首页 > 最新文献

Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy最新文献

英文 中文
Delegation and Judicial Review 授权与司法覆核
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2010-01-01 DOI: 10.7916/D81J99CX
T. Merrill
One of the subthemes in the delegation debate concerns the importance of judicial review. The Supreme Court has often upheld broad delegations to administrative actors and in so doing has pointed out that judicial review is available to safeguard citizens from the abuse of unconstrained government power. (1) Broad delegations of power to executive actors are constitutionally permissible, the Court has suggested, in significant part because courts stand ready to assure citizens that the executive will discharge its discretion in a manner consistent with Congress's mandate and in a fashion that otherwise satisfies the requirements of reasoned decision making. (2) Administrative law professors have underscored this point. Professor Kenneth Culp Davis, in his inimitable style, took the theme to the utmost extreme. He argued that what is really significant about the nondelegation doctrine is not that Congress must provide an intelligible principle, but that judicial review is available to make sure that administrative agencies follow the principle. (3) What matters is that someone, somewhere, supplies a standard for the exercise of administrative discretion and that the courts can enforce this standard. (4) It does not really matter where the standard comes from. Congress might supply it, but so too might an agency or even a court. The important thing is to have some standard to control discretion, plus judicial review. The Court rejected this particular idea in Whitman v. American Trucking Associations. (5) Justice Scalia, writing for the Court, dismissed as "internally contradictory" the notion that an agency could cure a nondelegation problem by adopting a self-limiting standard. (6) As he explained: "The very choice of which portion of the power to exercise--that is to say, the prescription of the standard that Congress had omitted--would itself be an exercise of the forbidden legislative authority." (7) What has been less noticed about American Trucking is that the Court, having interred the self-limiting-standards idea, also omitted the ritual bow to judicial review as an important safeguard against abuses of broad delegations. To be sure, the Court reaffirmed that the question whether a statute violates the nondelegation doctrine is for the courts to decide. (8) And the Court engaged in vigorous judicial review of the agency decision that triggered the nondelegation challenge, holding that the agency's decision was unreasonable. (9) But neither Justice Scalia nor any of the concurring Justices said that the availability of judicial review was itself a relevant element in resolving the delegation challenge. Which leads to my topic: What is the role of judicial review in determining the constitutionality of broad delegations of power in a world in which the intelligible principle doctrine is, for practical purposes, dead? To make this question concrete, let me describe a petition for certiorari recently denied by the Supreme Court in County of El
代表团辩论的一个分主题涉及司法审查的重要性。最高法院经常支持对行政行为者的广泛授权,并在这样做时指出,司法审查可以保护公民不受不受约束的政府权力的滥用。(1)法院认为,宪法允许将权力广泛授权给行政行为者,这在很大程度上是因为法院随时准备向公民保证,行政部门将以符合国会授权的方式、以满足理性决策要求的方式行使其自由裁量权。行政法教授强调了这一点。肯尼斯·卡尔普·戴维斯教授以其独特的风格,将这一主题发挥到了极致。他认为,非授权原则真正重要的不是国会必须提供一个可理解的原则,而是司法审查可以确保行政机构遵循这一原则。(3)重要的是某人在某地为行政自由裁量权的行使提供了一个标准,法院可以执行这个标准。(4)标准从何而来并不重要。国会可以提供,但机构甚至法院也可以提供。重要的是要有一些标准来控制自由裁量权,加上司法审查。在惠特曼诉美国卡车运输协会案中,法院驳回了这一特殊想法。(5)大法官斯卡利亚(Justice Scalia)在为最高法院撰写的意见书中,认为一个机构可以通过采用自我限制的标准来解决不授权的问题,这种观点是“内部矛盾的”。(6)正如他所解释的那样:“选择行使哪一部分权力——也就是说,国会省略的标准规定——本身就是对被禁止的立法权的行使。”(7)关于美国卡车运输,很少有人注意到的是,法院在解释自我限制标准的想法时,也省略了接受司法审查的仪式,这是防止滥用广泛授权的重要保障。当然,法院重申,成文法是否违反不授权原则的问题应由法院决定。(8)法院对引发非授权质疑的机关决定进行了有力的司法审查,认为机关的决定是不合理的。(9)但是,斯卡利亚大法官和任何持同意意见的大法官都没有说,司法审查本身是解决授权挑战的一个相关因素。这就引出了我的话题:在一个可理解的原则学说实际上已经死亡的世界里,司法审查在确定广泛授权的合宪性方面的作用是什么?为了使这个问题具体化,让我来描述最近在埃尔帕索县诉纳波利塔诺案中被最高法院驳回的调卷请求。(10)请愿书是由耶鲁大学法学院最高法院诊所于2008年12月提出的,我目前是该诊所的主管。2009年6月15日,在会议重新列出请愿书七次之后,法院驳回了调卷请求。(12)一如往常,法院没有对拒绝作出解释。请愿书对1996年《非法移民改革和移民责任法案》(IIRIRA)的修正案提出了质疑,该修正案指示国土安全部长在墨西哥和美国之间的部分边境地区建立一道屏障,以帮助控制非法进入美国的人。(14)国会力图确保篱笆能尽快建成,特别是确保这个价值数百万美元的建筑工程不会因诉讼而陷入困境。为了实现这一目标,国会于2005年修订了IIRIRA。(15)经修订的法规在第102(c)条中授权国土安全部长“根据其自行判断,放弃为确保迅速建造[围栏]所必需的所有法律要求”。…
{"title":"Delegation and Judicial Review","authors":"T. Merrill","doi":"10.7916/D81J99CX","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.7916/D81J99CX","url":null,"abstract":"One of the subthemes in the delegation debate concerns the importance of judicial review. The Supreme Court has often upheld broad delegations to administrative actors and in so doing has pointed out that judicial review is available to safeguard citizens from the abuse of unconstrained government power. (1) Broad delegations of power to executive actors are constitutionally permissible, the Court has suggested, in significant part because courts stand ready to assure citizens that the executive will discharge its discretion in a manner consistent with Congress's mandate and in a fashion that otherwise satisfies the requirements of reasoned decision making. (2) Administrative law professors have underscored this point. Professor Kenneth Culp Davis, in his inimitable style, took the theme to the utmost extreme. He argued that what is really significant about the nondelegation doctrine is not that Congress must provide an intelligible principle, but that judicial review is available to make sure that administrative agencies follow the principle. (3) What matters is that someone, somewhere, supplies a standard for the exercise of administrative discretion and that the courts can enforce this standard. (4) It does not really matter where the standard comes from. Congress might supply it, but so too might an agency or even a court. The important thing is to have some standard to control discretion, plus judicial review. The Court rejected this particular idea in Whitman v. American Trucking Associations. (5) Justice Scalia, writing for the Court, dismissed as \"internally contradictory\" the notion that an agency could cure a nondelegation problem by adopting a self-limiting standard. (6) As he explained: \"The very choice of which portion of the power to exercise--that is to say, the prescription of the standard that Congress had omitted--would itself be an exercise of the forbidden legislative authority.\" (7) What has been less noticed about American Trucking is that the Court, having interred the self-limiting-standards idea, also omitted the ritual bow to judicial review as an important safeguard against abuses of broad delegations. To be sure, the Court reaffirmed that the question whether a statute violates the nondelegation doctrine is for the courts to decide. (8) And the Court engaged in vigorous judicial review of the agency decision that triggered the nondelegation challenge, holding that the agency's decision was unreasonable. (9) But neither Justice Scalia nor any of the concurring Justices said that the availability of judicial review was itself a relevant element in resolving the delegation challenge. Which leads to my topic: What is the role of judicial review in determining the constitutionality of broad delegations of power in a world in which the intelligible principle doctrine is, for practical purposes, dead? To make this question concrete, let me describe a petition for certiorari recently denied by the Supreme Court in County of El","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"33 1","pages":"73-85"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2010-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71363745","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Legislative Delegation, the Unitary Presidency, and the Legitimacy of the Administrative State 立法授权、一元制总统制与行政国家的合法性
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2010-01-01 DOI: 10.31228/osf.io/zyqrd
P. Shane
This essay focuses on the relationship between non-delegation doctrine and so-called unitary executive theory. It argues that, if the Supreme Court were to embrace unitary executive theory without, as is highly unlikely, tightening up on the non-delegation doctrine, the result would be a constitutional disaster in terms of reduced executive branch legal and political accountability. Increasing the legitimacy of the administrative state ought to involve more, not fewer mechanisms that subject the exercise of presidential power to effective checks and balances.
本文主要研究非授权理论与所谓的统一执行理论之间的关系。它认为,如果最高法院接受单一行政理论,而不收紧非授权原则(这是极不可能的),那么就减少行政部门的法律和政治责任而言,结果将是一场宪法灾难。提高行政国家的合法性应该包括更多而不是更少的机制,使总统权力的行使受到有效的制衡。
{"title":"Legislative Delegation, the Unitary Presidency, and the Legitimacy of the Administrative State","authors":"P. Shane","doi":"10.31228/osf.io/zyqrd","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.31228/osf.io/zyqrd","url":null,"abstract":"This essay focuses on the relationship between non-delegation doctrine and so-called unitary executive theory. It argues that, if the Supreme Court were to embrace unitary executive theory without, as is highly unlikely, tightening up on the non-delegation doctrine, the result would be a constitutional disaster in terms of reduced executive branch legal and political accountability. Increasing the legitimacy of the administrative state ought to involve more, not fewer mechanisms that subject the exercise of presidential power to effective checks and balances.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"33 1","pages":"103"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2010-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"69641282","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
THE WAR POWER 战争力量
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2009-10-14 DOI: 10.2307/j.ctv173f229.8
M. Paulsen
This short paper attempts to set forth a comprehensive, but brief, overview of the Constitution's allocation of war powers and to apply those lessons to the most signal, controversial issues of recent and current war practice: control of the decision to go to war; control over war-execution in all respects, including capture, interrogation, detention, and military punishment of enemy combatants (lawful and unlawful); interception of communications with the enemy; judicial constitutional interpretations touching on (and interfering with) the Constitution's allocation of war powers. The Constitution's allocation of war powers is a classic application of the Framers’ reliance on separation of powers in the constitutional design. The Framers regarded the war power as too important to be vested in a single set of hands and so, by conscious design, divided it and allocated portions of that power to various branches, giving some powers exclusively to each branch and also providing for some areas of overlap - and thus shared authority - among them of powers. First, the Constitution vests, in the main, in Congress, and not in the President, the decision to initiate war - the authority to take the nation into a state of war. Second, the Constitution vests in the President, and not in Congress, the power to conduct war. Each of these powers is, in the main, autonomous of the powers of the other branch and thus to a substantial degree immune from control by the other’s powers. Third, the Constitution vest no substantive war powers in the judiciary. But questions of the Constitution’s allocation of war powers nonetheless can be judicial questions. This does not mean that everything that the courts will decide on such matters is right. Nor does it mean even that everything that the courts say should be followed by the other branches of government. (Another aspect of the separation of powers is that the Framers regarded the power to interpret law - the power of constitutional interpretation - as another power too important to vest exclusively in any one branch of government. It too - like the war power - is a divided, shared power.) The political branches thus rightfully may use the constitutional powers at their disposal to resist judicial encroachments on the Constitution’s assignments of war powers to them. The power to authorize war properly rests with Congress, but Congress has exercised that power to grant the President enormous discretion to wage war. The Authorization to Use Military Force (AUMF) of September 18, 2001 is the broadest declaration of war in our nation's history, lawfully delegating to the President sweeping authority to use force against a wide array of enemies. Coupled with statutes like the Military Commissions Act of 2006 (MCA), Congress has added practically all of the war powers within its control to the President, and even endorsed a surprisingly pro-presidentialist view of the Constitution's allocation of powers. The Commander in C
这篇短文试图对宪法对战争权力的分配进行全面而简短的概述,并将这些经验教训应用于最近和当前战争实践中最具标志性、最具争议的问题:对开战决定的控制;控制战争执行的所有方面,包括俘虏、审讯、拘留和对敌方战斗人员的军事惩罚(合法和非法);拦截:拦截与敌人的通信;司法宪法解释触及(并干涉)宪法对战争权力的分配。宪法对战争权力的分配是制宪者在宪法设计中对三权分立的依赖的经典应用。制宪者认为战争权力太重要了,不能交给一群人,因此,通过有意识的设计,将它分开,并将部分权力分配给各个部门,将一些权力专门赋予每个部门,并规定了一些重叠的领域,从而在权力之间共享权力。首先,宪法赋予国会而不是总统发动战争的决定权——使国家进入战争状态的权力。第二,宪法赋予总统而不是国会发动战争的权力。这些权力中的每一个基本上都是独立于其他分支的权力的,因此在很大程度上不受其他权力的控制。第三,宪法没有赋予司法部门实质性的战争权力。但是,宪法对战争权力的分配问题仍然可以是司法问题。这并不意味着法院在这类问题上的所有裁决都是正确的。这也不意味着法院所说的一切都应该被政府的其他部门所遵循。(三权分立的另一个方面是,制宪者认为解释法律的权力——宪法解释权——是另一种过于重要的权力,不能只赋予任何一个政府部门。它也像战争权力一样,是一种分裂的、共享的权力。)因此,政治部门可以正当地使用宪法赋予它们的权力来抵制对宪法赋予它们的战争权力的司法侵犯。正确授权战争的权力属于国会,但国会行使这一权力赋予总统发动战争的巨大自由裁量权。2001年9月18日的授权使用军事力量(AUMF)是我国历史上最广泛的宣战,合法地授予总统对各种敌人使用武力的广泛权力。再加上《2006年军事委员会法案》(MCA)等法规,国会几乎将其控制范围内的所有战争权力都赋予了总统,甚至出人意料地支持了宪法权力分配的亲总统主义观点。总统的总司令权力条款,如果得到正确理解,就赋予总统在战争行为方面基本上拥有美国宪法赋予的全部权力。这是一种可怕而可怕的权力,但它是发动战争的权力的本质和制宪者决定将军事指挥权授予一个人的固有权力。总统,而不是国会,决定何时何地攻击,攻击谁,攻击的难度,战略和战术目标是什么,以及何时停止战斗。(或者根本不打仗:总统的行政和总司令权力赋予他几乎完全的权力宣布和平,作为他对战争行为的唯一酌处权的一个事件)。总统,而不是国会,决定如何处理俘虏、拘留、审讯、对违反战争法的敌方战斗人员的军事惩罚等问题。他决定如何拦截敌人的通讯。他行使解释和适用国际法的权力,以行使发动战争的权力。最直白地说,“总司令”条款的权力意味着,总统而不是国会拥有宪法权力,可以决定是否对敌方武装部队(无论是合法的还是非法的)成员进行杀害、俘虏、关押、审讯、给予或拒绝国际法保护,甚至是酷刑。最高法院最近的判决在几个方面背离了宪法对战争权力的分配。就他们这样做的程度而言,这些决定对国家政府的其他部门没有宪法约束力。
{"title":"THE WAR POWER","authors":"M. Paulsen","doi":"10.2307/j.ctv173f229.8","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2307/j.ctv173f229.8","url":null,"abstract":"This short paper attempts to set forth a comprehensive, but brief, overview of the Constitution's allocation of war powers and to apply those lessons to the most signal, controversial issues of recent and current war practice: control of the decision to go to war; control over war-execution in all respects, including capture, interrogation, detention, and military punishment of enemy combatants (lawful and unlawful); interception of communications with the enemy; judicial constitutional interpretations touching on (and interfering with) the Constitution's allocation of war powers. The Constitution's allocation of war powers is a classic application of the Framers’ reliance on separation of powers in the constitutional design. The Framers regarded the war power as too important to be vested in a single set of hands and so, by conscious design, divided it and allocated portions of that power to various branches, giving some powers exclusively to each branch and also providing for some areas of overlap - and thus shared authority - among them of powers. First, the Constitution vests, in the main, in Congress, and not in the President, the decision to initiate war - the authority to take the nation into a state of war. Second, the Constitution vests in the President, and not in Congress, the power to conduct war. Each of these powers is, in the main, autonomous of the powers of the other branch and thus to a substantial degree immune from control by the other’s powers. Third, the Constitution vest no substantive war powers in the judiciary. But questions of the Constitution’s allocation of war powers nonetheless can be judicial questions. This does not mean that everything that the courts will decide on such matters is right. Nor does it mean even that everything that the courts say should be followed by the other branches of government. (Another aspect of the separation of powers is that the Framers regarded the power to interpret law - the power of constitutional interpretation - as another power too important to vest exclusively in any one branch of government. It too - like the war power - is a divided, shared power.) The political branches thus rightfully may use the constitutional powers at their disposal to resist judicial encroachments on the Constitution’s assignments of war powers to them. The power to authorize war properly rests with Congress, but Congress has exercised that power to grant the President enormous discretion to wage war. The Authorization to Use Military Force (AUMF) of September 18, 2001 is the broadest declaration of war in our nation's history, lawfully delegating to the President sweeping authority to use force against a wide array of enemies. Coupled with statutes like the Military Commissions Act of 2006 (MCA), Congress has added practically all of the war powers within its control to the President, and even endorsed a surprisingly pro-presidentialist view of the Constitution's allocation of powers. The Commander in C","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"33 1","pages":"113"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2009-10-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68782784","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 5
National Security and the Rule of Law 国家安全和法治
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2009-06-22 DOI: 10.5040/9780755612390.ch-007
M. B. Mukasey
I have long had a deep respect for the Federalist Society and for its principles, and so I feel particularly privileged to be at this podium tonight. For over twenty-five years, the members of this Society have committed themselves to vigorous and open debate about the pressing legal issues of our day and how they ought to be resolved under the constant and durable provisions of our Constitution. The Federalist Society is committed to taking the Constitution seriously and understanding it to be a legal document, rather than an empty vessel to be filled by the policy preferences of those who happen to be wielding the pen at any given moment. On this evening, I want to applaud your contributions to the nation's legal culture and your efforts particularly over the past eight years to elevate the discourse surrounding the most important legal and policy issues facing our nation. It is my privilege to be here tonight with such distinguished guests, including members of the Supreme Court and the rest of the judiciary. There are also dozens of lawyers here who have served their country during this Administration, some of whom have now returned to the private sector and some of whom I have had the pleasure of working with during my tenure at the Justice Department. There are likely others in attendance who will have the opportunity to serve in the new Administration, all of which is a testament to those who founded this Society and who have a great deal to be proud of. The principles of the Society you founded have inspired a generation of lawyers and are now inspiring the next generation. As we near the end of this Administration and as we approach the first transition that our government has seen since the attacks of September 11, 2001, I would like to focus on the successes of this Administration that relate to matters that concern this Society, the legacy that will remain when this Administration leaves office, and on a matter relating to our national security that I think should continue to receive the attention of this Society. Perhaps of most obvious interest to the members of the Federalist Society are the judges and Justices whom the President has appointed to the federal bench. As the President recently explained to the Cincinnati chapter of this Society, he has sought out "judges who would faithfully interpret the Constitution-not use the courts to invent laws or dictate social policy." (1) With the help of many in this room, the President has succeeded in this effort and appointed many well-qualified and accomplished judges who have understood their role in interpreting--not writing--the laws. Most notably, the President has appointed two members of the Supreme Court, Chief Justice John Roberts and Justice Samuel Alito. These men are no strangers to the people in this room--indeed, they both spoke to this Society last year. Both of these remarkably accomplished Justices will continue to serve the Nation for many years to come, and we are grat
长期以来,我一直对联邦党人协会及其原则怀有深深的敬意,因此今晚能够站在这个讲台上,我感到特别荣幸。25年来,本协会的成员一直致力于就当今紧迫的法律问题进行积极和公开的辩论,以及如何根据我国《宪法》一贯和持久的规定来解决这些问题。联邦党人协会致力于认真对待《宪法》,并将其理解为一份法律文件,而不是一个空容器,由那些碰巧在任何特定时刻挥舞着笔的人的政策偏好来填充。今晚,我想赞扬你们对国家法律文化的贡献,以及你们在过去八年中为提升围绕我国面临的最重要的法律和政策问题的讨论所做的努力。我很荣幸今晚能在这里与这些尊贵的客人们在一起,包括最高法院的成员和其他司法人员。这里还有几十位在本届政府期间为国家服务的律师,其中一些人现在已经回到私营部门,其中一些人在我在司法部任职期间曾有幸与他们共事。很可能还有其他人出席,他们将有机会在新政府中服务,所有这些都是对本协会的创立者和有很多值得骄傲的人的证明。您创立的协会的原则激励了一代律师,现在正在激励下一代。在本届政府即将结束之际,在我们即将迎来自2001年9月11日恐怖袭击以来我国政府的第一次过渡之际,我想重点谈谈本届政府在与这个社会有关的问题上取得的成就,在本届政府离任后将留下的遗产,以及我认为应该继续受到这个社会关注的一个与我们国家安全有关的问题。联邦党人协会成员最感兴趣的可能是总统任命的联邦法官和大法官。正如总统最近向该协会辛辛那提分会解释的那样,他一直在寻找“忠实地解释宪法的法官,而不是利用法院来制定法律或规定社会政策。”(1)在在座许多人的帮助下,总统在这方面取得了成功,他任命了许多称职、有成就的法官,这些法官了解自己在解释——而不是撰写——法律方面的作用。最值得注意的是,总统任命了两名最高法院成员,首席大法官约翰·罗伯茨和大法官塞缪尔·阿利托。对于在座的各位来说,这两个人并不陌生——事实上,他们两人去年都曾在本协会发表过演讲。这两位杰出的大法官将在未来的许多年里继续为国家服务,我们不仅感谢他们的服务,也感谢他们对最高法院每届任期面临的宪法和法律解释难题的处理方法。总统有理由为他选择了这两个人而感到自豪,联邦党人协会也应该为它在支持他们的提名中所起的作用感到自豪。总统还提名了许多其他合格的联邦法院法官,并得到参议院的批准。不幸的是,还有一些优秀的、很有资格的人被剥夺了同样的机会。我们已经看到有经验、有经验和受人尊敬的候选人的提名由于程序性策略而被推迟或受挫。通常,这些被提名者很难在参议院获得投票,甚至很难在司法委员会举行听证会。对于那些从未得到投票甚至听证的人,我深表遗憾。你应该得到更好的。然而,今晚,我们应该注意到我们的成功。…
{"title":"National Security and the Rule of Law","authors":"M. B. Mukasey","doi":"10.5040/9780755612390.ch-007","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5040/9780755612390.ch-007","url":null,"abstract":"I have long had a deep respect for the Federalist Society and for its principles, and so I feel particularly privileged to be at this podium tonight. For over twenty-five years, the members of this Society have committed themselves to vigorous and open debate about the pressing legal issues of our day and how they ought to be resolved under the constant and durable provisions of our Constitution. The Federalist Society is committed to taking the Constitution seriously and understanding it to be a legal document, rather than an empty vessel to be filled by the policy preferences of those who happen to be wielding the pen at any given moment. On this evening, I want to applaud your contributions to the nation's legal culture and your efforts particularly over the past eight years to elevate the discourse surrounding the most important legal and policy issues facing our nation. It is my privilege to be here tonight with such distinguished guests, including members of the Supreme Court and the rest of the judiciary. There are also dozens of lawyers here who have served their country during this Administration, some of whom have now returned to the private sector and some of whom I have had the pleasure of working with during my tenure at the Justice Department. There are likely others in attendance who will have the opportunity to serve in the new Administration, all of which is a testament to those who founded this Society and who have a great deal to be proud of. The principles of the Society you founded have inspired a generation of lawyers and are now inspiring the next generation. As we near the end of this Administration and as we approach the first transition that our government has seen since the attacks of September 11, 2001, I would like to focus on the successes of this Administration that relate to matters that concern this Society, the legacy that will remain when this Administration leaves office, and on a matter relating to our national security that I think should continue to receive the attention of this Society. Perhaps of most obvious interest to the members of the Federalist Society are the judges and Justices whom the President has appointed to the federal bench. As the President recently explained to the Cincinnati chapter of this Society, he has sought out \"judges who would faithfully interpret the Constitution-not use the courts to invent laws or dictate social policy.\" (1) With the help of many in this room, the President has succeeded in this effort and appointed many well-qualified and accomplished judges who have understood their role in interpreting--not writing--the laws. Most notably, the President has appointed two members of the Supreme Court, Chief Justice John Roberts and Justice Samuel Alito. These men are no strangers to the people in this room--indeed, they both spoke to this Society last year. Both of these remarkably accomplished Justices will continue to serve the Nation for many years to come, and we are grat","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"32 1","pages":"831"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2009-06-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"70497811","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
Reviving Necessity in Eminent Domain 恢复征用权中的必要性
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2009-05-22 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.1409383
R. Bird
The necessity doctrine states that a condemnor may only take property via eminent domain that is necessary for furthering a proposed public use. With the advent of the Kelo v. City of New London decision and its deferential treatment of public use, necessity remains one of the few existing checks on government discretion in eminent domain. This article proposes a modest revival of the dormant necessity doctrine that preserves government discretion while curbing the reckless exercise of eminent domain.
必要性原则指出,谴责者只能通过征用权取得财产,这是促进拟议的公共使用所必需的。随着“凯洛诉新伦敦市”案的判决及其对公共用途的尊重,必要性仍然是对征用权中政府自由裁量权的少数现有制约之一。本文建议适度地复兴休眠的必要性原则,该原则保留政府的自由裁量权,同时遏制鲁莽地行使征用权。
{"title":"Reviving Necessity in Eminent Domain","authors":"R. Bird","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.1409383","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.1409383","url":null,"abstract":"The necessity doctrine states that a condemnor may only take property via eminent domain that is necessary for furthering a proposed public use. With the advent of the Kelo v. City of New London decision and its deferential treatment of public use, necessity remains one of the few existing checks on government discretion in eminent domain. This article proposes a modest revival of the dormant necessity doctrine that preserves government discretion while curbing the reckless exercise of eminent domain.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"33 1","pages":"239"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2009-05-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68176945","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 7
The Conservative Case for Precedent 保守主义的先例
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2008-06-22 DOI: 10.7916/D8FJ2GC2
T. Merrill
This Essay offers some reasons why conservatives should favor giving great weight to precedent in constitutional adjudication. Let me start with some preliminary observations about the debate between originalism and precedent more generally. First, the debate has been dominated to far too great an extent by specific cases, Roe v. Wade (1) in particular. It is distressing that the only issue that has seemed to matter in recent confirmation hearings is what a nominee thinks about Roe v. Wade. Similarly, in the precedent versus originalism debate, much of the discussion--even in the law reviews--is animated by what commentators think about Roe v. Wade. So, if you think Roe v. Wade was an illegitimate usurpation of power by the judiciary, and you want to overrule it, it somehow follows that you think all constitutional law should be based on something other than precedent. On the other hand, if you like Roe v. Wade, and you want to reaffirm it, somehow all precedent must be a good thing. This is an extraordinarily myopic way of thinking about the problem. Those who regard themselves as conservatives and embrace some of the values that David Strauss mentions--the rule of law, stability and predictability in the law, judicial restraint, the belief that social policy decisions should be made by elected representatives of the people rather than by the judges (2)--should not have their views on precedent versus originalism driven by one case. Second, we cannot resolve the debate by adopting the conceptual apparatus of one school or the other, and by pointing out that the rival approach has no place within the conceptual apparatus we adopt. To a large extent, originalism and precedent reside in parallel universes that do not intersect. The case for originalism starts with legal positivism, the idea that only enacted law is the law of the land. (3) Starting from this assumption, it follows that when there is an ambiguity in the law, we should try to resolve it by determining the meaning of the lawgiver. Such an approach naturally leads to looking at original sources for interpreting the law. As Steven Calabresi implicitly frames the question, "Does originalism say that precedent can trump the enacted law?" (4) The answer, of course, is "No, it does not." If we start from originalist premises, we do not leave much room for precedent or stare decisis. Conversely, if one starts from the universe of precedent, that universe is founded in the Holmesian observation that the law is, ultimately, the judgments of the courts. (5) If you adopt this perspective, you say, "Well, what predicts the judgments of courts is the precedents of courts, and therefore precedent is law." So, if we want to know whether or not following precedent is permissible, we find the answer by looking to precedent. And guess what we find? Judges say we ought to follow precedent. So precedent it is. This universe does not leave much space for the Constitution and enacted law. Thus, we have two
这篇文章提供了为什么保守派应该赞成在宪法裁决中重视先例的一些理由。让我先对原旨主义和先例之间的争论进行一些初步观察。首先,这场辩论在很大程度上被具体案件所主导,尤其是罗伊诉韦德案(Roe v. Wade)。令人痛心的是,在最近的确认听证会上,似乎唯一重要的问题是被提名人对罗伊诉韦德案的看法。同样,在先例与原旨主义的辩论中,许多讨论——甚至在法律评论中——都受到评论员对罗伊诉韦德案的看法的影响。所以,如果你认为罗伊诉韦德案是司法部门非法篡夺权力,而你想推翻它,那么你就会认为所有宪法都应该基于先例之外的东西。另一方面,如果你喜欢罗伊诉韦德案,你想要重申它,那么所有的先例都必须是好事。这是一种极其短视的思考问题的方式。那些认为自己是保守派并信奉大卫·施特劳斯(David Strauss)所提到的一些价值观的人——法治、法律的稳定性和可预见性、司法约束、社会政策决定应该由民选的人民代表而不是法官做出的信念(2)——不应该让他们对先例与原创性的看法受到一个案例的影响。其次,我们不能通过采用一个学派或另一个学派的概念工具来解决辩论,也不能通过指出对立的方法在我们采用的概念工具中没有位置来解决辩论。在很大程度上,原创主义和先例存在于不相交的平行宇宙中。原旨主义的案例始于法律实证主义,即只有颁布的法律才是国家的法律。(3)从这一假设出发,当法律存在歧义时,我们应该尝试通过确定立法者的含义来解决它。这种方法自然会导致在解释法律时寻找原始来源。正如Steven Calabresi含蓄地提出的问题,“原旨主义是否说先例可以胜过制定的法律?”答案当然是“不,它没有”。如果我们从原旨主义的前提出发,我们就没有留下多少先例或先例的余地。相反,如果一个人从先例的宇宙出发,那么这个宇宙是建立在福尔摩斯的观察之上的,即法律最终是法院的判决。(5)如果你采用这种观点,你会说,“嗯,预测法院判决的是法院的先例,因此先例就是法律。”因此,如果我们想知道是否允许遵循先例,我们可以通过查看先例来找到答案。猜猜我们发现了什么?法官说我们应该遵循先例。这是一个先例。这个宇宙没有多少空间留给宪法和制定的法律。因此,我们有两个在不同层面上运作的平行宇宙:制定法律的宇宙和法官制定法律的宇宙。一个人不能从一个前提出发来推翻另一个前提。现实情况是,至少从马歇尔法院(Marshall Court)以来,每一位大法官在某种程度上都依赖于原旨主义的推理和先例。卡拉布雷西教授是绝对正确的,当高度戏剧性和危机的时刻出现时,法官们倾向于回归宪法文本和制宪者的声明。(6)另一方面,对大法官的研究表明,他们在宪法意见书中引用的权威中,大约有80%或更多是最高法院的先例。(7)最仔细的研究考察了伦奎斯特和布伦南法官的观点,他们在研究进行时是典型的意识形态异类。据推测,中间派法官在更大程度上依赖先例。…
{"title":"The Conservative Case for Precedent","authors":"T. Merrill","doi":"10.7916/D8FJ2GC2","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.7916/D8FJ2GC2","url":null,"abstract":"This Essay offers some reasons why conservatives should favor giving great weight to precedent in constitutional adjudication. Let me start with some preliminary observations about the debate between originalism and precedent more generally. First, the debate has been dominated to far too great an extent by specific cases, Roe v. Wade (1) in particular. It is distressing that the only issue that has seemed to matter in recent confirmation hearings is what a nominee thinks about Roe v. Wade. Similarly, in the precedent versus originalism debate, much of the discussion--even in the law reviews--is animated by what commentators think about Roe v. Wade. So, if you think Roe v. Wade was an illegitimate usurpation of power by the judiciary, and you want to overrule it, it somehow follows that you think all constitutional law should be based on something other than precedent. On the other hand, if you like Roe v. Wade, and you want to reaffirm it, somehow all precedent must be a good thing. This is an extraordinarily myopic way of thinking about the problem. Those who regard themselves as conservatives and embrace some of the values that David Strauss mentions--the rule of law, stability and predictability in the law, judicial restraint, the belief that social policy decisions should be made by elected representatives of the people rather than by the judges (2)--should not have their views on precedent versus originalism driven by one case. Second, we cannot resolve the debate by adopting the conceptual apparatus of one school or the other, and by pointing out that the rival approach has no place within the conceptual apparatus we adopt. To a large extent, originalism and precedent reside in parallel universes that do not intersect. The case for originalism starts with legal positivism, the idea that only enacted law is the law of the land. (3) Starting from this assumption, it follows that when there is an ambiguity in the law, we should try to resolve it by determining the meaning of the lawgiver. Such an approach naturally leads to looking at original sources for interpreting the law. As Steven Calabresi implicitly frames the question, \"Does originalism say that precedent can trump the enacted law?\" (4) The answer, of course, is \"No, it does not.\" If we start from originalist premises, we do not leave much room for precedent or stare decisis. Conversely, if one starts from the universe of precedent, that universe is founded in the Holmesian observation that the law is, ultimately, the judgments of the courts. (5) If you adopt this perspective, you say, \"Well, what predicts the judgments of courts is the precedents of courts, and therefore precedent is law.\" So, if we want to know whether or not following precedent is permissible, we find the answer by looking to precedent. And guess what we find? Judges say we ought to follow precedent. So precedent it is. This universe does not leave much space for the Constitution and enacted law. Thus, we have two","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"31 1","pages":"977-981"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2008-06-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71366078","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Measuring Meta-Doctrine: An Empirical Assessment of Judicial Minimalism in the Supreme Court 衡量元主义:最高法院司法极简主义的实证评估
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2007-08-29 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.1026350
Robert T. Anderson
One of the most influential recent theories of Supreme Court decision-making is Cass Sunstein's "judicial minimalism." Sunstein argues that a majority of the justices of the Rehnquist Court were "minimalists," preferring to "leave things undecided" by favoring case-by-case adjudication over ambitious judicial agendas. While many legal scholars have embraced Sunstein's argument, no piece of scholarship has attempted a quantitative empirical test of the theory. This paper develops an empirical measure for judicial minimalism and examines whether minimalism affected the opinion writing and voting of the justices in the Rehnquist and Roberts Courts. The empirical analysis supports the conclusion that judicial minimalism has a statistically significant effect on the opinions of the justices, providing the first quantitative evidence of "meta-doctrine" in the Supreme Court.
最近关于最高法院决策最有影响力的理论之一是卡斯·桑斯坦的“司法极简主义”。桑斯坦认为,伦奎斯特法院的大多数法官都是“极简主义者”,他们更喜欢“让事情悬而未决”,倾向于逐案裁决,而不是雄心勃勃的司法议程。虽然许多法律学者接受了桑斯坦的观点,但还没有学者试图对这一理论进行定量的实证检验。本文发展了司法极简主义的实证度量,并考察了极简主义是否影响了伦奎斯特和罗伯茨法院法官的意见书写作和投票。实证分析支持了司法极简主义对法官意见具有统计显著影响的结论,为最高法院的“元主义”提供了第一个定量证据。
{"title":"Measuring Meta-Doctrine: An Empirical Assessment of Judicial Minimalism in the Supreme Court","authors":"Robert T. Anderson","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.1026350","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.1026350","url":null,"abstract":"One of the most influential recent theories of Supreme Court decision-making is Cass Sunstein's \"judicial minimalism.\" Sunstein argues that a majority of the justices of the Rehnquist Court were \"minimalists,\" preferring to \"leave things undecided\" by favoring case-by-case adjudication over ambitious judicial agendas. While many legal scholars have embraced Sunstein's argument, no piece of scholarship has attempted a quantitative empirical test of the theory. This paper develops an empirical measure for judicial minimalism and examines whether minimalism affected the opinion writing and voting of the justices in the Rehnquist and Roberts Courts. The empirical analysis supports the conclusion that judicial minimalism has a statistically significant effect on the opinions of the justices, providing the first quantitative evidence of \"meta-doctrine\" in the Supreme Court.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"32 1","pages":"1045"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2007-08-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68129950","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Can States Tax National Banks to Educate Consumers About Predatory Lending Practices 各州能否向国家银行征税以教育消费者了解掠夺性贷款行为
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2007-01-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.961273
H. Jackson, S. A. Anderson
Over the past quarter century, consumer lending markets in the United States have become increasingly national in scope with large national banks and other federally chartered institutions playing an ever important role in many sectors, including credit card lending and home mortgages. At the same time, a series of court decisions have ruled that a wide range of state laws regulating credit card abuses and predatory mortgage lending practices are preempted at least as applied to national banks and other federally chartered institutions. Given the dominant role of federal institutions in our country's lending markets, these rulings have narrowed the capacity of states to police local lending transactions. As an alternative to direct regulation, the California Assembly recently considered legislation designed to improve consumer understanding of financial transactions through educational efforts to be financed by a new state tax on income from certain problematic loans made to California residents by financial institutions, including national banks and other federally chartered institutions. In this Article, we consider whether a tax of the sort proposed in California could survive a preemption challenge under recent court rulings as well as other potential constitutional attacks. While the States have quite limited powers to regulate federally chartered financial institutions, Congress in 12 U.S.C. Section 548 explicitly authorizes states to tax national banks. We explore the scope of state taxing authority that Section 548 and the relationship between that authority and recent preemption rulings After reviewing a range of legal precedents, we conclude that a state tax of the sort considered in California - which imposes modest levies on federally chartered entities but does not prevent these from engaging in otherwise authorized activities - should qualify as a legitimate exercise of state taxing powers under 12 U.S.C. Section 548 and also should withstand scrutiny under the Due Process and Commerce Clauses to the extent the tax is imposed on out-of-state banks.
在过去的四分之一个世纪里,美国的消费贷款市场已经变得越来越全国性,大型全国性银行和其他联邦特许机构在许多领域发挥着越来越重要的作用,包括信用卡贷款和住房抵押贷款。与此同时,一系列法院判决裁定,监管信用卡滥用和掠夺性抵押贷款行为的范围广泛的州法律,至少在适用于国民银行和其他联邦特许机构时是优先适用的。鉴于联邦机构在我国贷款市场中的主导作用,这些裁决缩小了各州监管地方贷款交易的能力。作为直接监管的替代方案,加州议会最近考虑了一项立法,旨在通过教育努力提高消费者对金融交易的理解,资金来源是对金融机构(包括国家银行和其他联邦特许机构)向加州居民提供的某些问题贷款征收新的州税。在本文中,我们将考虑加州提出的这种税收是否能够在最近的法院裁决以及其他潜在的宪法攻击下经受住先发制人的挑战。虽然各州在监管联邦特许金融机构方面的权力相当有限,但国会在《美国法典》第12章第548节中明确授权各州向全国性银行征税。在回顾了一系列法律先例后,我们探讨了第548条规定的州税务机关的范围以及该机关与最近的优先购买权裁决之间的关系。我们得出的结论是,加州考虑的那种州税——对联邦特许实体征收适度的税收,但不阻止这些实体从事其他授权的活动——应该符合《美国法典》第12卷第548节规定的州征税权力的合法行使,并且在对州外银行征税的程度上,也应该经得起正当程序和商业条款的审查。
{"title":"Can States Tax National Banks to Educate Consumers About Predatory Lending Practices","authors":"H. Jackson, S. A. Anderson","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.961273","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.961273","url":null,"abstract":"Over the past quarter century, consumer lending markets in the United States have become increasingly national in scope with large national banks and other federally chartered institutions playing an ever important role in many sectors, including credit card lending and home mortgages. At the same time, a series of court decisions have ruled that a wide range of state laws regulating credit card abuses and predatory mortgage lending practices are preempted at least as applied to national banks and other federally chartered institutions. Given the dominant role of federal institutions in our country's lending markets, these rulings have narrowed the capacity of states to police local lending transactions. As an alternative to direct regulation, the California Assembly recently considered legislation designed to improve consumer understanding of financial transactions through educational efforts to be financed by a new state tax on income from certain problematic loans made to California residents by financial institutions, including national banks and other federally chartered institutions. In this Article, we consider whether a tax of the sort proposed in California could survive a preemption challenge under recent court rulings as well as other potential constitutional attacks. While the States have quite limited powers to regulate federally chartered financial institutions, Congress in 12 U.S.C. Section 548 explicitly authorizes states to tax national banks. We explore the scope of state taxing authority that Section 548 and the relationship between that authority and recent preemption rulings After reviewing a range of legal precedents, we conclude that a state tax of the sort considered in California - which imposes modest levies on federally chartered entities but does not prevent these from engaging in otherwise authorized activities - should qualify as a legitimate exercise of state taxing powers under 12 U.S.C. Section 548 and also should withstand scrutiny under the Due Process and Commerce Clauses to the extent the tax is imposed on out-of-state banks.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"141 1","pages":"831"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2007-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67911431","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 5
The Rule of International Law 国际法规则
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2006-09-22 DOI: 10.5040/9781472562494.ch-014
Jeremy Waldron
I. This Article will focus on how one should think about the rule of law in the international arena. Asking about the rule of law in the international arena is not just asking whether there is such a thing as international law, or what it is, or what we think of particular treaties (such as human rights covenants), or of the value of customary international law, or of the enforceability of international law in our own courts. The phrase "the rule of law" brings to mind a particular set of values and principles associated with the idea of legality. (1) These values and principles are the ancient focus of our allegiance as lawyers. The rule of law is one of the most important sources of the dignity and honor of the legal profession, and an awareness of the principles and values that it comprises ought to be part of all lawyers' professional ethos, something that disciplines the spirit and attitude that lawyers bring to their work. True, the rule of law is not the only value that lawyers serve. Lawyers must serve justice too, for justice is part of law's promise. (2) And, of course, lawyers serve the interests of their clients and of society generally. But the rule of law constrains lawyers in their pursuit of these other goals: they pursue justice and the social good through the rule of law, not around it or in spite of it. This Article will talk particularly about the obligations the rule of law imposes upon lawyers as they act in various capacities. Is it clear what the rule of law demands of lawyers in the international arena? Many people think it demands less in the international arena--that it demands less of a national government in the international arena, for example, than in the domestic arena--not just because there is less international law but also because a different attitude toward the rule of law is appropriate in international affairs. This Article is skeptical about that suggestion, and I shall present a number of reasons for rejecting it. II. To begin with, what does the rule of law require of lawyers in the municipal arena? (3) Usually one thinks of the rule of law as a requirement placed on governments: the government must exercise its power through the application of general rules; it must make those rules public; it must limit the discretion of its officials; it must not impose penalties on people without due process; and so on. But the rule of law applies to the individual, too. So, what does the rule of law require of the ordinary citizen? Well, it requires that she obey the laws that apply to her. She should be alert to changes in the law; she should arrange for her legal advisors to keep her informed of her legal obligations; she should refrain from taking the law into her own hands; and she should not act in any way that impedes, harms, or undermines the operation of the legal system. Every ordinary citizen has these obligations and can properly expect the assistance of her legal advisors. As the ordinary citizen goes abo
一、本文将重点讨论在国际舞台上应该如何思考法治问题。询问国际舞台上的法治不仅仅是询问是否存在国际法,或者它是什么,或者我们对特定条约(如人权公约)的看法,或者习惯国际法的价值,或者国际法在我们自己的法院的可执行性。“法治”一词使人想起与合法性概念有关的一套特定的价值观和原则。这些价值观和原则是我们作为律师忠诚的核心。法治是法律职业尊严和荣誉的最重要来源之一,对法治所包含的原则和价值观的认识应该成为所有律师职业精神的一部分,它规范了律师在工作中所表现出的精神和态度。诚然,法治并不是律师服务的唯一价值。律师也必须为正义服务,因为正义是法律承诺的一部分。当然,律师也为他们的委托人和整个社会的利益服务。但法治限制了律师对其他目标的追求:他们通过法治来追求正义和社会利益,而不是绕过法治或无视法治。本文将特别讨论法治赋予律师以各种身份行事的义务。法治对律师在国际舞台上的要求是否明确?许多人认为它在国际舞台上的要求更少——例如,它在国际舞台上对一个国家政府的要求比在国内舞台上的要求更少——不仅是因为国际法较少,还因为在国际事务中对法治采取不同的态度是合适的。本文对这一建议持怀疑态度,我将提出一些拒绝它的理由。2首先,法治对市政领域的律师有什么要求?(3)人们通常认为法治是对政府的一种要求:政府必须通过适用一般规则来行使权力;它必须将这些规则公之于众;它必须限制其官员的自由裁量权;它绝不能未经正当程序就对人民施加惩罚;等等......但法治也适用于个人。那么,法治对普通公民有什么要求呢?这要求她遵守适用于她的法律。她应该对法律的变化保持警惕;她应安排法律顾问使她了解她的法律义务;她应该克制自己不把法律掌握在自己手中;她不应以任何方式阻碍、损害或破坏法律制度的运作。每个普通公民都有这些义务,并可以适当地期待法律顾问的帮助。当普通公民忙于自己的事务时,她可能会发现,在某些领域,法律的要求是最低的。要么给她钱,要么不提任何要求,让她自由地使用自己的设备。这不是一个遗憾的问题。对法治的忠诚并不意味着公民必须希望拥有更多的法律——或者更少的自由。如果她不愿意,也不要求她参与制定新的法律。在法律存在的地方,她必须遵守,但在法律不存在的地方,她没有特别的义务。国会议员的工作不是由个别市民或企业家来做的。例如,他们没有义务扩大法律约束的范围(根据常识、道德、法律精神、社会目的或其他任何东西),如果法律的来源没有显示出明确的制定这一效果。我们可以进一步阐述这一点。根据大多数法治概念,每个公民都有权享有既不模糊也不不确定的法律,而是以公开和明确的方式阐明的法律,而不是隐藏在教条之中。...
{"title":"The Rule of International Law","authors":"Jeremy Waldron","doi":"10.5040/9781472562494.ch-014","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5040/9781472562494.ch-014","url":null,"abstract":"I. This Article will focus on how one should think about the rule of law in the international arena. Asking about the rule of law in the international arena is not just asking whether there is such a thing as international law, or what it is, or what we think of particular treaties (such as human rights covenants), or of the value of customary international law, or of the enforceability of international law in our own courts. The phrase \"the rule of law\" brings to mind a particular set of values and principles associated with the idea of legality. (1) These values and principles are the ancient focus of our allegiance as lawyers. The rule of law is one of the most important sources of the dignity and honor of the legal profession, and an awareness of the principles and values that it comprises ought to be part of all lawyers' professional ethos, something that disciplines the spirit and attitude that lawyers bring to their work. True, the rule of law is not the only value that lawyers serve. Lawyers must serve justice too, for justice is part of law's promise. (2) And, of course, lawyers serve the interests of their clients and of society generally. But the rule of law constrains lawyers in their pursuit of these other goals: they pursue justice and the social good through the rule of law, not around it or in spite of it. This Article will talk particularly about the obligations the rule of law imposes upon lawyers as they act in various capacities. Is it clear what the rule of law demands of lawyers in the international arena? Many people think it demands less in the international arena--that it demands less of a national government in the international arena, for example, than in the domestic arena--not just because there is less international law but also because a different attitude toward the rule of law is appropriate in international affairs. This Article is skeptical about that suggestion, and I shall present a number of reasons for rejecting it. II. To begin with, what does the rule of law require of lawyers in the municipal arena? (3) Usually one thinks of the rule of law as a requirement placed on governments: the government must exercise its power through the application of general rules; it must make those rules public; it must limit the discretion of its officials; it must not impose penalties on people without due process; and so on. But the rule of law applies to the individual, too. So, what does the rule of law require of the ordinary citizen? Well, it requires that she obey the laws that apply to her. She should be alert to changes in the law; she should arrange for her legal advisors to keep her informed of her legal obligations; she should refrain from taking the law into her own hands; and she should not act in any way that impedes, harms, or undermines the operation of the legal system. Every ordinary citizen has these obligations and can properly expect the assistance of her legal advisors. As the ordinary citizen goes abo","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"16 1","pages":"15"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2006-09-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"70514654","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 64
Towards a Basal Tenth Amendment: A Riposte to National Bank Preemption of State Consumer Protection Laws 迈向基础第十修正案:对国家银行优先于国家消费者保护法的回应
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2005-01-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.824465
K. Fisher
Recent regulations promulgated by the Office of the Comptroller of the Currency assert a sweeping authority to preempt a broad array of state laws, including consumer protection laws, applicable not only to national banks but to their state-chartered operating subsidiaries. These regulations threaten to disrupt state efforts to combat predatory lending and other abusive practices and to interfere with a state's sovereign authority over corporations chartered under its laws. Yet federal courts faced with challenges to these initiatives have failed to devote any substantial analysis to claims based on the Tenth Amendment. The problem with such claims is the absence of any substantial doctrinal base in Tenth Amendment jurisprudence. This article first explores the legal and policy implications of the preemption program and identifies the consumer protection interests at stake and the states' role in vindicating those interests. It then considers the importance of judicial review to the Framers' federalism design and endeavors to distill from their commentary and debates some substantive content for the Tenth Amendment that federal courts could credibly enforce. The article concludes with a modest suggested template for doctrinal analysis of Tenth Amendment issues arising from federal administrative action.
美国货币监理署(Office of the Comptroller of the Currency)最近颁布的法规宣称,它拥有凌驾于一系列州法律(包括消费者保护法)之上的广泛权力,这些法律不仅适用于全国性银行,也适用于它们在州内特许经营的子公司。这些规定有可能破坏州政府打击掠夺性贷款和其他滥用行为的努力,并干扰州政府对根据其法律注册的公司的主权权力。然而,面对这些倡议的挑战,联邦法院未能对基于第十修正案的主张进行任何实质性分析。这种主张的问题在于,在第十修正案的判例中缺乏任何实质性的理论基础。本文首先探讨了优先权计划的法律和政策含义,并确定了受到威胁的消费者保护利益以及各州在维护这些利益方面的作用。然后,它考虑了司法审查对制宪者联邦制设计的重要性,并努力从他们的评论和辩论中提炼出联邦法院可以可信地执行的第十修正案的一些实质性内容。文章最后提出了一个适度的建议模板,用于对联邦行政行为引起的第十修正案问题进行理论分析。
{"title":"Towards a Basal Tenth Amendment: A Riposte to National Bank Preemption of State Consumer Protection Laws","authors":"K. Fisher","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.824465","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.824465","url":null,"abstract":"Recent regulations promulgated by the Office of the Comptroller of the Currency assert a sweeping authority to preempt a broad array of state laws, including consumer protection laws, applicable not only to national banks but to their state-chartered operating subsidiaries. These regulations threaten to disrupt state efforts to combat predatory lending and other abusive practices and to interfere with a state's sovereign authority over corporations chartered under its laws. Yet federal courts faced with challenges to these initiatives have failed to devote any substantial analysis to claims based on the Tenth Amendment. The problem with such claims is the absence of any substantial doctrinal base in Tenth Amendment jurisprudence. This article first explores the legal and policy implications of the preemption program and identifies the consumer protection interests at stake and the states' role in vindicating those interests. It then considers the importance of judicial review to the Framers' federalism design and endeavors to distill from their commentary and debates some substantive content for the Tenth Amendment that federal courts could credibly enforce. The article concludes with a modest suggested template for doctrinal analysis of Tenth Amendment issues arising from federal administrative action.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"29 1","pages":"981"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2005-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67836614","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
期刊
Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1