首页 > 最新文献

Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy最新文献

英文 中文
The Presumption of Constitutionality 合宪性推定
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2019-01-01 DOI: 10.2307/1115339
E. Whelan
{"title":"The Presumption of Constitutionality","authors":"E. Whelan","doi":"10.2307/1115339","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2307/1115339","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"58 1","pages":"17"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2019-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2307/1115339","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68233313","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Immigration, Freedom, and the Constitution 移民、自由和宪法
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2017-05-15 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2968440
I. Somin
In recent years, many conservatives have come to favor a highly restrictionist approach to immigration policy. But that position is in conflict with their own professed commitment to principles such as free markets, liberty, colorblindness, and enforcing constitutional limits on the power of the federal government. These values ultimately all support a strong presumption in favor of free migration. ********** I. IMMIGRATION AND FREEDOM Let us focus on free markets first. Immigration restrictions are among the the biggest government interventions in the economy. They prevent millions of people from taking jobs, renting homes, and pursuing a wide range of opportunities that they could otherwise have. Economists estimate that if we had free migration throughout the world, we could double world GNP. (1) That is not a gaffe or a mispring; it is a real estimate. Perhaps doubling GNP is overly optimistic. Still, increasing it by, say, 50 percent is a greater effect than virtually any other realistically feasible change in economic policy. (2) The reason why immigration restrictions have such an enormous effect is pretty simple. People become much more productive when they move from countries where they have little or no opportunity to use their talents, to those where they can be more productive. Just crossing from Mexico to the United States makes a person three or four more times more productive than they otherwise would be, even without improving their skills in any way. (3) And the opportunities to improve skills are, for most immigrants, far greater in the U.S. than where they initially came from. There is an enormous amount of wealth that can be created just by cutting back on our immigration restrictions. But it would be a mistake to say that the issue here is primarily economic. It is also, and even more fundamentally, about freedom. When people come to the United States from poor and oppressive societies, they increase their freedom in many ways. Think of refugees fleeing religious or ethnic persecution, women escaping patriarchal societies, or people fleeing massacres such as those perpetrated by ISIS. The ancestors of most modern Americans escaped such oppression during the period when we wisely did not have the kinds of immigration restrictions that we do today. If we had today's immigration policies back then, the ancestors of most of the current US population would never have been allowed to come. Immigration restrictions undermine the freedom of native-born Americans as well as immigrants. Because of our immigration laws, millions of native-born Americans cannot hire the workers they want, associate with the businesses that they choose, nor benefit from the entrepreneurship of immigrants; on average, they tend to be more entrepreneurial than native-born citizens. (4) II. IMMIGRATION AND DISCRIMINATION Current immigration policy is also inimical to the principle of color-blindness in government. In December 2014 President Obama's Departmen
近年来,许多保守派倾向于对移民政策采取高度限制的做法。但这一立场与他们自己宣称的对自由市场、自由、色盲以及对联邦政府权力实施宪法限制等原则的承诺相冲突。这些价值观最终都支持有利于自由移民的有力假设。**********一、移民与自由让我们首先关注自由市场。移民限制是政府对经济的最大干预措施之一。它们阻止了数百万人就业、租房和追求原本可以拥有的广泛机会。经济学家估计,如果我们在世界各地自由移民,我们可以使世界国民生产总值翻一番。(1) 这不是失态或说错了话;这是一个真实的估计。也许将国民生产总值翻一番过于乐观。尽管如此,将其提高50%的效果比几乎任何其他现实可行的经济政策变化都要大。(2) 移民限制产生如此巨大影响的原因很简单。当人们从很少或根本没有机会发挥才能的国家转移到那些可以提高生产力的国家时,他们的生产力就会大大提高。即使没有以任何方式提高技能,只要从墨西哥到美国,一个人的生产力就会比其他地方高出三四倍。(3) 对大多数移民来说,在美国提高技能的机会远大于他们最初的家乡。只要减少移民限制,就可以创造大量财富。但如果说这里的问题主要是经济问题,那就大错特错了。这也是,甚至更根本的,关于自由。当人们从贫穷和压迫的社会来到美国时,他们在很多方面增加了自由。想想逃离宗教或种族迫害的难民,逃离父权社会的妇女,或者逃离ISIS等大屠杀的人。大多数现代美国人的祖先在我们明智地没有像今天这样的移民限制的时期逃脱了这种压迫。如果我们当时有今天的移民政策,现在大多数美国人口的祖先永远不会被允许来。移民限制损害了土生土长的美国人和移民的自由。由于我们的移民法,数百万土生土长的美国人无法雇佣他们想要的工人,无法与他们选择的企业合作,也无法从移民的创业中受益;平均而言,他们往往比土生土长的公民更有创业精神。(4) II。移民和歧视目前的移民政策也不利于政府的色盲原则。2014年12月,奥巴马总统的国土安全部得出结论,除非继续进行大规模的种族定性,否则无法执行移民限制。这是奥巴马政府认为种族貌相是件好事的一个领域。(5) 这种定性不仅影响移民,还影响数百万土生土长的公民,他们唯一的罪行是碰巧与许多无证移民属于同一种族或族裔。(6) 如果你相信在政府政策中结束种族歧视,这将是一个很好的起点。据我所知,没有其他领域的联邦执法部门如此大规模地公开诉诸种族歧视,即使在一个普遍敌视种族貌相的自由主义政府之下也是如此。大多数保守派和自由主义者支持公共政策中的色盲原则,或者至少是支持这一原则的有力假设。我们不认为政府应该基于种族或族裔进行歧视…
{"title":"Immigration, Freedom, and the Constitution","authors":"I. Somin","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2968440","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2968440","url":null,"abstract":"In recent years, many conservatives have come to favor a highly restrictionist approach to immigration policy. But that position is in conflict with their own professed commitment to principles such as free markets, liberty, colorblindness, and enforcing constitutional limits on the power of the federal government. These values ultimately all support a strong presumption in favor of free migration. ********** I. IMMIGRATION AND FREEDOM Let us focus on free markets first. Immigration restrictions are among the the biggest government interventions in the economy. They prevent millions of people from taking jobs, renting homes, and pursuing a wide range of opportunities that they could otherwise have. Economists estimate that if we had free migration throughout the world, we could double world GNP. (1) That is not a gaffe or a mispring; it is a real estimate. Perhaps doubling GNP is overly optimistic. Still, increasing it by, say, 50 percent is a greater effect than virtually any other realistically feasible change in economic policy. (2) The reason why immigration restrictions have such an enormous effect is pretty simple. People become much more productive when they move from countries where they have little or no opportunity to use their talents, to those where they can be more productive. Just crossing from Mexico to the United States makes a person three or four more times more productive than they otherwise would be, even without improving their skills in any way. (3) And the opportunities to improve skills are, for most immigrants, far greater in the U.S. than where they initially came from. There is an enormous amount of wealth that can be created just by cutting back on our immigration restrictions. But it would be a mistake to say that the issue here is primarily economic. It is also, and even more fundamentally, about freedom. When people come to the United States from poor and oppressive societies, they increase their freedom in many ways. Think of refugees fleeing religious or ethnic persecution, women escaping patriarchal societies, or people fleeing massacres such as those perpetrated by ISIS. The ancestors of most modern Americans escaped such oppression during the period when we wisely did not have the kinds of immigration restrictions that we do today. If we had today's immigration policies back then, the ancestors of most of the current US population would never have been allowed to come. Immigration restrictions undermine the freedom of native-born Americans as well as immigrants. Because of our immigration laws, millions of native-born Americans cannot hire the workers they want, associate with the businesses that they choose, nor benefit from the entrepreneurship of immigrants; on average, they tend to be more entrepreneurial than native-born citizens. (4) II. IMMIGRATION AND DISCRIMINATION Current immigration policy is also inimical to the principle of color-blindness in government. In December 2014 President Obama's Departmen","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"40 1","pages":"1"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2017-05-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46878731","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Business Transactions and President Trump's 'Emoluments' Problem 商业交易和特朗普总统的“薪酬”问题
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2017-04-23 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2937186
S. Tillman
Recently, some have argued (1) that the term "emoluments," as used in the Constitution's Foreign Emoluments Clause (2) and Presidential Emoluments Clause, (3) reaches any pecuniary advantage, benefit, or profit arising in connection with business transactions for value. (4) There is good reason to doubt the correctness of this position. Why? The Presidential Emoluments Clause states: The President shall, at stated Times, receive for his Services, a Compensation, which shall neither be increased nor diminished during the Period for which he shall have been elected, and he shall not receive within that Period any other Emolument from the United States, or any of them. (5) If the emoluments-are-any-pecuniary-advantage position were correct, if "emoluments" as used in the Constitution extended to any pecuniary advantage, then presidents are and would have been precluded from doing business with the United States government. However, George Washington, who had presided over the Philadelphia Convention, (6) did business with the Federal Government on more than one occasion while he was president. He purchased several lots of land in the new federal capital at public auction. One such set of purchases took place on or about September 18, 1793. (7) The public auction was run by three commissioners: David Stuart, Daniel Carroll, and Thomas Johnson. Who were they? David Stuart was a member of the Virginia convention that ratified the Federal Constitution. Stuart was also a federal elector in the first federal election for President and Vice President of the United States. (8) Daniel Carroll was a member of the Federal Convention that drafted the Constitution and later a member of the First Congress. (9) Thomas Johnson was the first Governor of Maryland following independence, a member of the Maryland convention that ratified the Federal Constitution, and afterwards he served as a Justice of the Supreme Court of the United States. (10) So among the four participants (Washington and the three commissioners) were: three members of the Continental Congress; (11) three members of pre-independence colonial legislatures or post-independence state legislatures; (12) two members of state conventions that ratified the Constitution; two members of the Federal Convention (including the Convention's president); a member of the First Congress; a Justice of the Supreme Court of the United States; a governor; a federal elector for President and Vice President; and, our first President. Collectively these four are, undoubtedly, an accomplished group. Are we really to believe that not only did all four officials willingly, openly, and notoriously participate in a conspiracy to aid and abet the President in violating the Constitution's Presidential Emoluments Clause, but that they also left--for themselves and their posterity--a complete and signed documentary trail of their wrongdoing? (13) The emoluments-are-any-pecuniary-advantage position amounts to: (1) President Washin
最近,一些人认为:(1)《宪法》外国薪酬条款(2)和总统薪酬条款中使用的“薪酬”一词,(3)指的是与有价商业交易有关的任何金钱利益、利益或利润。(4) 有充分的理由怀疑这一立场的正确性。为什么?总统薪酬条款规定:总统应在规定的时间因其服务获得报酬,在其当选期间不得增加或减少,在该期间不得从美国或其中任何国家获得任何其他薪酬。(5) 如果薪酬是任何金钱利益,那么立场是正确的,如果宪法中使用的“薪酬”延伸到任何金钱利益上,那么总统现在和本应被禁止与美国政府做生意。然而,主持费城会议的乔治·华盛顿在担任总统期间不止一次与联邦政府做生意。他在公开拍卖会上购买了新联邦首都的几块土地。其中一次购买发生在1793年9月18日左右。(7) 此次公开拍卖由三位委员负责:大卫·斯图尔特、丹尼尔·卡罗尔和托马斯·约翰逊。他们是谁?大卫·斯图亚特是批准联邦宪法的弗吉尼亚州大会的成员。斯图尔特也是第一次美国总统和副总统联邦选举的联邦选举人。(8) 丹尼尔·卡罗尔是起草宪法的联邦会议成员,后来成为第一届国会议员。(9) 托马斯·约翰逊是马里兰州独立后的第一位州长,也是批准联邦宪法的马里兰州大会的成员,之后他担任美国最高法院法官。(10) 因此,四位与会者(华盛顿和三位委员)中有:三位大陆会议成员;(11) 独立前殖民地立法机构或独立后州立法机构的三名成员;(12) 批准《宪法》的两个州公约成员;联邦公约的两名成员(包括公约主席);第一届国会议员;美国最高法院法官;州长;总统和副总统的联邦选举人;以及我们的第一任总统。毫无疑问,这四个人加在一起是一个有成就的群体。我们真的相信吗,这四名官员不仅自愿、公开、臭名昭著地参与了一场阴谋,帮助和教唆总统违反宪法的总统薪酬条款,而且他们还为自己和子孙后代留下了一份完整的、签名的文件,记录他们的不法行为?(13) 薪酬是任何金钱利益职位的总和:(1)华盛顿总统充其量是严重疏忽,如果不是不正当的话;(2) 华盛顿的盟友公开支持明显而深刻的宪法违法行为;(3)华盛顿的政治对手完全保持沉默——在国会保持沉默,(14)在报纸上保持沉默,甚至在私人信件中也保持沉默。薪酬是任何金钱利益,这相当于21世纪法律学者的赤裸裸的断言(15),即他们比华盛顿政府起草、批准和实施宪法的人更了解宪法具有约束力的法律意义。另一种观点是,语言和历史的谦逊迫使理性的人认识到,我们有两个多世纪历史的宪法中的大部分语言都是不透明的。因此,为了让21世纪的公民理解宪法在批准时对一个特定(但在其他方面晦涩难懂)的法律术语,即“薪酬”的不透明语言意味着什么(以及它在今天仍然意味着什么),理性的人必须关注制定者、批准者、,以及三个分支在直接面对根据具体事实确定特定法律术语含义的必要性时的最初做法…
{"title":"Business Transactions and President Trump's 'Emoluments' Problem","authors":"S. Tillman","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2937186","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2937186","url":null,"abstract":"Recently, some have argued (1) that the term \"emoluments,\" as used in the Constitution's Foreign Emoluments Clause (2) and Presidential Emoluments Clause, (3) reaches any pecuniary advantage, benefit, or profit arising in connection with business transactions for value. (4) There is good reason to doubt the correctness of this position. Why? The Presidential Emoluments Clause states: The President shall, at stated Times, receive for his Services, a Compensation, which shall neither be increased nor diminished during the Period for which he shall have been elected, and he shall not receive within that Period any other Emolument from the United States, or any of them. (5) If the emoluments-are-any-pecuniary-advantage position were correct, if \"emoluments\" as used in the Constitution extended to any pecuniary advantage, then presidents are and would have been precluded from doing business with the United States government. However, George Washington, who had presided over the Philadelphia Convention, (6) did business with the Federal Government on more than one occasion while he was president. He purchased several lots of land in the new federal capital at public auction. One such set of purchases took place on or about September 18, 1793. (7) The public auction was run by three commissioners: David Stuart, Daniel Carroll, and Thomas Johnson. Who were they? David Stuart was a member of the Virginia convention that ratified the Federal Constitution. Stuart was also a federal elector in the first federal election for President and Vice President of the United States. (8) Daniel Carroll was a member of the Federal Convention that drafted the Constitution and later a member of the First Congress. (9) Thomas Johnson was the first Governor of Maryland following independence, a member of the Maryland convention that ratified the Federal Constitution, and afterwards he served as a Justice of the Supreme Court of the United States. (10) So among the four participants (Washington and the three commissioners) were: three members of the Continental Congress; (11) three members of pre-independence colonial legislatures or post-independence state legislatures; (12) two members of state conventions that ratified the Constitution; two members of the Federal Convention (including the Convention's president); a member of the First Congress; a Justice of the Supreme Court of the United States; a governor; a federal elector for President and Vice President; and, our first President. Collectively these four are, undoubtedly, an accomplished group. Are we really to believe that not only did all four officials willingly, openly, and notoriously participate in a conspiracy to aid and abet the President in violating the Constitution's Presidential Emoluments Clause, but that they also left--for themselves and their posterity--a complete and signed documentary trail of their wrongdoing? (13) The emoluments-are-any-pecuniary-advantage position amounts to: (1) President Washin","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"40 1","pages":"759"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2017-04-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48351871","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Free Expression on Campus: Mitigating the Costs of Contentious Speakers 校园言论自由:减少有争议演讲者的成本
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2017-01-01 DOI: 10.7916/D8Z33G7T
Suzanne B. Goldberg
{"title":"Free Expression on Campus: Mitigating the Costs of Contentious Speakers","authors":"Suzanne B. Goldberg","doi":"10.7916/D8Z33G7T","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.7916/D8Z33G7T","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"41 1","pages":"163-186"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2017-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71368690","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
Revitalizing the Clemency Process 重振宽恕程序
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2016-11-01 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.2862705
Paul J. Larkin, Jr.
St. Anselm once asked how a perfectly just God could also be merciful, since perfect justice and almighty grace could not seemingly coexist. Fortunately, the criminal justice system does not need to answer that question, one that has proven inscrutable for theologians and philosophers, because its assumptions do not apply to our system. An earthly judicial system will never be able to administer justice perfectly and cannot disburse mercy even approaching the quality of the divine. But the clemency power can try to achieve as much of an accommodation between those two goals as any human institution can. Unfortunately, however, our recent span of presidents, attuned more to political than humanitarian considerations and fearing the electoral wrath of the voters for mistaken judgments, have largely abandoned their ability to grant clemency in order to husband their political capital for pedestrian undertakings. Far worse, others have succumbed to the dark side of “the Force,” have used their power shamefully, and have left a stain on clemency that we have yet to remove. We now have reached a point where that taint can be eliminated. There is a consensus that the clemency process can and should be reformed. The problem lies not in the power itself, but in the process by which cases are brought to the President for his review and maybe in the people we have elected to make those decisions. The Office of the Pardon Attorney should be transferred from the Department of Justice to the Executive Office of the President, and the President should select someone to fill that position. That revision to the clemency process should help us see a return of the necessary role that clemency can play in a system that strives to be both just and merciful.
圣安瑟伦曾经问过,既然完美的正义和全能的恩典似乎不能共存,那么一个完全公正的上帝怎么可能同时仁慈呢?幸运的是,刑事司法系统不需要回答这个问题,这个问题已经被证明对神学家和哲学家来说是不可理解的,因为它的假设不适用于我们的系统。一个世俗的司法系统将永远无法完美地执行正义,也无法支付仁慈,甚至接近神圣的品质。但是,宽大处理的权力可以像任何人类机构一样,尽量在这两个目标之间实现协调。然而,不幸的是,我们最近的几任总统,更多地关注政治而不是人道主义考虑,担心选民因错误的判断而在选举中愤怒,他们在很大程度上放弃了给予宽大处理的能力,以便将自己的政治资本用于平凡的事业。更糟糕的是,其他人已经屈服于“原力”的阴暗面,可耻地使用他们的力量,并留下了我们尚未消除的仁慈污点。我们现在已经到了可以消除这种污染的地步。人们一致认为,宽大处理程序能够而且应该进行改革。问题不在于权力本身,而在于将案件提交给总统审查的过程,也许还在于我们选出来做这些决定的人。赦免检察官办公室应该从司法部转移到总统行政办公室,总统应该选择一个人来填补这个职位。对宽恕程序的这一修订应有助于我们看到宽恕在一个努力既公正又仁慈的制度中所能发挥的必要作用的恢复。
{"title":"Revitalizing the Clemency Process","authors":"Paul J. Larkin, Jr.","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.2862705","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2862705","url":null,"abstract":"St. Anselm once asked how a perfectly just God could also be merciful, since perfect justice and almighty grace could not seemingly coexist. Fortunately, the criminal justice system does not need to answer that question, one that has proven inscrutable for theologians and philosophers, because its assumptions do not apply to our system. An earthly judicial system will never be able to administer justice perfectly and cannot disburse mercy even approaching the quality of the divine. But the clemency power can try to achieve as much of an accommodation between those two goals as any human institution can. Unfortunately, however, our recent span of presidents, attuned more to political than humanitarian considerations and fearing the electoral wrath of the voters for mistaken judgments, have largely abandoned their ability to grant clemency in order to husband their political capital for pedestrian undertakings. Far worse, others have succumbed to the dark side of “the Force,” have used their power shamefully, and have left a stain on clemency that we have yet to remove. We now have reached a point where that taint can be eliminated. There is a consensus that the clemency process can and should be reformed. The problem lies not in the power itself, but in the process by which cases are brought to the President for his review and maybe in the people we have elected to make those decisions. The Office of the Pardon Attorney should be transferred from the Department of Justice to the Executive Office of the President, and the President should select someone to fill that position. That revision to the clemency process should help us see a return of the necessary role that clemency can play in a system that strives to be both just and merciful.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2016-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68398763","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
The Power to Define Offenses Against the Law of Nations 界定违反国际法之罪的权力
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2016-10-04 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2810911
Alex H. Loomis
Congress has the power to “define and punish...Offenses against the Law of Nations.” This clause clearly empowers Congress to punish universally recognized offenses under international law, piracy being one obvious example. But Congress also has the power to “define” offenses against the law of nations. Surely punishing an offense presupposes defining it. So what does “define” add?This paper provides an answer. The Constitution’s text and structure, early constitutional history, and modern foreign relations doctrine all suggest that Congress has the power to define offenses against the law of nations that preexisting international law does not proscribe. Congress may pass laws prohibiting private conduct that violates international law, as well as any private conduct that the United States has an international duty to punish. It can also punish offenses if it is ambiguous whether international law requires it too. Congress probably even has the power to create new offenses in order to foster changes in customary international law.
国会有权“定义和惩罚……违反国际法的罪行。”这一条款明确授权国会根据国际法惩罚普遍公认的罪行,海盗行为就是一个明显的例子。但国会也有权“定义”违反国际法的罪行。当然,惩罚一项罪行的前提是要给它下定义。那么define加了什么呢?本文提供了一个答案。宪法的文本和结构、早期宪法历史和现代外交原则都表明,国会有权定义先前存在的国际法不禁止的违反国内法的罪行。国会可以通过法律,禁止违反国际法的私人行为,以及美国有国际责任惩罚的任何私人行为。如果国际法是否也有这样的要求,它也可以惩罚违法行为。国会甚至可能有权力创造新的罪行,以促进习惯国际法的变化。
{"title":"The Power to Define Offenses Against the Law of Nations","authors":"Alex H. Loomis","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2810911","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2810911","url":null,"abstract":"Congress has the power to “define and punish...Offenses against the Law of Nations.” This clause clearly empowers Congress to punish universally recognized offenses under international law, piracy being one obvious example. But Congress also has the power to “define” offenses against the law of nations. Surely punishing an offense presupposes defining it. So what does “define” add?This paper provides an answer. The Constitution’s text and structure, early constitutional history, and modern foreign relations doctrine all suggest that Congress has the power to define offenses against the law of nations that preexisting international law does not proscribe. Congress may pass laws prohibiting private conduct that violates international law, as well as any private conduct that the United States has an international duty to punish. It can also punish offenses if it is ambiguous whether international law requires it too. Congress probably even has the power to create new offenses in order to foster changes in customary international law.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"40 1","pages":"417"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2016-10-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68342765","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Sexual Integrity of Religious Schools and Tax Exemption 宗教学校的性诚信与免税
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2016-07-26 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2814711
J. R. Buckles
Many private universities and other schools adhere to religiously grounded codes of conduct that embrace heterosexual monogamy as the sole moral context for sexual relationships. The federal income tax exemption of these schools has been questioned following the recent Supreme Court opinion of Obergefell v. Hodges. In Obergefell, the Supreme Court held that the right to marry is a fundamental constitutional right that same-sex couples may exercise. The relevance of this decision to the federal tax status of private religious schools arises from another Supreme Court decision, Bob Jones University v. United States. The Court in Bob Jones held that two schools with racially discriminatory policies as to students were not entitled to exemption from federal income tax because the policies violate established public policy. The issue now is whether the sexual conduct policies of private religious schools violate the established public policy of the United States following Obergefell. After reviewing Bob Jones and surveying the application of the public policy doctrine by the IRS and the courts, this article argues that, regardless of the factual context of a controversy in which the IRS seeks to invoke Bob Jones to deny or revoke federal income tax exemption, the public policy doctrine should be narrowly construed. Applying a suggested framework for limiting the public policy doctrine coherently, this Article argues that schools maintaining sexual conduct policies that prohibit sexual activity inconsistent with their religiously informed, traditional view of marriage remain tax-exempt after Obergefell. Apart from the proposed framework, this Article further explains why Obergefell’s analytical approach, language and tone are inconsistent with applying Bob Jones to the disadvantage of religious schools that maintain sexual conduct policies.
许多私立大学和其他学校坚持以宗教为基础的行为准则,将异性恋一夫一妻制作为性关系的唯一道德背景。在奥贝格费尔诉霍奇斯案(Obergefell v. Hodges)最近的最高法院判决之后,这些学校的联邦所得税豁免受到质疑。在奥贝格费尔案中,最高法院认为,结婚的权利是同性伴侣可以行使的一项基本宪法权利。这一决定与私立宗教学校的联邦税收地位的相关性源于最高法院的另一项裁决,鲍勃·琼斯大学诉美国。鲍勃·琼斯案法院认为,两所对学生实行种族歧视政策的学校无权免征联邦所得税,因为这些政策违反了既定的公共政策。现在的问题是私立宗教学校的性行为政策是否违反了奥贝格费尔案之后美国的既定公共政策。在回顾了鲍勃·琼斯案并调查了美国国税局和法院对公共政策原则的应用之后,本文认为,无论美国国税局试图援引鲍勃·琼斯案来否认或撤销联邦所得税豁免的争议的事实背景如何,都应该狭义地解释公共政策原则。本文运用一个建议的框架来连贯地限制公共政策原则,认为在奥贝格费尔事件之后,维持性行为政策的学校禁止与其宗教信仰和传统婚姻观不一致的性活动,仍然免税。除了提出的框架之外,本文还进一步解释了为什么Obergefell的分析方法、语言和语气与将Bob Jones应用于维持性行为政策的宗教学校的劣势不一致。
{"title":"The Sexual Integrity of Religious Schools and Tax Exemption","authors":"J. R. Buckles","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2814711","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2814711","url":null,"abstract":"Many private universities and other schools adhere to religiously grounded codes of conduct that embrace heterosexual monogamy as the sole moral context for sexual relationships. The federal income tax exemption of these schools has been questioned following the recent Supreme Court opinion of Obergefell v. Hodges. In Obergefell, the Supreme Court held that the right to marry is a fundamental constitutional right that same-sex couples may exercise. The relevance of this decision to the federal tax status of private religious schools arises from another Supreme Court decision, Bob Jones University v. United States. The Court in Bob Jones held that two schools with racially discriminatory policies as to students were not entitled to exemption from federal income tax because the policies violate established public policy. The issue now is whether the sexual conduct policies of private religious schools violate the established public policy of the United States following Obergefell. After reviewing Bob Jones and surveying the application of the public policy doctrine by the IRS and the courts, this article argues that, regardless of the factual context of a controversy in which the IRS seeks to invoke Bob Jones to deny or revoke federal income tax exemption, the public policy doctrine should be narrowly construed. Applying a suggested framework for limiting the public policy doctrine coherently, this Article argues that schools maintaining sexual conduct policies that prohibit sexual activity inconsistent with their religiously informed, traditional view of marriage remain tax-exempt after Obergefell. Apart from the proposed framework, this Article further explains why Obergefell’s analytical approach, language and tone are inconsistent with applying Bob Jones to the disadvantage of religious schools that maintain sexual conduct policies.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"40 1","pages":"255"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2016-07-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68346083","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Of Brutal Murder and Transcendental Sovereignty: The Meaning of Vested Private Rights 野蛮谋杀与先验主权:既得私权的意义
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2016-07-15 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2810162
A. MacLeod
The idea of vested private rights divides those who practice law from those who teach and think about law. On one side of the divide, practicing lawyers act as though (at least some) rights exist and exert binding obligation upon private persons and government officials. On the other side of the divide, scholars of law and jurisprudence have generally proceeded, since at least the rise of English positivism in the nineteenth century and the American legal realist movement in the early twentieth, as if the concept of vested right has little real meaning. This article attempts to explain the doctrine’s continued appeal and to discern some coherence in it while also accounting for the causes of skepticism.The approach is made by way of a central case study: the right of emancipation on free English soil. The study suggests a coherent, focal meaning of the vested private right as a norm that imposes a conclusive duty upon a duty-bearer or class of duty-bearers, and which constrains public officials’ powers to recognize, change, or adjudicate private rights and duties. This focal meaning suggests that central instances of vested rights are quite rare. This accounts for skepticism of the concept. Yet it also suggests that less-central instances of vested rights are rather common. This accounts for the concept’s practical appeal and enables one to distinguish weak or peripheral senses of vested private rights, which are not as conceptually interesting but are nevertheless significant for the practice of law, from strong or central senses, which are rare in practice but theoretically interesting.
既得私人权利的概念将法律从业者与教授和思考法律的人区分开来。在分歧的一方,执业律师表现得好像(至少有些)权利是存在的,并对个人和政府官员施加有约束力的义务。在分歧的另一边,至少从19世纪英国实证主义的兴起和20世纪初美国法律现实主义运动开始,法律和法学学者就普遍认为既得权利的概念没有什么真正的意义。本文试图解释该学说的持续吸引力,并辨别出其中的一些一致性,同时也说明了怀疑主义的原因。这个方法是通过一个中心案例研究:在自由的英国土地上的解放权利。这项研究表明,既得的私人权利作为一种规范具有连贯的、集中的意义,它对义务承担者或义务承担者阶级施加了决定性的义务,并限制了公职人员承认、改变或裁决私人权利和义务的权力。这一中心意义表明既得权利的中心实例相当罕见。这说明人们对这一概念持怀疑态度。然而,它也表明,既得权利的不那么核心的例子相当普遍。这解释了这一概念的实际吸引力,并使人们能够区分既得私人权利的弱或外围感觉,这些感觉在概念上不那么有趣,但对法律实践却很重要,而强或中心感觉在实践中很少见,但在理论上很有趣。
{"title":"Of Brutal Murder and Transcendental Sovereignty: The Meaning of Vested Private Rights","authors":"A. MacLeod","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2810162","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2810162","url":null,"abstract":"The idea of vested private rights divides those who practice law from those who teach and think about law. On one side of the divide, practicing lawyers act as though (at least some) rights exist and exert binding obligation upon private persons and government officials. On the other side of the divide, scholars of law and jurisprudence have generally proceeded, since at least the rise of English positivism in the nineteenth century and the American legal realist movement in the early twentieth, as if the concept of vested right has little real meaning. This article attempts to explain the doctrine’s continued appeal and to discern some coherence in it while also accounting for the causes of skepticism.The approach is made by way of a central case study: the right of emancipation on free English soil. The study suggests a coherent, focal meaning of the vested private right as a norm that imposes a conclusive duty upon a duty-bearer or class of duty-bearers, and which constrains public officials’ powers to recognize, change, or adjudicate private rights and duties. This focal meaning suggests that central instances of vested rights are quite rare. This accounts for skepticism of the concept. Yet it also suggests that less-central instances of vested rights are rather common. This accounts for the concept’s practical appeal and enables one to distinguish weak or peripheral senses of vested private rights, which are not as conceptually interesting but are nevertheless significant for the practice of law, from strong or central senses, which are rare in practice but theoretically interesting.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"41 1","pages":"253"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2016-07-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68342956","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Delegation Reconsidered: A Delegation Doctrine for the Modern Administrative State 重新思考授权:现代行政国家的授权理论
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2016-03-02 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.2741208
R. Cass
The delegation doctrine — holding that legislative authority cannot be ceded to executive or judicial officers — long has been accepted as a common-sense statement of the proposition that the constitutional design of separated powers for more than a century. Yet despite its broad acceptance as a doctrine that is consistent with the structure and text of the Constitution, it effectively is treated as simply a notional, not a realistic, constraint. Recent opinions from Justices Samuel Alito and Clarence Thomas, however, pointedly expressed concern about legislated grants of expansive authority to make rules regulating private conduct. These opinions provide an occasion for reexamining how much the Constitution’s division of and limitations on power traditionally assumed to be “legislative” can and should be judicially enforceable.If the constitutional structure is to be preserved, an enforceable delegation doctrine is needed, but the current doctrine — which turns on the scope of a legislative assignment of authority — will not work. Focusing instead first and foremost on the nature of the authority granted and its connection to the constitutional competence of the officials or bodies authorized to exercise discretionary power can provide a path to reinvigorating separation of powers protections.
一个多世纪以来,授权原则——认为立法权不能割让给行政官员或司法官员——一直被认为是对分立权力的宪法设计的常识性陈述。然而,尽管它被广泛接受为一种与宪法的结构和文本相一致的学说,但它实际上只是被视为一种概念上的约束,而不是一种现实的约束。然而,法官塞缪尔·阿利托(Samuel Alito)和克拉伦斯·托马斯(Clarence Thomas)最近的意见尖锐地表达了对立法授予广泛权力来制定规范私人行为的规则的担忧。这些意见为重新审视传统上被认为是“立法”的宪法对权力的划分和限制在多大程度上能够而且应该在司法上得到执行提供了机会。如果要保留宪法结构,就需要一种可执行的授权原则,但目前的原则——它开启了立法授权的范围——将不起作用。相反,首先关注所授予权力的性质及其与被授权行使自由裁量权的官员或机构的宪法权限的联系,可以提供一条恢复三权分立保护的途径。
{"title":"Delegation Reconsidered: A Delegation Doctrine for the Modern Administrative State","authors":"R. Cass","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.2741208","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2741208","url":null,"abstract":"The delegation doctrine — holding that legislative authority cannot be ceded to executive or judicial officers — long has been accepted as a common-sense statement of the proposition that the constitutional design of separated powers for more than a century. Yet despite its broad acceptance as a doctrine that is consistent with the structure and text of the Constitution, it effectively is treated as simply a notional, not a realistic, constraint. Recent opinions from Justices Samuel Alito and Clarence Thomas, however, pointedly expressed concern about legislated grants of expansive authority to make rules regulating private conduct. These opinions provide an occasion for reexamining how much the Constitution’s division of and limitations on power traditionally assumed to be “legislative” can and should be judicially enforceable.If the constitutional structure is to be preserved, an enforceable delegation doctrine is needed, but the current doctrine — which turns on the scope of a legislative assignment of authority — will not work. Focusing instead first and foremost on the nature of the authority granted and its connection to the constitutional competence of the officials or bodies authorized to exercise discretionary power can provide a path to reinvigorating separation of powers protections.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"40 1","pages":"147"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2016-03-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/ssrn.2741208","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68282283","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 5
Why are There So Few Conservatives and Libertarians in Legal Academia? An Empirical Exploration of Three Hypotheses 为什么法学学界的保守派和自由主义者如此之少?三个假设的实证探索
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2016-01-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2695634
J. Phillips
There are few conservatives and libertarians in legal academia. Why? Three explanations are usually provided: the Brainpower, Interest, and Greed Hypotheses. Alternatively, it could be because of Discrimination. This paper explores these possibilities by looking at citation and publication rates by law professors at the 16 highest-ranked law schools in the country. Using regression analysis, propensity score matching, propensity score reweighting, nearest neighbor matching, and coarsened exact matching, this paper finds that after taking into account traditional correlates of scholarly ability, conservative and libertarian law professors are cited more and publish more than their peers. The paper also finds that they tend to have more of the traditional qualifications required of law professors than their peers, with a few exceptions. This paper indicates that, at least in the schools sampled, conservative and libertarian law professors are not few in number because of a lack of scholarly ability or professional qualifications. Further, the patterns do not prove, but are consistent with, a story of discrimination. The downsides to having so few conservatives and libertarians in the legal academy are also briefly explored.
法律界几乎没有保守派和自由意志主义者。为什么?通常有三种解释:脑力假说、兴趣假说和贪婪假说。或者,这可能是因为歧视。本文通过观察全国排名最高的16所法学院的法学教授的引用和发表率来探讨这些可能性。运用回归分析、倾向得分匹配、倾向得分重加权、最近邻匹配和粗化精确匹配等方法,发现在考虑学术能力的传统相关因素后,保守派和自由主义法学教授的被引率和发表量均高于其同行。论文还发现,除了少数例外,他们往往比同龄人拥有更多法律教授所需的传统资格。本文指出,至少在抽样的学校中,由于缺乏学术能力或专业资格,保守派和自由主义法学教授的数量并不少。此外,这些模式并没有证明,但与歧视的故事是一致的。此外,本文还简要探讨了法律学院中保守派和自由意志主义者如此之少的弊端。
{"title":"Why are There So Few Conservatives and Libertarians in Legal Academia? An Empirical Exploration of Three Hypotheses","authors":"J. Phillips","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2695634","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2695634","url":null,"abstract":"There are few conservatives and libertarians in legal academia. Why? Three explanations are usually provided: the Brainpower, Interest, and Greed Hypotheses. Alternatively, it could be because of Discrimination. This paper explores these possibilities by looking at citation and publication rates by law professors at the 16 highest-ranked law schools in the country. Using regression analysis, propensity score matching, propensity score reweighting, nearest neighbor matching, and coarsened exact matching, this paper finds that after taking into account traditional correlates of scholarly ability, conservative and libertarian law professors are cited more and publish more than their peers. The paper also finds that they tend to have more of the traditional qualifications required of law professors than their peers, with a few exceptions. This paper indicates that, at least in the schools sampled, conservative and libertarian law professors are not few in number because of a lack of scholarly ability or professional qualifications. Further, the patterns do not prove, but are consistent with, a story of discrimination. The downsides to having so few conservatives and libertarians in the legal academy are also briefly explored.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"39 1","pages":"153"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2016-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.2695634","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68259951","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
期刊
Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1