首页 > 最新文献

HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science最新文献

英文 中文
Special Issue Introduction 特刊简介
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2021-09-01 DOI: 10.1086/715974
W. Schmaus, Olivier Rey
Today we talk about postpositivism. But which positivism is it that postpositivism would leave behind? It would appear to be the neopositivism or logical positivism of the Vienna Circle more than the positivism of Auguste Comte. This way of considering positivism is emblematic of a certain bias: the history of French philosophy of science has been relatively neglected compared to that of Central Europe. Some great figures, such as Pierre Duhem or Henri Poincaré, are taken into consideration, but they are most often treated as if their philosophy were entirely their own creation, much like Athena springing from the head of Zeus. The reality is different: Duhem’s and Poincaré’s thought, each in their own way, has historical roots in the original positivism of Auguste Comte. There is a certain irony to this neglect of the Comtean tradition. While the Vienna Circle logical positivists borrowed half of their name from it, they were hardly interested in studying the source of this philosophy. This relative lack of interest in the development of positivist ideas in France is somewhat paradoxical if we consider, for example, the political dimension that scholars of Vienna Circle have claimed in the thought of Rudolf Carnap,OttoNeurath,HansHahn, and Philip Frank. Such allegations are controversial: even though logical positivists may have had a political agenda, its connection with their philosophy of science is
今天我们讨论后实证主义。但后实证主义会抛弃哪一种实证主义呢?它看起来更像是维也纳学派的新实证主义或逻辑实证主义,而不是奥古斯特·孔德的实证主义。这种看待实证主义的方式象征着某种偏见:与中欧相比,法国科学哲学史相对被忽视了。一些伟大的人物,如皮埃尔·迪昂或亨利·庞加莱,也被考虑在内,但他们的哲学往往被认为完全是他们自己创造的,就像雅典娜从宙斯的头上冒出来一样。现实是不同的:迪昂和庞加莱的思想,以他们各自的方式,都有奥古斯特·孔德最初的实证主义的历史根源。这种对孔德传统的忽视具有一定的讽刺意味。虽然维也纳学派的逻辑实证主义者借用了它一半的名字,但他们对研究这种哲学的来源几乎没有兴趣。如果我们考虑到维也纳学派的学者们在鲁道夫·卡尔纳普、奥托·诺拉斯、汉斯·哈恩和菲利普·弗兰克的思想中所宣称的政治维度,那么法国对实证主义思想的发展相对缺乏兴趣就有点矛盾了。这样的指控是有争议的:尽管逻辑实证主义者可能有一个政治议程,但它与他们的科学哲学是有联系的
{"title":"Special Issue Introduction","authors":"W. Schmaus, Olivier Rey","doi":"10.1086/715974","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/715974","url":null,"abstract":"Today we talk about postpositivism. But which positivism is it that postpositivism would leave behind? It would appear to be the neopositivism or logical positivism of the Vienna Circle more than the positivism of Auguste Comte. This way of considering positivism is emblematic of a certain bias: the history of French philosophy of science has been relatively neglected compared to that of Central Europe. Some great figures, such as Pierre Duhem or Henri Poincaré, are taken into consideration, but they are most often treated as if their philosophy were entirely their own creation, much like Athena springing from the head of Zeus. The reality is different: Duhem’s and Poincaré’s thought, each in their own way, has historical roots in the original positivism of Auguste Comte. There is a certain irony to this neglect of the Comtean tradition. While the Vienna Circle logical positivists borrowed half of their name from it, they were hardly interested in studying the source of this philosophy. This relative lack of interest in the development of positivist ideas in France is somewhat paradoxical if we consider, for example, the political dimension that scholars of Vienna Circle have claimed in the thought of Rudolf Carnap,OttoNeurath,HansHahn, and Philip Frank. Such allegations are controversial: even though logical positivists may have had a political agenda, its connection with their philosophy of science is","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"23 1","pages":"421 - 427"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-09-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"78981169","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Chemical Philosophy of Robert Boyle: Mechanism, Chymical Atoms, and Emergence, by Marina Paola Banchetti-Robino 《罗伯特·波义耳的化学哲学:机制、化学原子和涌现》,作者:Marina Paola Banchetti-Robino
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2021-07-14 DOI: 10.1086/715881
William Eaton
{"title":"The Chemical Philosophy of Robert Boyle: Mechanism, Chymical Atoms, and Emergence, by Marina Paola Banchetti-Robino","authors":"William Eaton","doi":"10.1086/715881","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/715881","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-07-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"78137009","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Infinity and the Self: Royce on Dedekind 无限与自我:罗伊斯在戴德金
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2021-06-28 DOI: 10.1086/715874
S. Gandon
In Die Zahlen (1888), Dedekind defines an infinite set as a set that is isomorphic with one of its proper parts. In The World and the Individual (1900), the American philosopher Josiah Royce relates Dedekind’s notion to Fichte’s and Hegel’s concept of Self defined as an entity that reflects itself into itself. The first aim of this article is to explain Royce’s analysis and to put it in its proper context, that of a critique of Bradley’s mystical idealism. The second aim is to urge a shift in focus in Dedekind’s scholarship: instead of addressing the question of the relationship between mathematics and philosophy in Dedekind’s work through the supposed intentions of its author, it is more fruitful to analyze the reception that philosophers have made of his texts.
在Die Zahlen(1888)中,Dedekind将无限集定义为与其固有部分之一同构的集合。在《世界与个人》(1900)一书中,美国哲学家约西亚·罗伊斯将戴德金德的概念与费希特和黑格尔的“自我”概念联系起来,将其定义为一个反映自身的实体。本文的第一个目的是解释罗伊斯的分析,并将其置于适当的背景下,即对布拉德利神秘唯心主义的批判。第二个目的是促使对戴德金德学术的关注发生转变:与其通过作者的假想意图来解决戴德金德作品中数学和哲学之间关系的问题,倒不如分析哲学家对他的文本的接受情况更有成效。
{"title":"Infinity and the Self: Royce on Dedekind","authors":"S. Gandon","doi":"10.1086/715874","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/715874","url":null,"abstract":"In Die Zahlen (1888), Dedekind defines an infinite set as a set that is isomorphic with one of its proper parts. In The World and the Individual (1900), the American philosopher Josiah Royce relates Dedekind’s notion to Fichte’s and Hegel’s concept of Self defined as an entity that reflects itself into itself. The first aim of this article is to explain Royce’s analysis and to put it in its proper context, that of a critique of Bradley’s mystical idealism. The second aim is to urge a shift in focus in Dedekind’s scholarship: instead of addressing the question of the relationship between mathematics and philosophy in Dedekind’s work through the supposed intentions of its author, it is more fruitful to analyze the reception that philosophers have made of his texts.","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"20 1","pages":"354 - 382"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-06-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"73600087","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Erich H. Reck and Georg Schiemer, editors, The Prehistory of Mathematical Structuralism Erich H. Reck和Georg Schiemer编辑,《数学结构主义的史前史》
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2021-06-28 DOI: 10.1086/715882
A. Sereni
{"title":"Erich H. Reck and Georg Schiemer, editors, The Prehistory of Mathematical Structuralism","authors":"A. Sereni","doi":"10.1086/715882","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/715882","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"76 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-06-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"88574759","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
How Did Philosophy of Science Come About? 科学哲学是如何产生的?
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2021-06-28 DOI: 10.1086/715875
Anastasios Brenner
Recent research has brought to light numerous facts that go against received views of the development of philosophy of science. One encounters several concepts, claims, or projects much earlier than is generally acknowledged. Auguste Comte was careful to distinguish each major science with respect to method and object, speaking of mathematical philosophy, biological philosophy, sociological philosophy, and so forth. He thereby in a sense anticipated the regionalist turn: philosophical analysis should be carried out with respect to a specific body of knowledge. He also adopted a general perspective, a scientific philosophy. In the light of new discoveries, later thinkers such as Pierre Duhem, Gaston Milhaud, and Abel Rey endeavored to reformulate Comte’s doctrine as a neopositivism, a logical positivism, or an absolute positivism. The aim of this article is to examine the constitutive concepts mentioned and the controversies that hinge on them, in an effort to reach a precise understanding of the aim, scope, and import of philosophy of science in the context of nineteenth-century France.
最近的研究揭示了许多与人们对科学哲学发展的普遍看法相悖的事实。一个人遇到一些概念、主张或项目的时间比通常承认的要早得多。奥古斯特·孔德在方法和对象方面仔细区分了每一门主要的科学,他谈到了数学哲学、生物哲学、社会学哲学等等。因此,他在某种意义上预见了地域主义的转向:哲学分析应该针对特定的知识体系进行。他还采用了一种普遍的观点,一种科学的哲学。根据新的发现,后来的思想家,如皮埃尔·迪昂、加斯顿·米约和阿贝尔·雷,努力将孔德的学说重新表述为新实证主义、逻辑实证主义或绝对实证主义。本文的目的是研究所提到的构成概念和围绕它们的争议,努力达到对19世纪法国背景下科学哲学的目的、范围和重要性的精确理解。
{"title":"How Did Philosophy of Science Come About?","authors":"Anastasios Brenner","doi":"10.1086/715875","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/715875","url":null,"abstract":"Recent research has brought to light numerous facts that go against received views of the development of philosophy of science. One encounters several concepts, claims, or projects much earlier than is generally acknowledged. Auguste Comte was careful to distinguish each major science with respect to method and object, speaking of mathematical philosophy, biological philosophy, sociological philosophy, and so forth. He thereby in a sense anticipated the regionalist turn: philosophical analysis should be carried out with respect to a specific body of knowledge. He also adopted a general perspective, a scientific philosophy. In the light of new discoveries, later thinkers such as Pierre Duhem, Gaston Milhaud, and Abel Rey endeavored to reformulate Comte’s doctrine as a neopositivism, a logical positivism, or an absolute positivism. The aim of this article is to examine the constitutive concepts mentioned and the controversies that hinge on them, in an effort to reach a precise understanding of the aim, scope, and import of philosophy of science in the context of nineteenth-century France.","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"81 1","pages":"428 - 445"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-06-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"72723690","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Stefano Bordoni. When Historiography Met Epistemology: Sophisticated Histories and Philosophies of Science in French-speaking Countries in the Second Half of the Nineteenth Century. Bordoni斯特凡诺。当史学遇到认识论:19世纪下半叶法语国家的复杂历史和科学哲学。
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2021-06-28 DOI: 10.1086/715580
W. Schmaus
{"title":"Stefano Bordoni. When Historiography Met Epistemology: Sophisticated Histories and Philosophies of Science in French-speaking Countries in the Second Half of the Nineteenth Century.","authors":"W. Schmaus","doi":"10.1086/715580","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/715580","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"57 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-06-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"87554585","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Poincaré, Le Roy, and the Nouveau positivisme poincare,勒罗伊和新实证主义
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2021-06-28 DOI: 10.1086/715880
M. Paz
Henri Poincaré’s philosophy of science has been widely studied and has been related to other important scientific and philosophical figures such as Einstein, Hilbert, Helmholtz, Duhem, and even Bergson. Poincaré refers to many people in his works, but there is one name that appears repeatedly in his texts, in particular when he develops his general views on the value of science. That is Édouard Le Roy. There is a lack of secondary sources on Le Roy’s work and, when compared to Poincaré, references are usually given to Poincaré’s interpretation of his works and not to Le Roy himself. When writing on the value of science, Poincaré structures his discourse as a reply to Le Roy’s views. This paper aims at clarifying why it was so important for Poincaré to reply to Le Roy. To do that, we will discuss the figure of Le Roy in the context of the time, his philosophy (which he called nouveau positivisme), and the relation between Poincaré’s philosophical position and Le Roy’s. This will make Le Roy’s work more familiar to contemporary audiences but will also clarify some controversial aspects in Poincaré’s position.
亨利·庞加莱的科学哲学得到了广泛的研究,并与其他重要的科学和哲学人物,如爱因斯坦、希尔伯特、亥姆霍兹、迪昂甚至柏格森联系在一起。庞加莱在他的作品中提到了很多人,但有一个名字在他的文本中反复出现,特别是当他发展他对科学价值的总体看法时。这是Édouard勒罗伊。勒罗伊的作品缺乏二手资料,当与庞卡莱相比时,参考文献通常是庞卡莱对他的作品的解释,而不是勒罗伊本人。在论述科学的价值时,庞加莱将他的论述作为对勒罗伊观点的回应。本文旨在阐明为什么庞加莱回复勒罗伊是如此重要。为此,我们将讨论勒罗伊在时代背景下的形象,他的哲学(他称之为新实证主义),以及庞加莱的哲学立场与勒罗伊的哲学立场之间的关系。这将使勒罗伊的作品更熟悉当代观众,但也将澄清一些有争议的方面,在庞加莱的立场。
{"title":"Poincaré, Le Roy, and the Nouveau positivisme","authors":"M. Paz","doi":"10.1086/715880","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/715880","url":null,"abstract":"Henri Poincaré’s philosophy of science has been widely studied and has been related to other important scientific and philosophical figures such as Einstein, Hilbert, Helmholtz, Duhem, and even Bergson. Poincaré refers to many people in his works, but there is one name that appears repeatedly in his texts, in particular when he develops his general views on the value of science. That is Édouard Le Roy. There is a lack of secondary sources on Le Roy’s work and, when compared to Poincaré, references are usually given to Poincaré’s interpretation of his works and not to Le Roy himself. When writing on the value of science, Poincaré structures his discourse as a reply to Le Roy’s views. This paper aims at clarifying why it was so important for Poincaré to reply to Le Roy. To do that, we will discuss the figure of Le Roy in the context of the time, his philosophy (which he called nouveau positivisme), and the relation between Poincaré’s philosophical position and Le Roy’s. This will make Le Roy’s work more familiar to contemporary audiences but will also clarify some controversial aspects in Poincaré’s position.","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"105 1","pages":"446 - 460"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-06-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"86962062","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Anne Conway’s Exceptional Vitalism: Material Spirits and Active Matter 安妮·康威的《非凡活力论:物质精神和活性物质》
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2021-06-28 DOI: 10.1086/715883
Doina‐Cristina Rusu
Anne Conway’s philosophy has been categorized as “vitalism,” “vital monism,” “spiritualism,” “monistic spiritualism,” “immaterial vitalism,” and “antimaterialism.” While there is no doubt that she is a monist and a vitalist, problems arise with the categories of “spiritualism,” “immaterial vitalism,” and “antimaterialism.” Conway conceives of created substances as gross and fixed spirit, or rarefied and volatile matter. While interpreters agree that Conway’s “spirit” shares characteristics traditionally attributed to matter (e.g., extension, divisibility, impenetrability), and that she is critical of Henry More’s immaterial spirit, Conway’s spirit is still conceived as an immaterial soul-like or mind-like entity. I argue that Conway’s vitalism is material, and is best understood in the tradition of Renaissance vital naturalism. First, Conway does not criticize materialism per se, only mechanical materialism, which characterizes matter as lifeless. Her vitalism has to be materialistic in some sense, since only God is an immaterial substance. Second, Conway’s conceptions of matter and spirit, the language she uses, and the fact that she attributes thinking to extended, divisible, and impenetrable substances all place her within the tradition of Renaissance vital naturalism, wherein Bernardino Telesio, Tommaso Campanella, and Francis Bacon used “spirit” to account for all natural processes.
安妮·康威的哲学被分为“生机论”、“生机一元论”、“唯灵论”、“一元论唯灵论”、“非物质生机论”和“反物质论”。虽然毫无疑问,她是一个一元论者和活力论者,但问题出现在“唯心论”、“非物质活力论”和“反物质论”的分类上。康威认为被创造的物质是粗糙而固定的精神,或者是稀薄而易挥发的物质。虽然诠释者同意康威的“精神”具有传统上归因于物质的特征(例如,延伸性、可分割性、不可穿透性),并且她对亨利·莫尔的非物质精神持批评态度,但康威的精神仍然被认为是一种非物质的类似灵魂或类似心灵的实体。我认为康威的生机论是物质性的,在文艺复兴时期生机自然主义的传统中最容易理解。首先,康威并没有批判唯物主义本身,而是批判机械唯物主义,这种唯物主义把物质描述为无生命的。她的生机论在某种意义上必须是唯物主义的,因为只有上帝是一种非物质的物质。其次,康威对物质和精神的概念,她使用的语言,以及她将思维归因于延伸的、可分割的、不可穿透的物质的事实,都使她处于文艺复兴时期重要自然主义的传统之中,其中贝纳迪诺·特雷西奥、托马索·坎帕内拉和弗朗西斯·培根都用“精神”来解释所有的自然过程。
{"title":"Anne Conway’s Exceptional Vitalism: Material Spirits and Active Matter","authors":"Doina‐Cristina Rusu","doi":"10.1086/715883","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/715883","url":null,"abstract":"Anne Conway’s philosophy has been categorized as “vitalism,” “vital monism,” “spiritualism,” “monistic spiritualism,” “immaterial vitalism,” and “antimaterialism.” While there is no doubt that she is a monist and a vitalist, problems arise with the categories of “spiritualism,” “immaterial vitalism,” and “antimaterialism.” Conway conceives of created substances as gross and fixed spirit, or rarefied and volatile matter. While interpreters agree that Conway’s “spirit” shares characteristics traditionally attributed to matter (e.g., extension, divisibility, impenetrability), and that she is critical of Henry More’s immaterial spirit, Conway’s spirit is still conceived as an immaterial soul-like or mind-like entity. I argue that Conway’s vitalism is material, and is best understood in the tradition of Renaissance vital naturalism. First, Conway does not criticize materialism per se, only mechanical materialism, which characterizes matter as lifeless. Her vitalism has to be materialistic in some sense, since only God is an immaterial substance. Second, Conway’s conceptions of matter and spirit, the language she uses, and the fact that she attributes thinking to extended, divisible, and impenetrable substances all place her within the tradition of Renaissance vital naturalism, wherein Bernardino Telesio, Tommaso Campanella, and Francis Bacon used “spirit” to account for all natural processes.","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"20 1","pages":"528 - 546"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-06-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"85413872","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Soul, Archeus, and Nature in van Helmont’s Medical Naturalism 范赫尔蒙特医学自然主义中的灵魂、阿古斯和自然
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2021-06-28 DOI: 10.1086/715877
B. Demarest
Jan Baptist van Helmont’s development of the Paracelsian theory of the Archeus is often considered uncomfortably close to the animist theory that the specificity of organic bodies is largely due to the soul. In this paper, I argue that the historical assimilation of these two positions is mistaken. I show that van Helmont introduced his theory of the Archeus on the grounds that it guaranteed that natural processes are properly natural, and that his theory was driven by a specific conception of what it means for a process to be properly natural. I also argue that the specific way in which van Helmont developed his theory of the Archeus put him at odds with the more animist positions defended in his own time, and that he stressed rather than downplayed the efficacy of natural secondary causes. This analysis runs counter to both the long tradition of reading van Helmont’s theory as a species of animism, and the more recent tendency to stress those Christian dimensions of his thought that seem to imply the inefficacy of natural causes.
扬·浸礼会·范·赫尔蒙特发展的帕拉塞尔理论常被认为与万物有灵论接近得令人不安,万物有灵论认为有机身体的特殊性主要是由于灵魂。在本文中,我认为这两种立场的历史同化是错误的。我指出,范赫尔蒙特提出太古宙理论的理由是,它保证了自然过程是适当自然的,他的理论是由一个特定的概念所驱动的,即一个过程是适当自然的。我还认为,范赫尔蒙特发展他的太古神理论的具体方式,使他与他那个时代捍卫的更多万物有灵论者的立场不一致,他强调而不是淡化自然次要原因的功效。这种分析既违背了将范赫尔蒙特的理论视为万物有灵论的长期传统,也违背了最近强调他思想中基督教维度的趋势,这些维度似乎暗示了自然原因的无效。
{"title":"Soul, Archeus, and Nature in van Helmont’s Medical Naturalism","authors":"B. Demarest","doi":"10.1086/715877","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/715877","url":null,"abstract":"Jan Baptist van Helmont’s development of the Paracelsian theory of the Archeus is often considered uncomfortably close to the animist theory that the specificity of organic bodies is largely due to the soul. In this paper, I argue that the historical assimilation of these two positions is mistaken. I show that van Helmont introduced his theory of the Archeus on the grounds that it guaranteed that natural processes are properly natural, and that his theory was driven by a specific conception of what it means for a process to be properly natural. I also argue that the specific way in which van Helmont developed his theory of the Archeus put him at odds with the more animist positions defended in his own time, and that he stressed rather than downplayed the efficacy of natural secondary causes. This analysis runs counter to both the long tradition of reading van Helmont’s theory as a species of animism, and the more recent tendency to stress those Christian dimensions of his thought that seem to imply the inefficacy of natural causes.","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"26 1","pages":"564 - 584"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-06-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"82473122","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
The Life of the Thrice Sensitive, Rational and Wise Animate Matter: Cavendish’s Animism 三敏感、理性和智慧的生命:卡文迪许的万物有灵论
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2021-06-28 DOI: 10.1086/715872
Jonathan L. Shaheen
This paper explores Cavendish’s argument for what she calls “animate matter.” Her commitment to the ubiquity of animate matter, styled “Cavendish’s animism,” is presented as the conclusion of an inference to the best explanation of nature’s order. The reconstruction of Cavendish’s argument begins with an examination of the relationship between God’s creation of our world and the order produced through nature’s wise governance of her parts. Cavendish’s materialism and anti-atomism are presented as ingredients in her final account of God’s ordering of the world by making it a self-moving whole. On the present account of Cavendish’s metaphysics, this self-moving whole then freely produces the regular motions that constitute its ordering of itself, as a distinct ordering beyond God’s initial act of creating our world. The depth of Cavendish’s commitment to the animistic elements of her materialism—or in other words, the extent to which her system is genuinely animistic—is then considered.
本文探讨了卡文迪什关于她所谓的“有生命物质”的论点。她对无所不在的有生命物质的承诺,被称为“卡文迪许的万物有灵论”,作为对自然秩序的最佳解释的推论的结论。卡文迪什的论点的重建始于对上帝创造我们的世界与自然对其各部分的明智管理所产生的秩序之间关系的考察。卡文迪什的唯物主义和反原子论在她最后的叙述中被认为是上帝通过使世界成为一个自我运动的整体来安排世界的成分。在卡文迪什的形而上学中,这个自我运动的整体自由地产生了规则的运动,构成了它自己的秩序,作为一种独特的秩序,超越了上帝创造我们世界的最初行为。卡文迪什对她的唯物主义中万物有灵元素的承诺的深度——或者换句话说,她的体系真正是万物有灵的程度——随后被考虑。
{"title":"The Life of the Thrice Sensitive, Rational and Wise Animate Matter: Cavendish’s Animism","authors":"Jonathan L. Shaheen","doi":"10.1086/715872","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/715872","url":null,"abstract":"This paper explores Cavendish’s argument for what she calls “animate matter.” Her commitment to the ubiquity of animate matter, styled “Cavendish’s animism,” is presented as the conclusion of an inference to the best explanation of nature’s order. The reconstruction of Cavendish’s argument begins with an examination of the relationship between God’s creation of our world and the order produced through nature’s wise governance of her parts. Cavendish’s materialism and anti-atomism are presented as ingredients in her final account of God’s ordering of the world by making it a self-moving whole. On the present account of Cavendish’s metaphysics, this self-moving whole then freely produces the regular motions that constitute its ordering of itself, as a distinct ordering beyond God’s initial act of creating our world. The depth of Cavendish’s commitment to the animistic elements of her materialism—or in other words, the extent to which her system is genuinely animistic—is then considered.","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"116 1","pages":"621 - 641"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-06-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"87928928","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
期刊
HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1