首页 > 最新文献

POLIS最新文献

英文 中文
Tacitus’ Critique of Republicanism in His Germania 塔西佗在《日耳曼尼亚》中对共和主义的批判
3区 历史学 Pub Date : 2023-09-20 DOI: 10.1163/20512996-12340421
Thomas J.B. Cole
Abstract Although Tacitus began his writing career during the Principate at the end of the first century CE , the dominant approach to thinking about political life was still guided by Republicanism, a constellation of concepts from the mid-first century BCE Roman Republic. Republicanism held that there was only one type of monarchy and that it necessarily precluded libertas . Tacitus, who was living under different iterations of monopolistic power in the Principate, questions this tenet by examining various Germanic tribes. The Germania explores different types of monarchical arrangements, showing that monarchy is not a one-size-fits-all form and that there are significant political differences among the Germanic monarchies, some of which preserve libertas . In this examination, he highlights the inapplicability of Republicanism to a system as dynamic as the Principate.
虽然塔西佗的写作生涯始于公元一世纪末的元首制时期,但当时对政治生活的思考仍以共和主义为主导,共和主义是公元前一世纪中叶罗马共和国时期的一系列概念。共和主义认为只有一种君主政体,它必然排斥自由。塔西佗,生活在元首制的不同垄断权力下,通过研究不同的日耳曼部落,对这一信条提出了质疑。《日耳曼尼亚》探讨了不同类型的君主政体安排,表明君主政体并非一刀切的形式,日耳曼君主政体之间存在显著的政治差异,其中一些君主政体保留了自由。在这次考察中,他强调共和主义不适用于像元首制这样充满活力的制度。
{"title":"Tacitus’ Critique of Republicanism in His Germania","authors":"Thomas J.B. Cole","doi":"10.1163/20512996-12340421","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1163/20512996-12340421","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Although Tacitus began his writing career during the Principate at the end of the first century CE , the dominant approach to thinking about political life was still guided by Republicanism, a constellation of concepts from the mid-first century BCE Roman Republic. Republicanism held that there was only one type of monarchy and that it necessarily precluded libertas . Tacitus, who was living under different iterations of monopolistic power in the Principate, questions this tenet by examining various Germanic tribes. The Germania explores different types of monarchical arrangements, showing that monarchy is not a one-size-fits-all form and that there are significant political differences among the Germanic monarchies, some of which preserve libertas . In this examination, he highlights the inapplicability of Republicanism to a system as dynamic as the Principate.","PeriodicalId":43237,"journal":{"name":"POLIS","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"136378026","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Model of Voting in Cicero’s Best State 西塞罗最佳状态中的投票模式
IF 0.1 3区 历史学 Pub Date : 2023-04-25 DOI: 10.1163/20512996-12340410
S. McConnell
In the proposed law-code in De legibus there is a law that votes are to be known by the best citizens (the optimates) but free to the common people (the plebs) (3.10). This law, Cicero claims, grants ‘the appearance of liberty’ (libertatis species), preserves the authority (auctoritas) of the optimates, and promotes harmony between the classes (3.39). The law and the precise meaning of libertatis species remain opaque even with the lengthy commentary (3.33–39), and much scholarly debate and discussion has arisen as a result – most of it very critical of Cicero’s proposal and the arguments supporting it. This paper offers a fresh analysis of the voting law that is more charitable to Cicero. It unpacks the full details of the voting system that is developed in De legibus and sheds new light on developments in Cicero’s thinking about the best state.
在《论立法》(De legibus)中提出的法典中,有一条法律规定,最好的公民(the optimates)有权投票,但普通人(the plebs)可以自由投票(3.10)。西塞罗声称,这一法律赋予了“自由的表象”(libertatis species),维护了最优者的权威(auctoritas),并促进了阶级之间的和谐(3.39)。即使有冗长的评论(3.33-39),法律和自由物种的确切含义仍然是不透明的,因此出现了许多学术辩论和讨论——其中大多数对西塞罗的提议和支持它的论点非常批评。本文提供了一种对西塞罗更为仁慈的投票法的新分析。它揭示了《论立法》中发展起来的投票制度的全部细节,并为西塞罗关于最佳国家的思想的发展提供了新的线索。
{"title":"The Model of Voting in Cicero’s Best State","authors":"S. McConnell","doi":"10.1163/20512996-12340410","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1163/20512996-12340410","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000In the proposed law-code in De legibus there is a law that votes are to be known by the best citizens (the optimates) but free to the common people (the plebs) (3.10). This law, Cicero claims, grants ‘the appearance of liberty’ (libertatis species), preserves the authority (auctoritas) of the optimates, and promotes harmony between the classes (3.39). The law and the precise meaning of libertatis species remain opaque even with the lengthy commentary (3.33–39), and much scholarly debate and discussion has arisen as a result – most of it very critical of Cicero’s proposal and the arguments supporting it. This paper offers a fresh analysis of the voting law that is more charitable to Cicero. It unpacks the full details of the voting system that is developed in De legibus and sheds new light on developments in Cicero’s thinking about the best state.","PeriodicalId":43237,"journal":{"name":"POLIS","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2023-04-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"86913695","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Aristotle’s Understanding of Democratic Justice and His Distinction between Two Kinds of Equality: A Response 亚里士多德对民主正义的理解及其两种平等的区分:回应
IF 0.1 3区 历史学 Pub Date : 2023-04-25 DOI: 10.1163/20512996-12340405
M. Knoll
This short article is a response to Douglas Cairns, Mirko Canevaro, and Kleanthis Mantzouranis, who in Polis 39 (2022) explicitly criticize both of my previous interpretations of Aristotle’s view of democratic justice and of the relation of proportional and numerical equality. Against Cairns et al., I argue that there is no tension or contradiction between Aristotle’s statements on these two kinds of equality and on democratic justice. The paper suggests a new reading of Aristotle’s texts that strictly distinguishes between Aristotle’s own views and his references to ‘respected opinions’ (endoxa). It concludes that Aristotle consistently identifies democratic justice with ‘numerical’ or ‘arithmetic’ equality and not with proportional equality, which he usually identifies with equality ‘according to worth or merit’ (kat’ axian).
这篇短文是对Douglas Cairns, Mirko Canevaro和Kleanthis Mantzouranis的回应,他们在Polis 39(2022)中明确批评了我之前对亚里士多德民主正义观和比例与数量平等关系的解释。与凯恩斯等人的观点相反,我认为亚里士多德关于这两种平等的论述与关于民主正义的论述之间并不存在张力或矛盾。本文建议对亚里士多德的文本进行新的阅读,严格区分亚里士多德自己的观点和他对“尊重意见”的引用(endoxa)。它的结论是,亚里士多德始终将民主正义等同于“数字”或“算术”平等,而不是比例平等,他通常将比例平等等同于“根据价值或功绩”(kat ' axian)。
{"title":"Aristotle’s Understanding of Democratic Justice and His Distinction between Two Kinds of Equality: A Response","authors":"M. Knoll","doi":"10.1163/20512996-12340405","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1163/20512996-12340405","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000This short article is a response to Douglas Cairns, Mirko Canevaro, and Kleanthis Mantzouranis, who in Polis 39 (2022) explicitly criticize both of my previous interpretations of Aristotle’s view of democratic justice and of the relation of proportional and numerical equality. Against Cairns et al., I argue that there is no tension or contradiction between Aristotle’s statements on these two kinds of equality and on democratic justice. The paper suggests a new reading of Aristotle’s texts that strictly distinguishes between Aristotle’s own views and his references to ‘respected opinions’ (endoxa). It concludes that Aristotle consistently identifies democratic justice with ‘numerical’ or ‘arithmetic’ equality and not with proportional equality, which he usually identifies with equality ‘according to worth or merit’ (kat’ axian).","PeriodicalId":43237,"journal":{"name":"POLIS","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2023-04-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"86045222","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Difference Sexual Difference Makes in Aristotle’s Corpus 亚里士多德语料库中的性别差异
IF 0.1 3区 历史学 Pub Date : 2023-04-25 DOI: 10.1163/20512996-12340412
A. Trott
In Aristotle on Sexual Difference, Marguerite Deslauriers showcases the ways that the biological treatises invite consideration of major themes and debates in Aristotle scholarship: the relation of the theoretical to the practical texts, of the soul to the body, of eidos to morphē, of the status and operation of species form, of material’s ability to affect form, of the directionality of influence of the psychological and the physiological, of the structure of deliberation, the extent to which practical reason can be divided from choice and action, and more. Many scholars of Aristotle treat both Politics and Generation of Animals as minor works that shouldn’t be consulted for insight into the central questions of Aristotle’s corpus. This book makes the emphatic case that both texts are indeed fertile domains for investigating concerns that pervade his work – a case that Deslauriers supports with wide-ranging references including but not limited to Posterior Analytics, De Anima, Metaphysics, Nicomachean Ethics and Rhetoric. More than drawing together particular pieces of her reading of Aristotle’s view of sexual difference and its place in political life that she has made in other work (for example, that sexual difference is in the matter, not the form), Deslauriers argue for a coherent case of Aristotle’s treatment of female animals and of women citizens across his corpus. This monograph is the work of a scholar who has been thinking over these matters for decades, and it shows. The book is precise in its argumentation and its self-understanding of the stakes: to defend the importance of sexual difference for Aristotle. Deslauriers foresees objections and has replies grounded in specific passages that are not
在《亚里士多德论性别差异》一书中,玛格丽特·德斯劳里耶展示了生物学论文如何引发对亚里士多德学术中主要主题的思考和辩论:理论与实践文本的关系,灵魂与身体的关系,eidos与morphi的关系,物种形式的状态和运作,物质影响形式的能力,心理和生理影响的定向性,思考的结构,实践理性可以从选择和行动中分离的程度,等等。许多研究亚里士多德的学者都把《政治学》和《动物的产生》视为次要作品,不应该参考它们来深入了解亚里士多德文集的核心问题。这本书强调,这两个文本确实是研究他的作品中所涉及的问题的肥沃领域——德斯劳里耶用广泛的参考文献支持了这一观点,包括但不限于《后分析学》、《论阿尼玛》、《形而上学》、《尼各马可伦理学和修辞学》。Deslauriers不仅将她在其他作品中对亚里士多德关于性别差异及其在政治生活中的地位的观点(例如,性别差异是在问题上,而不是在形式上)的特定阅读片段集中在一起,还认为亚里士多德在他的文集中对雌性动物和女性公民的处理是连贯的。这本专著是一位学者的作品,他几十年来一直在思考这些问题,它表明。这本书在论证和对利害关系的自我理解上是精确的:为亚里士多德的性别差异的重要性辩护。德斯劳里耶预见到了反对意见,并根据一些具体的段落给出了回应
{"title":"The Difference Sexual Difference Makes in Aristotle’s Corpus","authors":"A. Trott","doi":"10.1163/20512996-12340412","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1163/20512996-12340412","url":null,"abstract":"In Aristotle on Sexual Difference, Marguerite Deslauriers showcases the ways that the biological treatises invite consideration of major themes and debates in Aristotle scholarship: the relation of the theoretical to the practical texts, of the soul to the body, of eidos to morphē, of the status and operation of species form, of material’s ability to affect form, of the directionality of influence of the psychological and the physiological, of the structure of deliberation, the extent to which practical reason can be divided from choice and action, and more. Many scholars of Aristotle treat both Politics and Generation of Animals as minor works that shouldn’t be consulted for insight into the central questions of Aristotle’s corpus. This book makes the emphatic case that both texts are indeed fertile domains for investigating concerns that pervade his work – a case that Deslauriers supports with wide-ranging references including but not limited to Posterior Analytics, De Anima, Metaphysics, Nicomachean Ethics and Rhetoric. More than drawing together particular pieces of her reading of Aristotle’s view of sexual difference and its place in political life that she has made in other work (for example, that sexual difference is in the matter, not the form), Deslauriers argue for a coherent case of Aristotle’s treatment of female animals and of women citizens across his corpus. This monograph is the work of a scholar who has been thinking over these matters for decades, and it shows. The book is precise in its argumentation and its self-understanding of the stakes: to defend the importance of sexual difference for Aristotle. Deslauriers foresees objections and has replies grounded in specific passages that are not","PeriodicalId":43237,"journal":{"name":"POLIS","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2023-04-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"87199997","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Did Platon (Politeia 571d) Believe That Every One of Us Is a Repressed Cannibal? 柏拉图(Politeia 571d)相信我们每个人都是被压抑的食人族吗?
IF 0.1 3区 历史学 Pub Date : 2023-04-25 DOI: 10.1163/20512996-12340406
Cătălin Enache
At the beginning of Book 9 of the Politeia (571cd), Platon suggests that all people bear in themselves unlawful desires like the desire to have sex with their own mother or with any other human, god, or beast, the desire to murder anyone, or the desire to eat anything. Modern scholars take it for granted that by the desire to eat anything, Platon means cannibalism. This view is based on the fact that Platon discusses unlawful desires in connection with the tyrannical man and that the tyrant is, elsewhere in the Politeia, twice connected with anthropophagy (at 8.565d–566a and 10.619c). This paper challenges this communis opinio and argues that we have no reason to assume that at Politeia 9.571d Platon claims that every one of us has the hidden desire to consume human flesh. Also, the alleged cannibalism of the Platonic tyrant is questioned. A close reading of the passages 8.565d–566a and 10.619c reveals that in the depiction of the tyrant Platon makes use of mythological motifs and literary topoi but never literally claims that the tyrant has cannibalistic desires.
在《Politeia》(571cd)第9卷的开头,柏拉图提出,所有的人都有非法的欲望,比如与自己的母亲或任何其他人、神或野兽发生性关系的欲望,谋杀任何人的欲望,或者吃任何东西的欲望。现代学者理所当然地认为,柏拉图所说的想吃任何东西的欲望意味着同类相食。这种观点是基于这样一个事实,即柏拉图讨论了与暴虐的人有关的非法欲望,而在《政治篇》的其他地方,暴君两次与食人有关(在8.565d-566a和10.619c)。本文对这一共产主义观点提出了挑战,认为我们没有理由认为柏拉图在Politeia 9.57 d上声称我们每个人都有吃人肉的隐藏欲望。此外,柏拉图式暴君的食人行为也受到质疑。仔细阅读8.565d-566a和10.619c段,可以发现柏拉图在描述暴君时使用了神话主题和文学主题,但从未真正声称暴君有同类相食的欲望。
{"title":"Did Platon (Politeia 571d) Believe That Every One of Us Is a Repressed Cannibal?","authors":"Cătălin Enache","doi":"10.1163/20512996-12340406","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1163/20512996-12340406","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000At the beginning of Book 9 of the Politeia (571cd), Platon suggests that all people bear in themselves unlawful desires like the desire to have sex with their own mother or with any other human, god, or beast, the desire to murder anyone, or the desire to eat anything. Modern scholars take it for granted that by the desire to eat anything, Platon means cannibalism. This view is based on the fact that Platon discusses unlawful desires in connection with the tyrannical man and that the tyrant is, elsewhere in the Politeia, twice connected with anthropophagy (at 8.565d–566a and 10.619c). This paper challenges this communis opinio and argues that we have no reason to assume that at Politeia 9.571d Platon claims that every one of us has the hidden desire to consume human flesh. Also, the alleged cannibalism of the Platonic tyrant is questioned. A close reading of the passages 8.565d–566a and 10.619c reveals that in the depiction of the tyrant Platon makes use of mythological motifs and literary topoi but never literally claims that the tyrant has cannibalistic desires.","PeriodicalId":43237,"journal":{"name":"POLIS","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2023-04-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"80286153","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Greed, Outrage, and Civil Conflict in Aristotle’s Politics 亚里士多德政治学中的贪婪、愤怒与国内冲突
IF 0.1 3区 历史学 Pub Date : 2023-04-25 DOI: 10.1163/20512996-12340404
Ryan K. Balot
Scholars generally agree that, according to Aristotle, factionalizers are motivated by a sense of injustice (the ‘first cause’) to redress imbalances in wealth and honor (the ‘second cause’). Recent discussions, however, have offered a misleading interpretation of Aristotle’s third cause, which he identifies as the origin of the factionalizers’ sense of injustice. It involves, most importantly, greed, hubris, and other factors such as fear and ‘disproportionate growth’. In conversation with a recent publication in Polis, this article restores the third cause to its proper place in Aristotle’s account. Abusive power holders, driven by greed, hubris, and overreaching, oppress their fellow citizens – following in the tradition of Homer’s Agamemnon, Hesiod’s basileis, and Solon’s aristocrats. These power holders prompt a sense of anger, indignation, and injustice in their fellow citizens, who ultimately form factions and take action on their own behalf.
学者们普遍认为,根据亚里士多德的观点,派系化者的动机是一种不公正感(“第一原因”),以纠正财富和荣誉的不平衡(“第二原因”)。然而,最近的讨论对亚里士多德的第三个原因提供了一种误导性的解释,他认为这是派系主义者不公正感的起源。最重要的是,它涉及到贪婪、傲慢和其他因素,如恐惧和“不成比例的增长”。在与《城邦》杂志最近发表的一篇文章的对话中,这篇文章将第三个原因恢复到亚里士多德的叙述中应有的位置。滥用权力的人,在贪婪、傲慢和越权的驱使下,压迫他们的同胞——遵循荷马的阿伽门农、赫西奥德的basileis和梭伦的贵族的传统。这些掌权者在他们的同胞中激起了愤怒、愤慨和不公正的感觉,他们最终形成了派系,并为自己的利益采取行动。
{"title":"Greed, Outrage, and Civil Conflict in Aristotle’s Politics","authors":"Ryan K. Balot","doi":"10.1163/20512996-12340404","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1163/20512996-12340404","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000Scholars generally agree that, according to Aristotle, factionalizers are motivated by a sense of injustice (the ‘first cause’) to redress imbalances in wealth and honor (the ‘second cause’). Recent discussions, however, have offered a misleading interpretation of Aristotle’s third cause, which he identifies as the origin of the factionalizers’ sense of injustice. It involves, most importantly, greed, hubris, and other factors such as fear and ‘disproportionate growth’. In conversation with a recent publication in Polis, this article restores the third cause to its proper place in Aristotle’s account. Abusive power holders, driven by greed, hubris, and overreaching, oppress their fellow citizens – following in the tradition of Homer’s Agamemnon, Hesiod’s basileis, and Solon’s aristocrats. These power holders prompt a sense of anger, indignation, and injustice in their fellow citizens, who ultimately form factions and take action on their own behalf.","PeriodicalId":43237,"journal":{"name":"POLIS","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2023-04-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"76116288","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
‘What’s in a Name?’ Ideology and Language in the Epistulae ad Caesarem “名字有什么关系?”《书信与凯撒》中的意识形态与语言
IF 0.1 3区 历史学 Pub Date : 2023-04-25 DOI: 10.1163/20512996-12340408
Héctor Paleo-Paz
The following paper offers a study on how contestation over the meaning of language forged the political ideology present in the second of the Epistulae ad Caesarem. ‘Ideology’ being a notoriously malleable concept, Michael Freeden’s theoretical approach is used to focus what it means, how it is manifested in the sources, and how it can be located and analysed. The political thought of the Late Republic is studied by examining the vocabulary contained in one of the disputed letters that Sallust addressed to Julius Caesar. Taking libertas as a case study of an ‘essentially contested concept’, the relation between language, meaning and ideology is dissected, outlining the morphological configuration that underlies the second Epistula. It is argued that the resulting array of political arguments is one iteration of what has been called popularis ideology.
本文主要研究语言意义之争是如何塑造了《书信与恺撒勒姆》第二篇中的政治意识形态的。“意识形态”是一个众所周知的具有可塑性的概念,迈克尔·弗里登的理论方法被用来关注它的含义,它如何在来源中表现出来,以及如何定位和分析它。晚期共和国的政治思想是通过检查萨罗斯特写给凯撒大帝的一封有争议的信件中包含的词汇来研究的。将自由作为“本质上有争议的概念”的案例研究,剖析语言,意义和意识形态之间的关系,概述第二篇书信的形态结构。有人认为,由此产生的一系列政治争论是所谓的“大众意识形态”的一种重复。
{"title":"‘What’s in a Name?’ Ideology and Language in the Epistulae ad Caesarem","authors":"Héctor Paleo-Paz","doi":"10.1163/20512996-12340408","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1163/20512996-12340408","url":null,"abstract":"The following paper offers a study on how contestation over the meaning of language forged the political ideology present in the second of the Epistulae ad Caesarem. ‘Ideology’ being a notoriously malleable concept, Michael Freeden’s theoretical approach is used to focus what it means, how it is manifested in the sources, and how it can be located and analysed. The political thought of the Late Republic is studied by examining the vocabulary contained in one of the disputed letters that Sallust addressed to Julius Caesar. Taking libertas as a case study of an ‘essentially contested concept’, the relation between language, meaning and ideology is dissected, outlining the morphological configuration that underlies the second Epistula. It is argued that the resulting array of political arguments is one iteration of what has been called popularis ideology.","PeriodicalId":43237,"journal":{"name":"POLIS","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2023-04-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"85851757","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Servile Stories and Contested Histories: Empire, Memory, and Criticism in Livy’s Ab Urbe Condita 卑贱的故事和有争议的历史:李维的《城市状况》中的帝国、记忆和批评
IF 0.1 3区 历史学 Pub Date : 2023-04-25 DOI: 10.1163/20512996-12340409
Max Lykins
Scholars often turn to Livy’s famous digression on Aulus Cossus and the spolia opima (4.17–20) to shed light on his larger political inclinations. These readings generally regard Livy as either an Augustan (or at least a patriotic Roman) or an apolitical skeptic. Yet neither view, I argue, fully explains the Cossus affair. What is needed is an interpretation that recognizes the political nature of the Cossus digression and its skepticism toward Augustus. Attending to Livy’s rhetorical strategy in the digression allows us to see it as an instance of oblique criticism of Augustus and his control over Roman life. The explanatory power of this reading extends to episodes from the life of Romulus as well. I argue Livy uses these stories to make a theoretical argument about the nature of despotism, namely, that it seeks to control narratives of the past just as much as it aims for political domination.
学者们经常求助于李维关于奥勒斯·科苏斯和斯普利亚·奥普马(4.17-20)的著名题外话,以揭示他更大的政治倾向。这些解读通常认为李维要么是奥古斯都(或者至少是一个爱国的罗马人),要么是一个不关心政治的怀疑论者。然而,我认为,这两种观点都不能完全解释科苏斯事件。我们需要的是一种解释,承认科苏斯的离题及其对奥古斯都的怀疑的政治本质。注意到李维在题外话中的修辞策略,我们可以把它看作是对奥古斯都及其对罗马生活的控制的间接批评。这种解读的解释力也延伸到了罗穆卢斯生活中的片段。我认为李维用这些故事来做一个关于专制本质的理论论证,也就是说,它试图控制对过去的叙述,就像它的目标是政治统治一样。
{"title":"Servile Stories and Contested Histories: Empire, Memory, and Criticism in Livy’s Ab Urbe Condita","authors":"Max Lykins","doi":"10.1163/20512996-12340409","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1163/20512996-12340409","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000Scholars often turn to Livy’s famous digression on Aulus Cossus and the spolia opima (4.17–20) to shed light on his larger political inclinations. These readings generally regard Livy as either an Augustan (or at least a patriotic Roman) or an apolitical skeptic. Yet neither view, I argue, fully explains the Cossus affair. What is needed is an interpretation that recognizes the political nature of the Cossus digression and its skepticism toward Augustus. Attending to Livy’s rhetorical strategy in the digression allows us to see it as an instance of oblique criticism of Augustus and his control over Roman life. The explanatory power of this reading extends to episodes from the life of Romulus as well. I argue Livy uses these stories to make a theoretical argument about the nature of despotism, namely, that it seeks to control narratives of the past just as much as it aims for political domination.","PeriodicalId":43237,"journal":{"name":"POLIS","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2023-04-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"73649416","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Introduction: The Causes of Stasis in Aristotle’s Politics: Critical Responses to Cairns, Canevaro, and Mantzouranis 引言:亚里士多德政治学停滞的原因:对凯恩斯、卡纳瓦罗和曼祖拉尼斯的批判回应
IF 0.1 3区 历史学 Pub Date : 2023-04-25 DOI: 10.1163/20512996-12340403
T. Lockwood
{"title":"Introduction: The Causes of Stasis in Aristotle’s Politics: Critical Responses to Cairns, Canevaro, and Mantzouranis","authors":"T. Lockwood","doi":"10.1163/20512996-12340403","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1163/20512996-12340403","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":43237,"journal":{"name":"POLIS","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2023-04-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"84608120","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Tyranny in Tragedy 悲剧中的暴政
IF 0.1 3区 历史学 Pub Date : 2023-04-25 DOI: 10.1163/20512996-12340407
Edmund Stewart
The meaning of the word tyrannos in Greek tragedy is much debated. Some have assumed that the word is always a neutral term signifying ‘ruler’ alone. Others argue for competing ideologies regarding tyranny: the result of an evolution in thinking on autocracy. This article challenges both of these assumptions. The negative meaning of tyrannos is always latent in tragedy, even where the word is used objectively and not as a term of abuse. Tyrannos does not simply indicate a powerful individual but implies absolute power, fortune and wealth. This absolute power leads to ruin and tyrannical vice. Tyrannos signifies not a bad or illegitimate ruler, but rather one with the potential to develop such characteristics. It is the tyrant who evolves, whereas Greek conceptions of tyranny remain largely unchanged from at least the time of Aeschylus to that of Aristotle.
在希腊悲剧中,“僭主”一词的含义一直备受争议。有些人认为这个词一直是一个中性词,仅表示“统治者”。另一些人则争论关于暴政的竞争意识形态:这是对专制思想演变的结果。本文挑战了这两种假设。tyrannos的负面含义总是潜藏在悲剧中,即使这个词是客观地使用的,而不是作为一个辱骂的术语。Tyrannos不仅仅指强大的个人,还意味着绝对的权力、财富和财富。这种绝对的权力导致毁灭和残暴的恶习。泰拉诺斯并不意味着一个坏的或非法的统治者,而是一个有可能发展出这些特征的人。是暴君在演变,而希腊人对暴政的观念,至少从埃斯库罗斯时代到亚里士多德时代,基本上没有改变。
{"title":"Tyranny in Tragedy","authors":"Edmund Stewart","doi":"10.1163/20512996-12340407","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1163/20512996-12340407","url":null,"abstract":"\u0000The meaning of the word tyrannos in Greek tragedy is much debated. Some have assumed that the word is always a neutral term signifying ‘ruler’ alone. Others argue for competing ideologies regarding tyranny: the result of an evolution in thinking on autocracy. This article challenges both of these assumptions. The negative meaning of tyrannos is always latent in tragedy, even where the word is used objectively and not as a term of abuse. Tyrannos does not simply indicate a powerful individual but implies absolute power, fortune and wealth. This absolute power leads to ruin and tyrannical vice. Tyrannos signifies not a bad or illegitimate ruler, but rather one with the potential to develop such characteristics. It is the tyrant who evolves, whereas Greek conceptions of tyranny remain largely unchanged from at least the time of Aeschylus to that of Aristotle.","PeriodicalId":43237,"journal":{"name":"POLIS","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.1,"publicationDate":"2023-04-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"82723194","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
POLIS
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1