首页 > 最新文献

Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy最新文献

英文 中文
Private Property and the Politics of Environmental Protection 私有财产与环境保护政治
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2004-09-22 DOI: 10.7916/D80001R9
T. Merrill
Private property plays two opposing roles in stories about the environment. In the story favored by most environmentalists, private property is the bad guy. (1) It balkanizes an interconnected ecosystem into artificial units of individual ownership. Owners of these finite parcels have little incentive to invest in ecosystem resources and every incentive to dump polluting wastes onto other parcels. Only by relocating control over natural resources in some central authority like the federal government, can we make integrated decisions designed to preserve the health of the entire ecosystem. For these traditional environmentalists, private property is the problem; public control is the solution. There is a counter story, told by the proponents of what is sometimes called free market environmentalism. (2) In this story, private property is the good guy. Environmental degradation is a problem because of incomplete property rights. If all resources were privately owned, then no one would be able to impose externalities on anyone else; potential polluters would have to purchase the right to pollute first. Similarly, if all resources--including habitats of endangered species and other ecologically sensitive resources--were privately owned, then owners would have incentives to invest in the preservation of these resources, and would use their ingenuity to get persons who care about environmental protection to pay for it. For free market environmentalists, public control of resources is the problem; private property is the solution. Both sides in this debate are only half right. The traditional environmentalists are closer to the mark in their diagnosis of the problem. Property rights are always and inevitably incomplete, as it is costly to set up and enforce any system of private property. Because property rights are incomplete, owners of resources that are subject to private ownership--such as parcels of land devoted to productive uses--will always have incentives to disregard the costs they impose on common resources that are not subject to private ownership. Sometimes creating new types of property rights can help the situation; more often, however, the only cost-effective solution to these sorts of spillovers is government regulation. On the other hand, the free market environmentalists are closer to the mark in devising a solution to the problem. Missing from the traditional account is any credible theory of how we can generate collective action to protect sensitive ecosystem resources. Bursts of collective altruism do happen, but they are difficult to sustain. Witness the history of socialism, or, more pertinently the history of environmentalism. (3) What is needed is an institutional arrangement that generates private incentives supporting collective action that will protect the environment. The best such arrangement is the widespread private ownership of land. In this sense, the free market environmentalists are closer to the mark in their prescri
私有财产在关于环境的故事中扮演着两个相反的角色。在大多数环保主义者青睐的故事中,私有财产是坏人。(1)它将一个相互关联的生态系统分割成个人所有权的人工单位。这些有限地块的所有者几乎没有动力投资生态系统资源,却有动力将污染废物倾倒到其他地块上。只有将自然资源的控制权移交给联邦政府等中央机构,我们才能做出综合决策,保护整个生态系统的健康。对于这些传统的环保主义者来说,私有财产是问题所在;公众控制是解决办法。有时被称为自由市场环境保护主义的支持者讲述了一个相反的故事。在这个故事中,私有财产是好人。由于产权不完全,环境恶化成为一个问题。如果所有的资源都是私有的,那么没有人能够把外部性强加给其他人;潜在的污染者必须首先购买污染权。同样,如果所有的资源——包括濒危物种的栖息地和其他生态敏感资源——都是私人所有,那么所有者就会有动力投资于这些资源的保护,并会利用他们的聪明才智让关心环境保护的人为此买单。对于自由市场的环保主义者来说,资源的公共控制是问题所在;私有财产是解决办法。这场辩论双方都只说对了一半。传统的环保主义者对这个问题的诊断更接近事实。财产权总是而且不可避免地是不完整的,因为建立和执行任何私有财产制度都是代价高昂的。由于产权是不完整的,属于私有制的资源——比如用于生产的小块土地——的所有者总是有动机无视它们对不属于私有制的公共资源造成的成本。有时,创造新型产权可以帮助解决问题;然而,更多情况下,应对此类溢出效应的唯一具有成本效益的解决方案是政府监管。另一方面,主张自由市场的环保主义者在设计解决问题的办法方面更接近目标。传统的解释中缺少任何关于我们如何采取集体行动来保护敏感生态系统资源的可信理论。集体利他主义的爆发确实会发生,但它们很难维持下去。看看社会主义的历史,或者更确切地说,看看环境保护主义的历史。(3)所需要的是一种制度安排,产生私人激励,支持保护环境的集体行动。这种最好的安排是广泛的土地私有制。从这个意义上说,自由市场的环保主义者比传统的环保主义者更接近他们的治疗方法,他们呼吁一个更大的政府。偶然的经验主义强烈地表明私有财产有利于环境。20世纪80年代的东欧提供了一种关于不同财产制度影响的自然实验。从波罗的海到地中海,一道铁幕横贯东欧。在西线,不动产主要属于私人所有。在这条线的东边,不动产归国家所有。结果是显而易见的:西侧的城镇和村庄通常整洁干净,街道擦得干干净净,窗户上挂着五颜六色的花箱,而东侧的城镇和村庄则单调肮脏,墙上的灰泥掉了下来,到处都看不到花。这些成对的社区通常由相同年代和建筑风格的建筑组成,并由具有相同种族背景和文化传统的家庭居住。…
{"title":"Private Property and the Politics of Environmental Protection","authors":"T. Merrill","doi":"10.7916/D80001R9","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.7916/D80001R9","url":null,"abstract":"Private property plays two opposing roles in stories about the environment. In the story favored by most environmentalists, private property is the bad guy. (1) It balkanizes an interconnected ecosystem into artificial units of individual ownership. Owners of these finite parcels have little incentive to invest in ecosystem resources and every incentive to dump polluting wastes onto other parcels. Only by relocating control over natural resources in some central authority like the federal government, can we make integrated decisions designed to preserve the health of the entire ecosystem. For these traditional environmentalists, private property is the problem; public control is the solution. There is a counter story, told by the proponents of what is sometimes called free market environmentalism. (2) In this story, private property is the good guy. Environmental degradation is a problem because of incomplete property rights. If all resources were privately owned, then no one would be able to impose externalities on anyone else; potential polluters would have to purchase the right to pollute first. Similarly, if all resources--including habitats of endangered species and other ecologically sensitive resources--were privately owned, then owners would have incentives to invest in the preservation of these resources, and would use their ingenuity to get persons who care about environmental protection to pay for it. For free market environmentalists, public control of resources is the problem; private property is the solution. Both sides in this debate are only half right. The traditional environmentalists are closer to the mark in their diagnosis of the problem. Property rights are always and inevitably incomplete, as it is costly to set up and enforce any system of private property. Because property rights are incomplete, owners of resources that are subject to private ownership--such as parcels of land devoted to productive uses--will always have incentives to disregard the costs they impose on common resources that are not subject to private ownership. Sometimes creating new types of property rights can help the situation; more often, however, the only cost-effective solution to these sorts of spillovers is government regulation. On the other hand, the free market environmentalists are closer to the mark in devising a solution to the problem. Missing from the traditional account is any credible theory of how we can generate collective action to protect sensitive ecosystem resources. Bursts of collective altruism do happen, but they are difficult to sustain. Witness the history of socialism, or, more pertinently the history of environmentalism. (3) What is needed is an institutional arrangement that generates private incentives supporting collective action that will protect the environment. The best such arrangement is the widespread private ownership of land. In this sense, the free market environmentalists are closer to the mark in their prescri","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2004-09-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71363580","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
The Quasi War Cases—And Their Relevance to Whether Letters of Marque and Reprisal Constrain Presidential War Powers 准战争案件——以及它们与商标函和报复是否限制总统战争权力的关系
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2004-08-17 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.577264
J. Sidak
Constitutional scholars cite three Supreme Court decisions arising from the undeclared Quasi War with France in 1798-1800 as support for the proposition that Congress may authorize war of any magnitude, and that, except in case of sudden or imminent attack on the United States, this congressional authority displaces any right of the President to use military force of even modest magnitude without prior congressional authorization. The textual hook claimed by these scholars for so reading Bas v. Tingy, Talbot v. Seeman, and Little v. Bareme is the phrase in Article I, section 8 of the Constitution that immediately follows the grant to Congress of the power To declare War - namely, the power to grant Letters of Marque and Reprisal, and make Rules concerning Captures on Land and Water. These additional words, it is argued, enable Congress to regulate the President's ability to use military force in a manner short of full-scale war. This prevailing interpretation of the Quasi War cases is incorrect and has special significance because the U.S. Court of Appeals for the District of Columbia Circuit gave it credence in 2000 in the war powers case Campbell v. Clinton and because one or more of the cases continues to be cited in litigation concerning the current war on terror.
宪法学者引用最高法院关于1798-1800年与法国未宣战的准战争的三个裁决,作为对下述主张的支持:国会可授权任何规模的战争,而且,除了对美国的突然或迫在眉睫的攻击之外,国会的权力取代了总统在未经国会事先授权的情况下使用军事力量的任何权利,即使是适度的规模。这些学者如此解读巴斯诉廷蒂案、塔尔博特诉西曼案和利特尔诉巴雷姆案时所声称的文本hook是宪法第一条第8款中的一句话,紧接在授予国会宣战权之后,即授予国会颁发“封杀令”和“报复令”的权力,以及制定有关陆地和水上俘虏的规则。有人认为,这些额外的词语使国会能够规范总统以一种非全面战争的方式使用军事力量的能力。这种对准战争案件的普遍解释是不正确的,而且具有特殊的意义,因为美国哥伦比亚特区巡回上诉法院在2000年的坎贝尔诉克林顿战争权力案中给予了它的信任,而且因为其中一个或多个案件继续在有关当前反恐战争的诉讼中被引用。
{"title":"The Quasi War Cases—And Their Relevance to Whether Letters of Marque and Reprisal Constrain Presidential War Powers","authors":"J. Sidak","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.577264","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.577264","url":null,"abstract":"Constitutional scholars cite three Supreme Court decisions arising from the undeclared Quasi War with France in 1798-1800 as support for the proposition that Congress may authorize war of any magnitude, and that, except in case of sudden or imminent attack on the United States, this congressional authority displaces any right of the President to use military force of even modest magnitude without prior congressional authorization. The textual hook claimed by these scholars for so reading Bas v. Tingy, Talbot v. Seeman, and Little v. Bareme is the phrase in Article I, section 8 of the Constitution that immediately follows the grant to Congress of the power To declare War - namely, the power to grant Letters of Marque and Reprisal, and make Rules concerning Captures on Land and Water. These additional words, it is argued, enable Congress to regulate the President's ability to use military force in a manner short of full-scale war. This prevailing interpretation of the Quasi War cases is incorrect and has special significance because the U.S. Court of Appeals for the District of Columbia Circuit gave it credence in 2000 in the war powers case Campbell v. Clinton and because one or more of the cases continues to be cited in litigation concerning the current war on terror.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2004-08-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67767463","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 5
Social Welfare, Human Dignity, and the Puzzle of What We Owe Each Other 社会福利,人类尊严,以及我们对彼此亏欠的困惑
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2003-12-12 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.478561
Amy Wax
Proponents of work-based welfare reform claim that moving the poor from welfare to work will advance the goals of economic self-reliance and independence. Reform opponents attack these objectives as ideologically motivated and conceptually incoherent. Drawing on perspectives developed by luck egalitarians and feminist theorists, these critics disparage conventional notions of economic desert, find fault with market measures of value, debunk ideals of autonomy, and emphasize the pervasiveness of interdependence and unearned benefits within free market societies. These arguments pose an important challenge to justifications usually advanced for work-based welfare reform. Reform proponents must concede that no member of society can hope to achieve complete personal and economic independence from others. Rather, self-reliance and dependency are always a matter of kind and degree. These states must be understood as having a "social meaning" that does not rest on conceptually pure absolutes, but rather on the fulfillment of normative expectations regarding conduct and participation in social and economic life. Within this framework, the fact that self-reliance can never be complete does not undermine its worth or importance as a goal. That dependency is sometimes unavoidable or even desirable does not mean that it should be indulged or accepted in all cases. How might welfare reform advocates construct more effective arguments for minimizing dependency and fostering self-sufficiency among the poor? One approach would look to the distinctions ordinary people make between constructive citizenship and social parasitism. The challenge is to give the idea of constructive citizenship definite and rigorous content - content that serves as a useful guide to wise policy and that makes work-based reform less vulnerable to attack on theoretical grounds. The paper explains how the concept of conditional reciprocity, as it informs common notions of acceptable redistribution, can help achieve this goal.
以工作为基础的福利改革的支持者声称,将穷人从福利转移到工作将促进经济自力更生和独立的目标。反对改革的人抨击这些目标是出于意识形态动机,在概念上不连贯。根据运气平等主义者和女权主义理论家的观点,这些批评家贬低了传统的经济沙漠观念,发现了市场价值衡量的错误,揭穿了自主的理想,并强调了自由市场社会中普遍存在的相互依存和不劳而获的利益。这些论点对通常提出的以工作为基础的福利改革的理由提出了重要挑战。改革支持者必须承认,没有一个社会成员能够指望实现完全的个人和经济独立于他人。相反,自力更生和依赖总是一个种类和程度的问题。这些国家必须被理解为具有“社会意义”,它不依赖于概念上的纯粹绝对,而是依赖于对社会和经济生活中的行为和参与的规范期望的实现。在这个框架内,自力更生永远不可能完全这一事实并不会削弱其作为一个目标的价值或重要性。依赖有时是不可避免的,甚至是可取的,但这并不意味着在所有情况下都应该纵容或接受依赖。福利改革的倡导者如何构建更有效的论据来减少对穷人的依赖并促进他们的自给自足?一种方法将着眼于普通人对建设性公民和社会寄生的区别。我们面临的挑战是为建设性公民身份的概念赋予明确而严谨的内容——这些内容可以作为明智政策的有用指南,并使基于工作的改革不那么容易受到理论依据的攻击。这篇论文解释了条件互惠的概念是如何帮助实现这一目标的,因为它告诉了可接受的再分配的共同概念。
{"title":"Social Welfare, Human Dignity, and the Puzzle of What We Owe Each Other","authors":"Amy Wax","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.478561","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.478561","url":null,"abstract":"Proponents of work-based welfare reform claim that moving the poor from welfare to work will advance the goals of economic self-reliance and independence. Reform opponents attack these objectives as ideologically motivated and conceptually incoherent. Drawing on perspectives developed by luck egalitarians and feminist theorists, these critics disparage conventional notions of economic desert, find fault with market measures of value, debunk ideals of autonomy, and emphasize the pervasiveness of interdependence and unearned benefits within free market societies. These arguments pose an important challenge to justifications usually advanced for work-based welfare reform. Reform proponents must concede that no member of society can hope to achieve complete personal and economic independence from others. Rather, self-reliance and dependency are always a matter of kind and degree. These states must be understood as having a \"social meaning\" that does not rest on conceptually pure absolutes, but rather on the fulfillment of normative expectations regarding conduct and participation in social and economic life. Within this framework, the fact that self-reliance can never be complete does not undermine its worth or importance as a goal. That dependency is sometimes unavoidable or even desirable does not mean that it should be indulged or accepted in all cases. How might welfare reform advocates construct more effective arguments for minimizing dependency and fostering self-sufficiency among the poor? One approach would look to the distinctions ordinary people make between constructive citizenship and social parasitism. The challenge is to give the idea of constructive citizenship definite and rigorous content - content that serves as a useful guide to wise policy and that makes work-based reform less vulnerable to attack on theoretical grounds. The paper explains how the concept of conditional reciprocity, as it informs common notions of acceptable redistribution, can help achieve this goal.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2003-12-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67745956","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 9
Stopping Time: The Pro-Slavery and 'Irrevocable' Thirteenth Amendment 停止时间:支持奴隶制和“不可撤销”的第十三修正案
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2003-11-18 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.467280
Christopher Bryant
In the post-secession winter of 1861, both Houses of Congress approved a proposed thirteenth amendment to the U.S. Constitution. Three northern States even ratified the proposal before the Civil War intervened. That version of the thirteenth amendment, introduced in the House by Representative Thomas Corwin of Ohio, purported to prohibit any future amendment granting Congress power to interfere with slavery in the States. The Congressional Globe volumes for the winter 1861 legislative session include rich debates about whether the amending power could be used to limit future exercise of that same authority. Those forgotten debates offer significant insights for modern controversies about the exclusivity of, and limitations on, the extraordinary power granted in Article V of the U.S. Constitution. Recent years have witnessed an outpouring of academic writing on the amending power. Salient examples of this scholarship are the works of Yale Law School Professors Bruce Ackerman and Akhil Amar, who have raised distinct challenges to the claim that Article V constitutes the sole legitimate means for constitutional revision. Their imaginative and controversial work has in turn prompted vigorous debate among constitutional scholars, political scientists, and historians about the role Article V can and should play in our constitutional order. As voluminous as the recent Article V scholarship has been, at least one fundamental question has gone virtually unnoticed: what, if anything, prevents or limits the use of Article V to make procedural or substantive changes to the amending power itself? This question, which presents problems of the greatest theoretical difficulty, was posed starkly by Mr. Corwin's 1861 proposal. This article uses that Civil War-era proposal as a lens through which to study the tension between the claim that Article V articulates the exclusive procedure by which the Constitution may be amended and our nation's historical commitment to the ideal that the people are sovereign. Revisiting the long-forgotten Corwin Amendment illuminates current debates about the legal and political theory by which the U.S. Constitution can set forth the sole means for its revision. By understanding why the Corwin Amendment would have failed in its stated purpose (because a subsequent Article V amendment would have been sufficient to repeal it and grant Congress power over slavery), we discover certain fundamental constitutional principles. Those principles, important in their own right, also raise novel questions concerning the contemporary claims of Professors Ackerman and Amar that Article V cannot be the exclusive procedure for legitimate constitutional change.
1861年的冬天,美国脱离联邦后,国会参众两院通过了美国宪法第13条修正案。三个北方州甚至在内战爆发前就批准了这项提案。由俄亥俄州众议员托马斯·考文(Thomas Corwin)在众议院提出的第十三号修正案,意在禁止未来任何赋予国会干预美国奴隶制权力的修正案。1861年冬季立法会议的《国会环球报》包含了关于修改权是否可以用来限制未来行使同一权力的丰富辩论。这些被遗忘的辩论为现代关于美国宪法第五条赋予的非凡权力的排他性和限制的争论提供了重要的见解。近年来,关于修正权的学术著述层出不穷。耶鲁大学法学院教授Bruce Ackerman和Akhil Amar的著作是这种学术研究的突出例子,他们对宪法第五条是修改宪法的唯一合法手段的说法提出了截然不同的挑战。他们富有想象力和争议的工作反过来又引发了宪法学者、政治科学家和历史学家之间关于宪法第五条在我们的宪法秩序中能够和应该发挥的作用的激烈辩论。尽管最近关于宪法第五条的研究大量涌现,但至少有一个基本问题几乎没有被人注意到:是什么(如果有的话)阻止或限制了对宪法第五条的使用,对修正案本身进行程序性或实质性的改变?柯文先生在1861年的提案中赤裸裸地提出了这个问题,这是理论上最困难的问题。本文以内战时期的提案为视角,研究宪法第五条规定了宪法修改的排他性程序与我国对人民拥有主权这一理想的历史承诺之间的紧张关系。重新审视被遗忘已久的《考文修正案》(Corwin Amendment)阐明了当前关于法律和政治理论的争论,根据这些理论,美国宪法可以规定其修改的唯一途径。通过理解为什么《考文修正案》未能实现其既定的目的(因为随后的第五条修正案足以废除它,并赋予国会对奴隶制的权力),我们发现了某些基本的宪法原则。这些原则本身就很重要,但也对阿克曼教授和阿马尔教授的当代主张提出了新的问题,即第五条不能成为合法修改宪法的唯一程序。
{"title":"Stopping Time: The Pro-Slavery and 'Irrevocable' Thirteenth Amendment","authors":"Christopher Bryant","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.467280","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.467280","url":null,"abstract":"In the post-secession winter of 1861, both Houses of Congress approved a proposed thirteenth amendment to the U.S. Constitution. Three northern States even ratified the proposal before the Civil War intervened. That version of the thirteenth amendment, introduced in the House by Representative Thomas Corwin of Ohio, purported to prohibit any future amendment granting Congress power to interfere with slavery in the States. The Congressional Globe volumes for the winter 1861 legislative session include rich debates about whether the amending power could be used to limit future exercise of that same authority. Those forgotten debates offer significant insights for modern controversies about the exclusivity of, and limitations on, the extraordinary power granted in Article V of the U.S. Constitution. Recent years have witnessed an outpouring of academic writing on the amending power. Salient examples of this scholarship are the works of Yale Law School Professors Bruce Ackerman and Akhil Amar, who have raised distinct challenges to the claim that Article V constitutes the sole legitimate means for constitutional revision. Their imaginative and controversial work has in turn prompted vigorous debate among constitutional scholars, political scientists, and historians about the role Article V can and should play in our constitutional order. As voluminous as the recent Article V scholarship has been, at least one fundamental question has gone virtually unnoticed: what, if anything, prevents or limits the use of Article V to make procedural or substantive changes to the amending power itself? This question, which presents problems of the greatest theoretical difficulty, was posed starkly by Mr. Corwin's 1861 proposal. This article uses that Civil War-era proposal as a lens through which to study the tension between the claim that Article V articulates the exclusive procedure by which the Constitution may be amended and our nation's historical commitment to the ideal that the people are sovereign. Revisiting the long-forgotten Corwin Amendment illuminates current debates about the legal and political theory by which the U.S. Constitution can set forth the sole means for its revision. By understanding why the Corwin Amendment would have failed in its stated purpose (because a subsequent Article V amendment would have been sufficient to repeal it and grant Congress power over slavery), we discover certain fundamental constitutional principles. Those principles, important in their own right, also raise novel questions concerning the contemporary claims of Professors Ackerman and Amar that Article V cannot be the exclusive procedure for legitimate constitutional change.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2003-11-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.467280","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67742364","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 6
The Proliferation of Legal Truth 法律真相的扩散
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2003-02-28 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.383400
J. Balkin
This essay describes an important aspect of law's power. Law has power not only because it sets prices and sanctions on behavior, but also because it shapes and colonizes human understanding. Through the creation of legal categories, distinctions, causes of action, institutions and devices, law is continuously proliferating legal truths into the world, making things true and false in the eyes of the law. This capacity to create truth and to make things real is the flip side of law's power. Law has power because it can make things true or false in ways that matter to us; conversely, law can make things true or false in ways that matter to us because it has power over us. The proliferation of legal truth is important for three reasons. First, the proliferation of legal truth shapes, directs, and constrains how people live their lives. Second, the proliferation of legal truth colonizes human imagination, shaping people's beliefs and their understandings about social reality. Third, the proliferation of legal truth is important because truth in the eyes of the law is not the only truth, and the way the world looks to law is not the only reality. Law's power to enforce its vision of the world can clash and conflict with other practices of knowledge, like medicine or psychology, and with other forms of truth, like historical or scientific truth.
本文描述了法律权力的一个重要方面。法律之所以有力量,不仅是因为它规定了行为的价格和制裁,还因为它塑造和殖民了人类的理解。通过创造法律类别、区别、行为原因、制度和手段,法律不断地将法律真理扩散到世界上,使法律眼中的事物变得真实和虚假。这种创造真理和使事情成为现实的能力是法律权力的另一面。法律具有力量,因为它可以以对我们重要的方式使事情成真或成真;相反,法律可以以对我们重要的方式使事情成真或成真,因为它对我们有权力。法律真相的扩散之所以重要,有三个原因。首先,法律真相的扩散塑造、指导并限制了人们的生活方式。其次,法律真理的泛滥殖民了人类的想象,塑造了人们的信仰和对社会现实的理解。第三,法律真相的扩散很重要,因为法律眼中的真相并不是唯一的真相,世界看待法律的方式也不是唯一的现实。法律执行其世界观的力量可能与其他知识实践(如医学或心理学)以及其他形式的真理(如历史或科学真理)发生冲突和冲突。
{"title":"The Proliferation of Legal Truth","authors":"J. Balkin","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.383400","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.383400","url":null,"abstract":"This essay describes an important aspect of law's power. Law has power not only because it sets prices and sanctions on behavior, but also because it shapes and colonizes human understanding. Through the creation of legal categories, distinctions, causes of action, institutions and devices, law is continuously proliferating legal truths into the world, making things true and false in the eyes of the law. This capacity to create truth and to make things real is the flip side of law's power. Law has power because it can make things true or false in ways that matter to us; conversely, law can make things true or false in ways that matter to us because it has power over us. The proliferation of legal truth is important for three reasons. First, the proliferation of legal truth shapes, directs, and constrains how people live their lives. Second, the proliferation of legal truth colonizes human imagination, shaping people's beliefs and their understandings about social reality. Third, the proliferation of legal truth is important because truth in the eyes of the law is not the only truth, and the way the world looks to law is not the only reality. Law's power to enforce its vision of the world can clash and conflict with other practices of knowledge, like medicine or psychology, and with other forms of truth, like historical or scientific truth.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2003-02-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68654753","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 48
Roe and the new frontier. 罗伊案和新边疆。
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2003-01-01
Lisa Shaw Roy
{"title":"Roe and the new frontier.","authors":"Lisa Shaw Roy","doi":"","DOIUrl":"","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2003-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"24833872","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Truth, Truths, "Truth," and "Truths" in the Law 真理,真理,“真理”,律法中的“真理”
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2003-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/JPSL20033711
S. Haack
The best way to get a clear view of questions about truth--in the law or anywhere else--is to start, not with debates over "modernism" versus "post-modernism," and the whole dubious history of ideas they presuppose, but with a few simple distinctions. Truth is the property of being true, what it is to be true. Of the umpteen competing philosophical theories of truth, the most plausible are, in intent or in effect, generalizations of the Aristotelian Insight that "to say of what is that it is, or of what is not that it is not, is true." (1) These theories explain truth without reference to what you or I or anyone believes, without reference to culture, paradigm, or perspective. Some of them, the various versions of the correspondence theory, turn the emphatic adverb for which we reach when we say that p is true just in case actually, really, in fact, p, into serious metaphysics, construing truth as a relation, structural or conventional, of propositions or statements to facts or reality. (2) Others, such as Tarski's semantic theory, (3) Ramsey's "redundancy" theory, (4) and the contemporary deflationist, minimalist, disquotationalist, and prosententialist theories that are their descendants, (5) don't require such an elaborate ontological apparatus. Truths are the many and various propositions, beliefs, etc., which are true, including: particular empirical claims, scientific theories, historical propositions, mathematical theorems, logical principles, textual interpretations, statements about what a person believes or wants or intends, about social roles and rules, etc. To say that a claim is true is not to say that anyone, or everyone, believes it, but that things are as it says. However, some claims are such that the relevant things--a person's beliefs or intentions, a legal or grammatical rule--depend, in one way or another, on us; and some are such that it makes sense to ascribe a truth-value only relative to this or that community or social practice. Moreover, not every sentence, not even every declarative sentence, manages to express something true or false; some, for instance, are too indeterminate in meaning to have a truth-value. The effect of scare quotes is to turn an expression meaning "X" into an expression meaning "so-called 'X'." So scare-quotes "troth," as distinct from truth, is what is taken to be truth; and scare-quotes "truths," as distinct from truths, are claims, propositions, or beliefs, which are taken to be truths--many of which are not really troths at all. We humans, after all, are thoroughly fallible creatures. Even with the best will in the world, finding out the truth can be hard work; and we are often willing, even eager, to take pains to avoid discovering, or to cover up, unpalatable truths. The rhetoric of truth, moreover, can be used in nefarious ways. Hence an important source of the idea that truth is merely a rhetorical or political concept: the seductive, but crashingly invalid, argument I call the "Passes-for
要想清楚地了解关于真理的问题——无论是在法律领域还是在其他任何领域——最好的办法不是从“现代主义”与“后现代主义”的争论开始,也不是从它们所预设的整个可疑的思想史开始,而是从一些简单的区别开始。真理是真实的属性,它是真实的。在无数相互竞争的关于真理的哲学理论中,最似是而非的理论,在意图或效果上,都是对亚里士多德洞察力的概括,即“说什么是真的,或说什么不是真的,都是真的。”(1)这些理论解释真理,不涉及你、我或任何人的信仰,不涉及文化、范式或观点。其中一些,对应理论的不同版本,把强调副词变成了严肃的形而上学,将真理解释为命题或陈述与事实或现实的关系,结构上的或惯例上的关系。(2)其他理论,如塔斯基的语义理论,(3)拉姆齐的“冗余”理论,(4)以及他们的后代——当代通货紧缩主义、极简主义、反引用主义和先验主义理论,(5)并不需要如此复杂的本体论工具。真理是许多不同的命题、信仰等,它们是真实的,包括:特定的经验主张、科学理论、历史命题、数学定理、逻辑原理、文本解释、关于一个人相信什么、想要什么、想要什么、关于社会角色和规则等的陈述。说一种说法是正确的,并不是说任何人或每个人都相信它,而是说事情就是它所说的那样。然而,有些主张是这样的,相关的事情——一个人的信仰或意图,法律或语法规则——以这样或那样的方式取决于我们;有些是这样的,把真理的价值只归因于这个或那个社区或社会实践是有意义的。而且,不是每个句子,甚至不是每个陈述句,都能表达真或假;例如,有些词在意义上太不确定而没有真值。惊吓引号的作用是把一个意思是“X”的表达式变成一个意思是“所谓的‘X’”的表达式。因此,可怕的引用“真理”,作为与真理不同的东西,被认为是真理;而引语中的“真理”,与真理截然不同,是被认为是真理的主张、命题或信念——其中许多根本不是真理。毕竟,我们人类是完全容易犯错的生物。即使有世界上最好的意志,找出真相也可能是一项艰苦的工作;我们常常愿意,甚至渴望,煞费苦心地避免发现或掩盖令人不快的真相。此外,真理的修辞可以用在邪恶的地方。因此,真理仅仅是一种修辞或政治概念这一观点的重要来源是:我称之为“伪谬误”(Passes-for Fallacy),这种论点诱人,但极其无效。(6)这种观点认为,被认为是真理的东西往往并不是真理,而只是权贵们设法让人们接受的真理;因此,真理的概念只不过是意识形态上的骗局。坦率地说,这不仅显然是无效的,而且显然有破坏自身的危险。然而,如果你不能区分真相和恐怖的“真相”,或者真相和恐怖的“真相”,它似乎是不可抗拒的。如今,“替死罪”似乎无处不在。也许它根植于马克思和弗洛伊德的哲学,虚假意识的观念和“怀疑的解释学”。(7)它是由宣传体制促成的,在我们这个时代,是由铺天盖地的信息和错误信息促成的,这些信息和错误信息首先助长了轻信,然后,当人们意识到自己被愚弄时,助长了犬儒主义。因为,当人们发现,所谓的真理根本不是真理——《真理报》充斥着谎言和宣传,报纸上过早鼓吹的科学突破或奇迹进展根本不是真理——人们就会越来越不信任真理的主张,越来越不愿意在不加引号的情况下谈论真理;直到最后,他们对真理的概念失去了信心,以前预防性的警语不再警告,开始嘲笑:“真理?…
{"title":"Truth, Truths, \"Truth,\" and \"Truths\" in the Law","authors":"S. Haack","doi":"10.5840/JPSL20033711","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/JPSL20033711","url":null,"abstract":"The best way to get a clear view of questions about truth--in the law or anywhere else--is to start, not with debates over \"modernism\" versus \"post-modernism,\" and the whole dubious history of ideas they presuppose, but with a few simple distinctions. Truth is the property of being true, what it is to be true. Of the umpteen competing philosophical theories of truth, the most plausible are, in intent or in effect, generalizations of the Aristotelian Insight that \"to say of what is that it is, or of what is not that it is not, is true.\" (1) These theories explain truth without reference to what you or I or anyone believes, without reference to culture, paradigm, or perspective. Some of them, the various versions of the correspondence theory, turn the emphatic adverb for which we reach when we say that p is true just in case actually, really, in fact, p, into serious metaphysics, construing truth as a relation, structural or conventional, of propositions or statements to facts or reality. (2) Others, such as Tarski's semantic theory, (3) Ramsey's \"redundancy\" theory, (4) and the contemporary deflationist, minimalist, disquotationalist, and prosententialist theories that are their descendants, (5) don't require such an elaborate ontological apparatus. Truths are the many and various propositions, beliefs, etc., which are true, including: particular empirical claims, scientific theories, historical propositions, mathematical theorems, logical principles, textual interpretations, statements about what a person believes or wants or intends, about social roles and rules, etc. To say that a claim is true is not to say that anyone, or everyone, believes it, but that things are as it says. However, some claims are such that the relevant things--a person's beliefs or intentions, a legal or grammatical rule--depend, in one way or another, on us; and some are such that it makes sense to ascribe a truth-value only relative to this or that community or social practice. Moreover, not every sentence, not even every declarative sentence, manages to express something true or false; some, for instance, are too indeterminate in meaning to have a truth-value. The effect of scare quotes is to turn an expression meaning \"X\" into an expression meaning \"so-called 'X'.\" So scare-quotes \"troth,\" as distinct from truth, is what is taken to be truth; and scare-quotes \"truths,\" as distinct from truths, are claims, propositions, or beliefs, which are taken to be truths--many of which are not really troths at all. We humans, after all, are thoroughly fallible creatures. Even with the best will in the world, finding out the truth can be hard work; and we are often willing, even eager, to take pains to avoid discovering, or to cover up, unpalatable truths. The rhetoric of truth, moreover, can be used in nefarious ways. Hence an important source of the idea that truth is merely a rhetorical or political concept: the seductive, but crashingly invalid, argument I call the \"Passes-for","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2003-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.5840/JPSL20033711","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71265289","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 27
The President's Constitutional Authority to Conduct Military Operations Against Terrorist Organizations and the Nations that Harbor or Support Them 宪法赋予总统对恐怖组织和包庇或支持恐怖组织的国家采取军事行动的权力
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2002-09-16 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.331202
R. Delahunty, J. Yoo
The terrorist attacks on the United States on September 11, 2001 raised important questions concerning the President's authority to take military action in response. Although Congress acted promptly to pass legislation authorizing the President to take military action against the terrorists and those linked to them, we argue that the President has broad constitutional power, even without such legislation, to deploy military force to retaliate against those implicated in the September 11 attacks. Congress acknowledged this inherent executive power in its recent legislation, as it had earlier in the War Powers Resolution. Further, the President has the inherent power not only to retaliate against any person, organization, or state suspected of involvement in terrorist attacks on the United States, but also against foreign states suspected of harboring or supporting such organizations. Finally, we argue that the President's constitutional authority to deploy military force against terrorists and the states that harbor or support them includes both the power to respond to past attacks and the power to act preemptively against future ones. Our analysis falls into four parts. First, we examine the constitutional text and structure. We conclude that the Constitution vests the President with the plenary authority, as Commander in Chief and the sole organ of the nation in its foreign relations, to use military force abroad, especially in response to grave national emergencies created by sudden, unforeseen attacks on the people and territory of the United States. Second, we confirm that conclusion by reviewing executive and judicial statements and decisions interpreting the President's constitutional powers. Third, we analyze the relevant historical precedent, which supports the argument for Presidential authority in these matters. Finally, we discuss congressional enactments that acknowledge the President's full authority to use force both to respond to the September 11 attacks on the United States and to deter future strikes of that nature.
2001年9月11日对美国的恐怖袭击引发了关于总统采取军事行动的权力的重要问题。尽管国会迅速采取行动,通过立法授权总统对恐怖分子及其同伙采取军事行动,但我们认为,即使没有这样的立法,总统也有广泛的宪法权力,可以部署军事力量报复与9 / 11袭击有关的人。国会在其最近的立法中承认了这种内在的行政权力,正如它早先在《战争权力决议》中所做的那样。此外,总统不仅拥有对涉嫌参与针对美国的恐怖袭击的任何个人、组织或国家进行报复的固有权力,还拥有对涉嫌窝藏或支持此类组织的外国进行报复的固有权力。最后,我们认为,总统对恐怖分子和庇护或支持恐怖分子的国家部署军事力量的宪法权力既包括对过去袭击作出反应的权力,也包括对未来袭击采取先发制人行动的权力。我们的分析分为四个部分。首先,我们考察宪法的文本和结构。我们的结论是,《宪法》赋予总统作为总司令和国家在外交关系中的唯一机关的全部权力,在国外使用军事力量,特别是在对美国人民和领土受到突然的、无法预料的攻击所造成的严重国家紧急情况作出反应时。其次,我们通过审查解释总统宪法权力的行政和司法声明和决定来确认这一结论。第三,我们分析了相关的历史先例,这些先例支持总统在这些问题上的权威。最后,我们讨论承认总统有充分权力使用武力对美国遭受的9 / 11袭击作出反应并阻止未来同类袭击的国会立法。
{"title":"The President's Constitutional Authority to Conduct Military Operations Against Terrorist Organizations and the Nations that Harbor or Support Them","authors":"R. Delahunty, J. Yoo","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.331202","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.331202","url":null,"abstract":"The terrorist attacks on the United States on September 11, 2001 raised important questions concerning the President's authority to take military action in response. Although Congress acted promptly to pass legislation authorizing the President to take military action against the terrorists and those linked to them, we argue that the President has broad constitutional power, even without such legislation, to deploy military force to retaliate against those implicated in the September 11 attacks. Congress acknowledged this inherent executive power in its recent legislation, as it had earlier in the War Powers Resolution. Further, the President has the inherent power not only to retaliate against any person, organization, or state suspected of involvement in terrorist attacks on the United States, but also against foreign states suspected of harboring or supporting such organizations. Finally, we argue that the President's constitutional authority to deploy military force against terrorists and the states that harbor or support them includes both the power to respond to past attacks and the power to act preemptively against future ones. Our analysis falls into four parts. First, we examine the constitutional text and structure. We conclude that the Constitution vests the President with the plenary authority, as Commander in Chief and the sole organ of the nation in its foreign relations, to use military force abroad, especially in response to grave national emergencies created by sudden, unforeseen attacks on the people and territory of the United States. Second, we confirm that conclusion by reviewing executive and judicial statements and decisions interpreting the President's constitutional powers. Third, we analyze the relevant historical precedent, which supports the argument for Presidential authority in these matters. Finally, we discuss congressional enactments that acknowledge the President's full authority to use force both to respond to the September 11 attacks on the United States and to deter future strikes of that nature.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2002-09-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.331202","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68583870","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 11
Terrorism, Federalism, and Police Misconduct 恐怖主义、联邦制和警察不当行为
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2001-12-19 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.294253
William J. Stuntz
Criminal law enforcement in the United States is overwhelmingly local - the large majority of police and prosecutors work for local governments, the large majority of arrests are made by local police, the overwhelming majority of criminal prosecutions are brought by local district attorneys' offices, and the great bulk of prisoners are in their cells as a result of those local prosecutions. The states do very little policing and almost no prosecution. And while the federal government does more in this sphere, it is still very much a backstop. This essay explores two questions: How does that allocation of law enforcement power affect the level of police misconduct in the United States? And how will the war on terrorism change both the allocation and the amount of police misbehavior? In brief, my answers to those questions are: In a system like ours, federal police - chiefly the FBI - may present more serious misconduct problems than do local police, because the FBI is neither politically accountable nor tightly constrained by limited resources. (Local police are both accountable and resource-constrained.) The war on terrorism may change that conclusion, by increasing not only the FBI's power, but also its level of accountability and constraint.
美国的刑事执法绝大多数是地方性的——绝大多数警察和检察官为地方政府工作,绝大多数逮捕是由地方警察执行的,绝大多数刑事起诉是由地方检察官办公室提出的,绝大多数囚犯是由于这些地方起诉而被关进牢房的。各州几乎不做警务工作,也几乎不起诉。虽然联邦政府在这方面做得更多,但它在很大程度上仍然是一个后盾。本文探讨了两个问题:执法权力的分配如何影响美国警察不当行为的程度?反恐战争将如何改变警察不当行为的分配和数量?简而言之,我对这些问题的回答是:在像我们这样的系统中,联邦警察——主要是联邦调查局——可能会比地方警察出现更严重的不当行为问题,因为联邦调查局既不负有政治责任,也不受有限资源的严格约束。(当地警察既要负责,又要资源有限。)反恐战争可能会改变这一结论,因为它不仅增强了FBI的权力,还增强了它的问责和约束程度。
{"title":"Terrorism, Federalism, and Police Misconduct","authors":"William J. Stuntz","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.294253","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.294253","url":null,"abstract":"Criminal law enforcement in the United States is overwhelmingly local - the large majority of police and prosecutors work for local governments, the large majority of arrests are made by local police, the overwhelming majority of criminal prosecutions are brought by local district attorneys' offices, and the great bulk of prisoners are in their cells as a result of those local prosecutions. The states do very little policing and almost no prosecution. And while the federal government does more in this sphere, it is still very much a backstop. This essay explores two questions: How does that allocation of law enforcement power affect the level of police misconduct in the United States? And how will the war on terrorism change both the allocation and the amount of police misbehavior? In brief, my answers to those questions are: In a system like ours, federal police - chiefly the FBI - may present more serious misconduct problems than do local police, because the FBI is neither politically accountable nor tightly constrained by limited resources. (Local police are both accountable and resource-constrained.) The war on terrorism may change that conclusion, by increasing not only the FBI's power, but also its level of accountability and constraint.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2001-12-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68439088","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 8
Cyberjam: The Law and Economics of Internet Congestion of the Telephone Network 网络堵塞:电话网络拥塞的法律和经济学
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2001-09-13 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.282995
J. Sidak, Daniel F. Spulber
In this article we evaluate the economic and legal implications of allowing ISPs to avoid paying for interstate access by taking advantage of the FCC's access-charge exemption for enhanced service providers (ESPs). We agree with the FCC's conclusion that the dramatic growth of Internet usage and Internet services create significant benefits for the economy and the American people. We discuss, however, that the ESP exemption creates traffic jams at the on-ramps to the information superhighway- what we call a cyberjam.In Part II, we examine the role that competitive prices play in influencing supply and demand in the market for access to Internet services over the PSTN. In Part III, we examine the economics of network congestion. In Part IV, we examine the pricing of access to ISPs over the PSTN. In Part V, we consider property rights issues associated with the costs of the FCC's tentative conclusion to continue the temporary ESP exemption. In Part VI, we argue that is unlawful for the FCC to order incumbent LECs to continue subsidizing ISPs through the perpetuation of the currently temporary ESP exemption from interstate access charges, or through any other artifice.
在本文中,我们评估了允许isp通过利用FCC对增强型服务提供商(esp)的接入费用豁免来避免支付州际接入费用的经济和法律含义。我们同意联邦通信委员会的结论,即互联网使用和互联网服务的急剧增长为经济和美国人民创造了巨大的利益。然而,我们讨论到ESP豁免会在信息高速公路的入口匝道造成交通堵塞——我们称之为网络堵塞。在第二部分中,我们研究了竞争性价格在影响通过PSTN接入互联网服务的市场供求方面所起的作用。在第三部分,我们研究了网络拥塞的经济学。在第四部分中,我们研究了通过PSTN访问isp的定价。在第五部分中,我们考虑了与FCC继续临时ESP豁免的初步结论的成本相关的产权问题。在第六部分中,我们认为联邦通信委员会命令在位的LECs通过目前暂时免除州际接入费用或通过任何其他手段继续补贴isp是非法的。
{"title":"Cyberjam: The Law and Economics of Internet Congestion of the Telephone Network","authors":"J. Sidak, Daniel F. Spulber","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.282995","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.282995","url":null,"abstract":"In this article we evaluate the economic and legal implications of allowing ISPs to avoid paying for interstate access by taking advantage of the FCC's access-charge exemption for enhanced service providers (ESPs). We agree with the FCC's conclusion that the dramatic growth of Internet usage and Internet services create significant benefits for the economy and the American people. We discuss, however, that the ESP exemption creates traffic jams at the on-ramps to the information superhighway- what we call a cyberjam.In Part II, we examine the role that competitive prices play in influencing supply and demand in the market for access to Internet services over the PSTN. In Part III, we examine the economics of network congestion. In Part IV, we examine the pricing of access to ISPs over the PSTN. In Part V, we consider property rights issues associated with the costs of the FCC's tentative conclusion to continue the temporary ESP exemption. In Part VI, we argue that is unlawful for the FCC to order incumbent LECs to continue subsidizing ISPs through the perpetuation of the currently temporary ESP exemption from interstate access charges, or through any other artifice.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2001-09-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68364082","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 7
期刊
Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1