加了特定的限制。只有在他的晚年,通过赋予这些原则陈述一种自主的地位,卡西尔才赋予先验一种确定的但仅仅是调节的意义。这并没有对自然法则提出具体的要求,而只是一种寻找自然法则的动机。
{"title":"Relativity Theory as a Theory of Principles: A Reading of Cassirer’s Zur Einstein’schen Relativitätstheorie","authors":"Marco Giovanelli","doi":"10.1086/726076","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/726076","url":null,"abstract":"In his Zur Einstein’schen Relativitätstheorie, Ernst Cassirer presents relativity theory as the last manifestation of the tradition of the “physics of principles” that, starting from the nineteenth century, has progressively prevailed over that of the “physics of models.” In particular, according to Cassirer, the relativity principle plays a role similar to the energy principle in previous physics. In this article, I argue that this comparison represents the core of Cassirer’s neo-Kantian interpretation of relativity. Cassirer pointed out that before and after Kant, the history of physics presents significant instances in which the search for formal conditions that the laws of nature must satisfy preceded and made possible the direct search for such laws. In his earlier years, Cassirer seems to have regarded principles like the energy principle, the relativity principle, and the principle of least action as a constitutive but provisional form of a priori, imposing specific limitations on the form of the allowable laws of nature. Only in his later years, by attributing an autonomous status to these statements of principle, did Cassirer attribute a definitive but merely regulative meaning to the a priori. This does not impose specific requirements on natural laws but only a motivation to search for them.","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"1 1","pages":"261 - 296"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2023-06-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"75692557","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Cogito, Ergo Sumus? The Pregnancy Problem in Descartes’s Philosophy 我思,Ergo Sumus?笛卡尔哲学中的怀孕问题
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2023-04-24 DOI: 10.1086/725593
Maja Sidzinska
Given Descartes’s metaphysical and natural-philosophic commitments, it is difficult to theorize the pregnant human being as a human being under his system. Specifically, given (1) Descartes’s account of generation; (2) his commitment to mechanistic explanations where bodies are concerned; (3) his reliance on a subtle individuating principle for human (and animal) bodies; and (4) his metaphysics of human beings, which include minds, bodies, and mind-body unions, there is no available human substance or entity that may clearly be the subject of pregnancy. The incompatibility of any of the three options found in commitment 4 with commitment 1, 2, or 3, together with other undesirable consequences should any be selected, results in what I call the pregnancy problem. The pregnancy problem is a previously unconsidered problem for the Cartesian philosophy. Given the pregnancy problem, commitment 1, 2, 3, or 4, or a combination of these would have to be revised for Descartes’s system to avoid a variety of tensions; alternatively, counterintuitive consequences may have to be accepted. Ironically, given Descartes’s interest in generation and medicine more generally, the Cartesian framework struggles to accommodate pregnancy in human beings. This may have implications for the systematicity and sex neutrality of dualist metaphysics in general.
考虑到笛卡尔的形而上学和自然哲学的承诺,在他的体系下,很难将怀孕的人作为一个人理论化。具体来说,考虑到(1)笛卡尔的世代论;(2)他对有关身体的机械论解释的承诺;(3)他对人类(和动物)身体微妙的个性化原则的依赖;(4)他关于人类的形而上学,包括思想,身体和身心结合,没有可用的人类物质或实体可以明确地成为怀孕的主题。在承诺4中发现的三个选项中的任何一个与承诺1、2或3不相容,再加上选择任何一个的其他不良后果,就会导致我所说的怀孕问题。怀孕问题是笛卡尔哲学以前没有考虑过的问题。考虑到怀孕的问题,承诺1、2、3或4,或它们的组合都必须根据笛卡尔的系统进行修改,以避免各种紧张关系;或者,违反直觉的结果可能不得不被接受。具有讽刺意味的是,考虑到笛卡尔对生育和医学更普遍的兴趣,笛卡尔的框架很难适应人类怀孕。这可能会对二元论形而上学的系统性和性别中立性产生影响。
{"title":"Cogito, Ergo Sumus? The Pregnancy Problem in Descartes’s Philosophy","authors":"Maja Sidzinska","doi":"10.1086/725593","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/725593","url":null,"abstract":"Given Descartes’s metaphysical and natural-philosophic commitments, it is difficult to theorize the pregnant human being as a human being under his system. Specifically, given (1) Descartes’s account of generation; (2) his commitment to mechanistic explanations where bodies are concerned; (3) his reliance on a subtle individuating principle for human (and animal) bodies; and (4) his metaphysics of human beings, which include minds, bodies, and mind-body unions, there is no available human substance or entity that may clearly be the subject of pregnancy. The incompatibility of any of the three options found in commitment 4 with commitment 1, 2, or 3, together with other undesirable consequences should any be selected, results in what I call the pregnancy problem. The pregnancy problem is a previously unconsidered problem for the Cartesian philosophy. Given the pregnancy problem, commitment 1, 2, 3, or 4, or a combination of these would have to be revised for Descartes’s system to avoid a variety of tensions; alternatively, counterintuitive consequences may have to be accepted. Ironically, given Descartes’s interest in generation and medicine more generally, the Cartesian framework struggles to accommodate pregnancy in human beings. This may have implications for the systematicity and sex neutrality of dualist metaphysics in general.","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"37 1","pages":"209 - 240"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2023-04-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"77741959","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Front Matter 前页
Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2023-03-01 DOI: 10.1086/725535
{"title":"Front Matter","authors":"","doi":"10.1086/725535","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/725535","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"99 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"134950049","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
:The Science of Proof: Forensic Medicine in Modern France 《证据科学:现代法国的法医学》
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2023-03-01 DOI: 10.1086/724052
Brandon Long
{"title":":The Science of Proof: Forensic Medicine in Modern France","authors":"Brandon Long","doi":"10.1086/724052","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/724052","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"28 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2023-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"85439531","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
:Dem wissenschaftlichen Determinismus auf der Spur: Von der klassischen Mechanik zur Entstehung der Quantenphysik 科学的决定论一路从古典力学到量子物理的起源
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2023-03-01 DOI: 10.1086/724051
Massimo Ferrari
{"title":":Dem wissenschaftlichen Determinismus auf der Spur: Von der klassischen Mechanik zur Entstehung der Quantenphysik","authors":"Massimo Ferrari","doi":"10.1086/724051","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/724051","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"53 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2023-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"83406213","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
We Have Never Been “New Experimentalists”: On the Rise and Fall of the Turn to Experimentation in the 1980s 我们从来都不是“新实验主义者”:20世纪80年代转向实验的兴衰
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2023-01-10 DOI: 10.1086/724045
J. Potters, M. Simons
The 1980s, it is often claimed, was the decade when experimentation finally became a philosophical topic. This was the responsibility, the claim continues, of one particular movement within philosophy of science, called “new experimentalism.” The aim of this article is to complicate this historical narrative. We argue that in the 1980s, the study of experimentation was carried out not by one movement with one particular aim but rather in a diverse and open-ended way by people with different aims and backgrounds. We then argue that from the late 1990s onward, this diversity disappeared and made room for disciplinary divisions—questions concerning experimentation became philosophical, others sociological, and so on. The reason for this, we claim, was that science and technology studies, philosophy of technology, and philosophy of science took over aspects of the 1980s study of experimentation. In this way, we argue, these elements became institutionalized, whereas others were forgotten. The importance of this process of institutionalization is illustrated by means of a discussion of other, similar approaches to the philosophy of experimentation that have not been able to ensure continuity because they did not find an institutional home.
人们常说,20世纪80年代是实验最终成为哲学话题的十年。他们继续声称,这是科学哲学中一个被称为“新实验主义”的特殊运动的责任。本文的目的是使这一历史叙述复杂化。我们认为,在20世纪80年代,实验研究不是由一个具有特定目标的运动进行的,而是由具有不同目标和背景的人以多样化和开放式的方式进行的。然后我们认为,从20世纪90年代末开始,这种多样性消失了,为学科划分腾出了空间——有关实验的问题变成了哲学问题,其他问题变成了社会学问题,等等。我们认为,造成这种情况的原因是,科学和技术研究、技术哲学和科学哲学接管了20世纪80年代实验研究的各个方面。我们认为,通过这种方式,这些要素被制度化,而其他要素则被遗忘。通过对实验哲学的其他类似方法的讨论,可以说明这一制度化过程的重要性,这些方法由于没有找到一个机构的家而无法确保连续性。
{"title":"We Have Never Been “New Experimentalists”: On the Rise and Fall of the Turn to Experimentation in the 1980s","authors":"J. Potters, M. Simons","doi":"10.1086/724045","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/724045","url":null,"abstract":"The 1980s, it is often claimed, was the decade when experimentation finally became a philosophical topic. This was the responsibility, the claim continues, of one particular movement within philosophy of science, called “new experimentalism.” The aim of this article is to complicate this historical narrative. We argue that in the 1980s, the study of experimentation was carried out not by one movement with one particular aim but rather in a diverse and open-ended way by people with different aims and backgrounds. We then argue that from the late 1990s onward, this diversity disappeared and made room for disciplinary divisions—questions concerning experimentation became philosophical, others sociological, and so on. The reason for this, we claim, was that science and technology studies, philosophy of technology, and philosophy of science took over aspects of the 1980s study of experimentation. In this way, we argue, these elements became institutionalized, whereas others were forgotten. The importance of this process of institutionalization is illustrated by means of a discussion of other, similar approaches to the philosophy of experimentation that have not been able to ensure continuity because they did not find an institutional home.","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"8 1","pages":"91 - 119"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2023-01-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"76307745","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Philosophical Method of Dioscorides’s De Materia Medica 迪奥斯科里德《本草论》的哲学方法
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2023-01-10 DOI: 10.1086/724061
M. Marren, Kevin Marren
It is commonly thought that Dioscorides’s view on medicine is purely pragmatic, focused entirely on the effectiveness of medicines, and derived from trial and error. One reason for this interpretation is that Dioscorides himself wrote little about his theory of medicine. In this article, however, we argue that he would have arranged De Materia Medica in a way that would have been useful only to a skilled practitioner. This argument implies that Dioscorides had a medical theory, as the arrangement of the content could not have followed a trial-and-error approach. It is only in the sense of having a theory that he is able to claim that his text is more “complete” than others. This article provides a historical overview of the text from its genesis to its reception and, ultimately, to its falling out of use. This article concludes with a series of hypotheses on the correspondence between theory and arrangement of the treatise, with the aim of narrowing scholarly conjectures about both. In the final analysis, we argue that an arrangement by family resemblance most closely corresponds to the theory that animates Dioscorides’s text.
人们普遍认为,迪奥斯科里迪斯的医学观点纯粹是实用主义的,完全关注药物的有效性,并且是从试验和错误中得出的。这种解释的一个原因是迪奥斯科里德斯自己很少写他的医学理论。然而,在本文中,我们认为他会以一种只对熟练的从业者有用的方式安排《本草论》。这个论点暗示迪奥斯科里迪斯有一个医学理论,因为内容的安排不可能遵循试错方法。只有在拥有理论的意义上,他才能够声称他的文本比其他人更“完整”。本文提供了一个历史概述的文本,从它的起源到它的接受,并最终,它的衰落使用。本文最后对《论著》的理论与编排之间的对应关系提出了一系列假设,旨在缩小学术界对两者的猜测。在最后的分析中,我们认为,家庭相似性的安排最接近于激活迪奥斯科里德文本的理论。
{"title":"Philosophical Method of Dioscorides’s De Materia Medica","authors":"M. Marren, Kevin Marren","doi":"10.1086/724061","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/724061","url":null,"abstract":"It is commonly thought that Dioscorides’s view on medicine is purely pragmatic, focused entirely on the effectiveness of medicines, and derived from trial and error. One reason for this interpretation is that Dioscorides himself wrote little about his theory of medicine. In this article, however, we argue that he would have arranged De Materia Medica in a way that would have been useful only to a skilled practitioner. This argument implies that Dioscorides had a medical theory, as the arrangement of the content could not have followed a trial-and-error approach. It is only in the sense of having a theory that he is able to claim that his text is more “complete” than others. This article provides a historical overview of the text from its genesis to its reception and, ultimately, to its falling out of use. This article concludes with a series of hypotheses on the correspondence between theory and arrangement of the treatise, with the aim of narrowing scholarly conjectures about both. In the final analysis, we argue that an arrangement by family resemblance most closely corresponds to the theory that animates Dioscorides’s text.","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"60 1","pages":"180 - 198"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2023-01-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"83956950","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Poincaré’s Radical Ontology 庞加莱的激进本体论
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2023-01-10 DOI: 10.1086/724050
J. Holder
I present an exegesis of Henri Poincaré’s metaphysical position in three key essays within his book The Value of Science. In doing so, I argue for three theses: (a) that Poincaré’s metaphysical position in these sources is incompatible with his metaphysical position in his earlier book Science and Hypothesis; (b) that the phenomenological relationism defended by Poincaré in these sources is not a form of structural realism but rather a structuralist form of empiricism and (by design) has no greater metaphysical commitments than constructive empiricism; and (c) that Poincaré holds in these sources that the existence of the external world is merely a convention. These theses serve to correct misconceptions about the consistency of Poincaré’s philosophical corpus, his positions on the realism-antirealism landscape, and the scope of his conventionalism.
我在亨利·庞加莱的《科学的价值》一书中的三篇关键文章中对他的形而上学立场进行了注解。在此过程中,我提出了三个论点:(a)庞加莱在这些资料中的形而上学立场与他在早期著作《科学与假说》中的形而上学立场是不相容的;(b)庞加莱在这些资料中所捍卫的现象学关系主义不是结构实在论的一种形式,而是经验主义的一种结构主义形式,并且(有意地)没有比建构经验主义更大的形而上学承诺;(c)庞加莱在这些材料中认为外部世界的存在仅仅是一种约定。这些论点有助于纠正关于庞加莱哲学主体的一致性、他对现实主义-反现实主义景观的立场以及他的传统主义范围的误解。
{"title":"Poincaré’s Radical Ontology","authors":"J. Holder","doi":"10.1086/724050","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/724050","url":null,"abstract":"I present an exegesis of Henri Poincaré’s metaphysical position in three key essays within his book The Value of Science. In doing so, I argue for three theses: (a) that Poincaré’s metaphysical position in these sources is incompatible with his metaphysical position in his earlier book Science and Hypothesis; (b) that the phenomenological relationism defended by Poincaré in these sources is not a form of structural realism but rather a structuralist form of empiricism and (by design) has no greater metaphysical commitments than constructive empiricism; and (c) that Poincaré holds in these sources that the existence of the external world is merely a convention. These theses serve to correct misconceptions about the consistency of Poincaré’s philosophical corpus, his positions on the realism-antirealism landscape, and the scope of his conventionalism.","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"SE-10 1","pages":"151 - 179"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2023-01-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"84637628","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
John Dewey: Was the Inventor of Instrumentalism Himself an Instrumentalist? 约翰·杜威:工具主义的发明者自己是工具主义者吗?
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2023-01-10 DOI: 10.1086/724043
C. Henne
In discussing instrumentalism in philosophy of science, John Dewey is rarely studied but rather mentioned in passing to credit him for coining the label. His instrumentalism is often interpreted as the view that science is an instrument designed to control the environment and satisfy our practical ends or likened to the Duhemian view that scientific objects are useful fictions for organizing observable phenomena. Dewey was careful to qualify the first view and denied holding the second. Furthermore, the observable-unobservable distinction does not play any significant role in Dewey’s instrumentalism. The question then arises: Was the inventor of instrumentalism himself an instrumentalist? I present the key aspects of Dewey’s instrumentalism and contrast his views with the instrumentalism of Mach, Duhem, and Poincaré. Dewey’s epistemological instrumentalism is global and not local; nevertheless, it is fallibilist and optimistic rather than skeptical and pessimistic. Dewey’s ontological instrumentalism concerns the nature of scientific objects, regardless of whether they are observable or unobservable, and is fully compatible with realism about atoms or electrons. Dewey’s practical instrumentalism holds that because science provides understanding of the workings of nature rather than an exhaustive picture of reality, it is the best instrument we have for the enrichment of experience.
在讨论科学哲学中的工具主义时,很少研究约翰·杜威,而是顺便提到他,以赞扬他创造了这个标签。他的工具主义经常被解释为这样一种观点,即科学是一种旨在控制环境并满足我们实际目的的工具,或者被比作杜赫米的观点,即科学对象是组织可观察现象的有用虚构。杜威小心地限定了第一种观点,并否认持有第二种观点。此外,可观察和不可观察的区别在杜威的工具主义中没有发挥任何重要作用。那么问题来了:工具主义的发明者自己也是工具主义者吗?我提出了杜威工具主义的关键方面,并将他的观点与马赫、杜昂和庞卡莱的工具主义进行了对比。杜威的认识论工具主义是全球性的,而不是地方性的;然而,它是易犯错误的和乐观的,而不是怀疑和悲观的。杜威的本体论工具主义关注的是科学对象的本质,不管它们是可观察的还是不可观察的,它与关于原子或电子的实在论完全相容。杜威的实践工具主义认为,因为科学提供了对自然运作的理解,而不是对现实的详尽描述,所以它是我们丰富经验的最好工具。
{"title":"John Dewey: Was the Inventor of Instrumentalism Himself an Instrumentalist?","authors":"C. Henne","doi":"10.1086/724043","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/724043","url":null,"abstract":"In discussing instrumentalism in philosophy of science, John Dewey is rarely studied but rather mentioned in passing to credit him for coining the label. His instrumentalism is often interpreted as the view that science is an instrument designed to control the environment and satisfy our practical ends or likened to the Duhemian view that scientific objects are useful fictions for organizing observable phenomena. Dewey was careful to qualify the first view and denied holding the second. Furthermore, the observable-unobservable distinction does not play any significant role in Dewey’s instrumentalism. The question then arises: Was the inventor of instrumentalism himself an instrumentalist? I present the key aspects of Dewey’s instrumentalism and contrast his views with the instrumentalism of Mach, Duhem, and Poincaré. Dewey’s epistemological instrumentalism is global and not local; nevertheless, it is fallibilist and optimistic rather than skeptical and pessimistic. Dewey’s ontological instrumentalism concerns the nature of scientific objects, regardless of whether they are observable or unobservable, and is fully compatible with realism about atoms or electrons. Dewey’s practical instrumentalism holds that because science provides understanding of the workings of nature rather than an exhaustive picture of reality, it is the best instrument we have for the enrichment of experience.","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"46 1","pages":"120 - 150"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2023-01-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"88574754","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Popper: Critical Rationalist, Conventionalist, and Virtue Epistemologist 波普尔:批判理性主义者、约定主义者和美德认识论家
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2023-01-10 DOI: 10.1086/724046
Patrick M. Duerr
This article revisits Karl Popper’s falsificationist methodology with respect to three tasks. The first is to illuminate and systematize Popper’s methodological views in light of his core epistemological commitments. A second and related objective is to gauge which aspects of falsificationism should be identified as “conventionalist”—a label that Popper himself uses (albeit with qualifications) but that is compromised by and, thus, stands in need of elucidation because of Popper’s idiosyncratic understanding of conventionalism. Third, by elaborating Popper’s virtue-epistemological, dialogical model of rationality, I show how Popper’s conventionalism, fallibilism, and critical rationalism form a coherent system. This system allows Popper to accord science the status of a privileged source of knowledge—without naïve appeal to authority. My systematization of Popper’s views yields an intrinsically and exegetically more satisfactory reading of Popper’s falsificationism than usual presentations. Thanks to its marked flexibility and methodological liberalism, it bypasses many standard objections but still offers sound and relevant methodological advice. With its “virtue-methodological” thrust, Popper sketches an original and promising approach to methodology, the fertility of which deserves further exploration for contemporary debates.
本文从三个方面回顾了卡尔·波普尔的证伪主义方法论。首先,根据波普尔的核心认识论承诺,阐明并系统化他的方法论观点。第二个和相关的目标是衡量证伪主义的哪些方面应该被认定为“约定主义”——波普尔自己使用的标签(尽管有条件),但由于波普尔对约定主义的特殊理解,这一标签受到了损害,因此需要加以阐明。第三,通过阐述波普尔的美德认识论、理性对话模型,我展示了波普尔的约定主义、可错论和批判理性主义如何形成一个连贯的系统。这一体系允许波普尔赋予科学知识的特权来源地位,而无需naïve诉诸权威。我对波普尔观点的系统化产生了一种本质上和训诂上更令人满意的对波普尔证伪主义的解读,而不是通常的陈述。由于其显著的灵活性和方法论上的自由主义,它绕过了许多标准的反对意见,但仍然提供了合理和相关的方法论建议。在“美德方法论”的推动下,波普尔描绘了一种新颖而有前途的方法论方法,其丰富性值得在当代辩论中进一步探索。
{"title":"Popper: Critical Rationalist, Conventionalist, and Virtue Epistemologist","authors":"Patrick M. Duerr","doi":"10.1086/724046","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/724046","url":null,"abstract":"This article revisits Karl Popper’s falsificationist methodology with respect to three tasks. The first is to illuminate and systematize Popper’s methodological views in light of his core epistemological commitments. A second and related objective is to gauge which aspects of falsificationism should be identified as “conventionalist”—a label that Popper himself uses (albeit with qualifications) but that is compromised by and, thus, stands in need of elucidation because of Popper’s idiosyncratic understanding of conventionalism. Third, by elaborating Popper’s virtue-epistemological, dialogical model of rationality, I show how Popper’s conventionalism, fallibilism, and critical rationalism form a coherent system. This system allows Popper to accord science the status of a privileged source of knowledge—without naïve appeal to authority. My systematization of Popper’s views yields an intrinsically and exegetically more satisfactory reading of Popper’s falsificationism than usual presentations. Thanks to its marked flexibility and methodological liberalism, it bypasses many standard objections but still offers sound and relevant methodological advice. With its “virtue-methodological” thrust, Popper sketches an original and promising approach to methodology, the fertility of which deserves further exploration for contemporary debates.","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"68 1","pages":"54 - 90"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2023-01-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"72963643","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1