首页 > 最新文献

Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy最新文献

英文 中文
Public Choice Theory and Occupational Licensing 公共选择理论与职业许可
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2015-01-09 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.2540084
Paul J. Larkin, Jr.
Occupational licensing is now one of the most widespread and fastest growing forms of labor market regulation. Occupational licensing requirement generally are defended on the ground that they offset the information disparity between service providers and consumers by guaranteeing a minimal level of qualifications. Over time, however, a large number of federal government officials, scholars, and commentators have criticized the widespread use of occupational licensing requirements. They have argued that licensing requirements benefit licensees, not consumers, by helping to create a cartel that can avoid competition and raise prices. Public Choice Theory is a useful tool for analyzing licensing requirements because it applies microeconomic and game theory to the political process. Doing so gives rise to the remarkable irony that the justification for regulation has come full circle. Originally, the rationale was that government intervention would remedy economic market failures in furtherance of the public interest. Today, we see that government intervention causes political market failures in furtherance of private interests. Government has become the problem, not the solution. That conclusion justifies a re-examination of the constitutionality of many occupational licensing schemes. Then Supreme Court has been unwilling to re-examine the constitutionality of these programs since the new Deal, but there are two grounds that might prove useful. One is the Equal Protection Clause. It requires a rational basis for treating similarly situated people differently. Here, the argument would be that the basis for requiring licenses is due to the operation of political bribery and extortion, which is not a legitimate state interest. The second argument would be that many license schemes vest lawmaking authority in private parties, which the Private Delegation Doctrine forbids.
职业许可现在是劳动力市场监管中最广泛和发展最快的形式之一。一般来说,职业许可要求的辩护理由是,它们通过保证最低水平的资格来抵消服务提供者和消费者之间的信息差距。然而,随着时间的推移,大量的联邦政府官员、学者和评论家批评了职业许可要求的广泛使用。他们认为,许可要求有利于被许可人,而不是消费者,因为它有助于形成一个可以避免竞争和提高价格的卡特尔。公共选择理论是分析许可要求的有用工具,因为它将微观经济学和博弈论应用于政治过程。这样做带来了一个显著的讽刺:监管的正当性又兜了一圈。最初,其基本原理是政府干预将弥补经济市场失灵,促进公众利益。今天,我们看到政府干预在促进私人利益的过程中导致了政治市场失灵。政府成了问题,而不是解决方案。这一结论为重新审查许多职业许可制度的合宪性提供了理由。自新政以来,最高法院一直不愿重新审查这些项目的合宪性,但有两个理由可能证明是有用的。一是平等保护条款。它需要一个理性的基础来区别对待处境相似的人。这里的论点是,要求许可证的依据是由于政治贿赂和敲诈勒索的运作,这不是合法的国家利益。第二个论点是,许多许可计划将立法权授予私人团体,这是私人授权原则所禁止的。
{"title":"Public Choice Theory and Occupational Licensing","authors":"Paul J. Larkin, Jr.","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.2540084","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2540084","url":null,"abstract":"Occupational licensing is now one of the most widespread and fastest growing forms of labor market regulation. Occupational licensing requirement generally are defended on the ground that they offset the information disparity between service providers and consumers by guaranteeing a minimal level of qualifications. Over time, however, a large number of federal government officials, scholars, and commentators have criticized the widespread use of occupational licensing requirements. They have argued that licensing requirements benefit licensees, not consumers, by helping to create a cartel that can avoid competition and raise prices. Public Choice Theory is a useful tool for analyzing licensing requirements because it applies microeconomic and game theory to the political process. Doing so gives rise to the remarkable irony that the justification for regulation has come full circle. Originally, the rationale was that government intervention would remedy economic market failures in furtherance of the public interest. Today, we see that government intervention causes political market failures in furtherance of private interests. Government has become the problem, not the solution. That conclusion justifies a re-examination of the constitutionality of many occupational licensing schemes. Then Supreme Court has been unwilling to re-examine the constitutionality of these programs since the new Deal, but there are two grounds that might prove useful. One is the Equal Protection Clause. It requires a rational basis for treating similarly situated people differently. Here, the argument would be that the basis for requiring licenses is due to the operation of political bribery and extortion, which is not a legitimate state interest. The second argument would be that many license schemes vest lawmaking authority in private parties, which the Private Delegation Doctrine forbids.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2015-01-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/ssrn.2540084","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68197388","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Bulk Metadata Collection: Statutory and Constitutional Considerations 批量元数据收集:法定和宪法考虑
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2014-06-22 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2344774
L. Donohue
The National Security Agency’s bulk collection of telephony metadata runs contrary to Congress’s intent in enacting the 1978 Foreign Intelligence Surveillance Act. The program also violates the statute in three ways: the requirement that records sought be “relevant to an authorized investigation;” the requirement that information could be obtained via subpoena duces mecum; and the steps required for use of pen registers and trap and trace devices. Additionally, the program gives rise to serious constitutional concerns. Efforts by the government to save the program on grounds of third party doctrine are unpersuasive in light of the unique circumstances of Smith v. Maryland, the privacy invasions resulting from the universal use of pen registers and trap and trace devices, and the advent of new technologies. Over the past decade, tension has emerged between the view that new technologies should be considered from the perspective of trespass doctrine and the view that Katz’s reasonable expectation of privacy test should apply. Cases involving, for instance, GPS chips, thermal scanners, and highly-trained dogs divide along these lines. Regardless of which approach one adopts, however, similar results mark the application of these doctrines. Under trespass doctrine, the primary order for the telephony metadata program amounts to a general warrant — the elimination of which was the aim of the Fourth Amendment. Under Katz, in turn, citizens do not expect that their telephony metadata will be collected and analyzed. Most Americans do not even realize what can be learned from such data, making invalid any claim that they reasonably expect the government to have access to such information. FISA reform is necessary to enable the government to take advantage of new technologies, to empower the intelligence agencies to respond to national security threats, and to bring surveillance operations within the bounds of statutory and constitutional law. Inserting adversarial counsel into the FISA process, creating a repository of technological expertise for FISC and FISCR, restoring prior targeting, heightening protections for U.S. persons, further delimiting relevant data, narrowing the definition of “foreign intelligence” to exclude “foreign affairs,” and requiring the government to demonstrate past effectiveness prior to obtaining renewal orders offer some possibilities for the future of foreign intelligence gathering in the United States.
美国国家安全局(National Security Agency)大量收集电话元数据的做法,与国会1978年颁布《外国情报监视法》(Foreign Intelligence Surveillance Act)的意图背道而驰。该计划还在三个方面违反了该法规:要求所寻求的记录必须“与授权的调查有关”;要求可以通过强制传唤获得信息;以及使用笔式寄存器、陷阱和跟踪装置所需的步骤。此外,该计划还引发了严重的宪法问题。鉴于史密斯诉马里兰州案的特殊情况、笔录记录器、陷阱和追踪装置的普遍使用以及新技术的出现导致的隐私侵犯,政府以第三方原则为由挽救该项目的努力是没有说服力的。在过去的十年中,一种观点认为新技术应该从非法侵入原则的角度来考虑,另一种观点认为应该适用卡茨关于隐私测试的合理预期,这两种观点之间出现了紧张关系。例如,涉及GPS芯片、热扫描仪和训练有素的狗的案件就按照这些路线划分。然而,无论采用哪种方法,这些理论的应用结果都是相似的。根据非法侵入原则,对电话元数据项目的主要命令相当于一般搜查令——消除这种搜查令是第四修正案的目的。反过来,在卡茨的领导下,公民不希望他们的电话元数据被收集和分析。大多数美国人甚至没有意识到可以从这些数据中了解到什么,这使得他们合理期望政府获得这些信息的任何主张都是无效的。为了使政府能够利用新技术,赋予情报机构应对国家安全威胁的权力,并使监视行动处于法定和宪法法律的范围内,FISA改革是必要的。在FISA程序中加入对抗性法律顾问,为FISC和fisr建立技术专门知识库,恢复先前的目标,加强对美国人的保护,进一步界定相关数据,缩小“外国情报”的定义以排除“外交事务”,并要求政府在获得更新命令之前证明过去的有效性,为未来在美国收集外国情报提供了一些可能性。
{"title":"Bulk Metadata Collection: Statutory and Constitutional Considerations","authors":"L. Donohue","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2344774","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2344774","url":null,"abstract":"The National Security Agency’s bulk collection of telephony metadata runs contrary to Congress’s intent in enacting the 1978 Foreign Intelligence Surveillance Act. The program also violates the statute in three ways: the requirement that records sought be “relevant to an authorized investigation;” the requirement that information could be obtained via subpoena duces mecum; and the steps required for use of pen registers and trap and trace devices. Additionally, the program gives rise to serious constitutional concerns. Efforts by the government to save the program on grounds of third party doctrine are unpersuasive in light of the unique circumstances of Smith v. Maryland, the privacy invasions resulting from the universal use of pen registers and trap and trace devices, and the advent of new technologies. Over the past decade, tension has emerged between the view that new technologies should be considered from the perspective of trespass doctrine and the view that Katz’s reasonable expectation of privacy test should apply. Cases involving, for instance, GPS chips, thermal scanners, and highly-trained dogs divide along these lines. Regardless of which approach one adopts, however, similar results mark the application of these doctrines. Under trespass doctrine, the primary order for the telephony metadata program amounts to a general warrant — the elimination of which was the aim of the Fourth Amendment. Under Katz, in turn, citizens do not expect that their telephony metadata will be collected and analyzed. Most Americans do not even realize what can be learned from such data, making invalid any claim that they reasonably expect the government to have access to such information. FISA reform is necessary to enable the government to take advantage of new technologies, to empower the intelligence agencies to respond to national security threats, and to bring surveillance operations within the bounds of statutory and constitutional law. Inserting adversarial counsel into the FISA process, creating a repository of technological expertise for FISC and FISCR, restoring prior targeting, heightening protections for U.S. persons, further delimiting relevant data, narrowing the definition of “foreign intelligence” to exclude “foreign affairs,” and requiring the government to demonstrate past effectiveness prior to obtaining renewal orders offer some possibilities for the future of foreign intelligence gathering in the United States.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"37 1","pages":"757"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2014-06-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68125522","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 25
The New Private-Regulation Skepticism: Due Process, Non-Delegation, and Antitrust Challenges 新的私人监管怀疑论:正当程序、非授权和反垄断挑战
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2014-06-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2335659
A. Volokh
In recent years, state and federal courts have been ruling against private regulatory organizations on a number of theories. This Article explores this new private-regulation skepticism and the theories that underpin it.This Article focuses on three main sources of law: the Due Process Clause, non-delegation doctrine, and antitrust law. To illustrate the doctrines, it follows five examples from recent cases and recent news of regulation by Amtrak, the North Carolina Board of Dental Examiners, the Mississippi Board of Pharmacy, the Texas Boll Weevil Eradication Foundation, and landowners in Texas water quality protection zones.The Due Process Clause is a potential limit on the private exercise of regulatory power, especially if the regulators and the regulated parties compete with each other. Federal non-delegation doctrine, by contrast, is unlikely to be much help in these challenges, though some states, like Texas, have vibrant non-delegation doctrines that not only are stricter than the federal one but also strongly distinguish between public and private delegates. Some courts don’t clearly distinguish between non-delegation and due process. I argue that they should, as the two doctrines serve very different purposes.Finally, federal antitrust law is available to guard against the anticompetitive dangers of “industry regulating itself.” Excessive conflicts of interest decrease the chance that a court will find state action immunity from antitrust law, and increase the chance that a court will find a substantive antitrust violation because of structural anticompetitive factors. Additionally, regulators that are sufficiently independent from state government are less likely to be insulated from liability by sovereign immunity. This new regulation skepticism thus provides several useful tools to challenge private regulation.
近年来,州法院和联邦法院根据一些理论对私人监管组织作出了不利于他们的裁决。本文探讨了这种新的私人监管怀疑主义以及支撑它的理论。本文将重点讨论三个主要的法律渊源:正当程序条款、非授权原则和反垄断法。为了说明这些理论,本文列举了美国铁路公司(Amtrak)、北卡罗来纳州牙科检查委员会、密西西比州药房委员会、德克萨斯州棉铃象鼻虫根除基金会和德克萨斯州水质保护区的土地所有者最近的五个案例和最新的监管新闻。正当程序条款是对私人行使监管权力的潜在限制,特别是在监管机构和被监管方相互竞争的情况下。相比之下,联邦的非授权原则不太可能在这些挑战中起到多大帮助,尽管一些州,如德克萨斯州,有充满活力的非授权原则,不仅比联邦的更严格,而且还强烈区分公共和私人代表。一些法院没有明确区分非授权和正当程序。我认为应该如此,因为这两种学说的目的截然不同。最后,联邦反托拉斯法可用于防范“行业自我监管”的反竞争危险。过度的利益冲突减少了法院认定国家行为豁免反垄断法的机会,并增加了法院因结构性反竞争因素而认定实质性反垄断违规的机会。此外,充分独立于州政府的监管机构不太可能因主权豁免而免于承担责任。因此,这种新的监管怀疑论为挑战私人监管提供了几个有用的工具。
{"title":"The New Private-Regulation Skepticism: Due Process, Non-Delegation, and Antitrust Challenges","authors":"A. Volokh","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2335659","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2335659","url":null,"abstract":"In recent years, state and federal courts have been ruling against private regulatory organizations on a number of theories. This Article explores this new private-regulation skepticism and the theories that underpin it.This Article focuses on three main sources of law: the Due Process Clause, non-delegation doctrine, and antitrust law. To illustrate the doctrines, it follows five examples from recent cases and recent news of regulation by Amtrak, the North Carolina Board of Dental Examiners, the Mississippi Board of Pharmacy, the Texas Boll Weevil Eradication Foundation, and landowners in Texas water quality protection zones.The Due Process Clause is a potential limit on the private exercise of regulatory power, especially if the regulators and the regulated parties compete with each other. Federal non-delegation doctrine, by contrast, is unlikely to be much help in these challenges, though some states, like Texas, have vibrant non-delegation doctrines that not only are stricter than the federal one but also strongly distinguish between public and private delegates. Some courts don’t clearly distinguish between non-delegation and due process. I argue that they should, as the two doctrines serve very different purposes.Finally, federal antitrust law is available to guard against the anticompetitive dangers of “industry regulating itself.” Excessive conflicts of interest decrease the chance that a court will find state action immunity from antitrust law, and increase the chance that a court will find a substantive antitrust violation because of structural anticompetitive factors. Additionally, regulators that are sufficiently independent from state government are less likely to be insulated from liability by sovereign immunity. This new regulation skepticism thus provides several useful tools to challenge private regulation.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"54 1","pages":"931"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2014-06-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.2335659","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68114751","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 32
The Paradox of Administrative Preemption 行政优先权的悖论
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2014-02-20 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2379627
David S. Rubenstein
Administrative preemption is a convenience and contrivance for modern government. But, as uncovered here, it is also a constitutional paradox. Specifically, in the federalism context the Court treats agency action as preemptive under the Supremacy Clause, which provides that certain federal “Laws” shall be supreme over state law. However, if agency action qualifies as “Law,” then it should be void under separation-of-powers principles (and thus ineligible to preempt state law). Meanwhile, if agency action does not qualify as “Law” (thus avoiding a separation-of-powers problem), then it should fall beyond the Supremacy Clause’s purview. Paradoxically, administrative preemption requires that agency action simultaneously qualify as (1) “Law” for federalism purposes and (2) “not Law” for separation of powers. The Founders surely never intended this. Although much has changed since then, resort to the Court’s interpretive glosses for modern government fare no better. For instance, if the Court’s premise behind administrative preemption is that agencies make “Law,” then how should we understand the Court’s longstanding insistence otherwise in the separation-of-powers context? And, if unelected administrative officials can displace state law in Congress’s stead, what are we to make of the Court’s heralded political-safeguards theory of federalism? These inquests underscore the difficulty of settling on a constitutional premise that is both broad enough to justify administrative preemption, yet narrow enough to preserve the Court’s legitimating theories of modern government. Perhaps administrative preemption is right, and the Court’s legitimating glosses for modern government are wrong. Or perhaps the inverse is true. This Article’s insight is that these cannot all be right — at least not without a new constitutional bargain.
行政优先权是现代政府的一种便利和发明。但是,正如本文所揭示的,这也是一个宪法悖论。具体而言,在联邦制背景下,法院根据最高条款将机构行为视为先发制人,该条款规定某些联邦“法律”应高于州法律。然而,如果代理行为符合“法律”的条件,那么它在三权分立原则下应该是无效的(因此没有资格优先于州法律)。同时,如果机构行为不符合“法律”的条件(从而避免权力分立问题),那么它应该超出最高条款的范围。矛盾的是,行政优先权要求机构行为同时符合(1)联邦目的的“法律”和(2)三权分立的“非法律”。国父们肯定没有这个打算。尽管从那时起发生了很大的变化,但诉诸最高法院对现代政府的解释也没有更好。例如,如果法院在行政优先权背后的前提是行政机关制定“法律”,那么我们应该如何理解法院在三权分立的背景下长期坚持的相反观点?而且,如果未经选举的行政官员可以代替国会取代州法律,我们又该如何理解最高法院倡导的联邦制政治保障理论呢?这些调查凸显了确立一个宪法前提的难度,这个前提既要广泛到足以证明行政优先权是合理的,又要狭隘到足以维护最高法院对现代政府的合法化理论。也许行政优先权是正确的,而最高法院为现代政府所做的合法化粉饰是错误的。或者反过来也是对的。本文的观点是,这些不可能都是正确的——至少在没有新的宪法协议的情况下是正确的。
{"title":"The Paradox of Administrative Preemption","authors":"David S. Rubenstein","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2379627","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2379627","url":null,"abstract":"Administrative preemption is a convenience and contrivance for modern government. But, as uncovered here, it is also a constitutional paradox. Specifically, in the federalism context the Court treats agency action as preemptive under the Supremacy Clause, which provides that certain federal “Laws” shall be supreme over state law. However, if agency action qualifies as “Law,” then it should be void under separation-of-powers principles (and thus ineligible to preempt state law). Meanwhile, if agency action does not qualify as “Law” (thus avoiding a separation-of-powers problem), then it should fall beyond the Supremacy Clause’s purview. Paradoxically, administrative preemption requires that agency action simultaneously qualify as (1) “Law” for federalism purposes and (2) “not Law” for separation of powers. The Founders surely never intended this. Although much has changed since then, resort to the Court’s interpretive glosses for modern government fare no better. For instance, if the Court’s premise behind administrative preemption is that agencies make “Law,” then how should we understand the Court’s longstanding insistence otherwise in the separation-of-powers context? And, if unelected administrative officials can displace state law in Congress’s stead, what are we to make of the Court’s heralded political-safeguards theory of federalism? These inquests underscore the difficulty of settling on a constitutional premise that is both broad enough to justify administrative preemption, yet narrow enough to preserve the Court’s legitimating theories of modern government. Perhaps administrative preemption is right, and the Court’s legitimating glosses for modern government are wrong. Or perhaps the inverse is true. This Article’s insight is that these cannot all be right — at least not without a new constitutional bargain.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"98 1","pages":"267"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2014-02-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68159483","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Why Nonoriginalism Does Not Justify Departing from the Original Meaning of the Recess Appointments Clause 为什么非原旨主义不能成为背离休会任命条款原意的理由
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2014-01-03 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2374563
Michael B. Rappaport
The Constitution requires officers to be appointed through a process of presidential nomination and senatorial consent, but the Recess Appointments Clause allows the President alone to make temporary appointments during Senate recesses. In this way, the President can fill offices even if the Senate is not available to confirm a nominee. A key question is how broad the President’s recess appointment authority is. In a 2005 article, I argued that the original meaning of the Clause provides narrow authority to the President. The executive branch, however, interprets the Clause much more broadly. If the executive’s interpretation is inconsistent with the original meaning, then how do its defenders seek to justify it? The main method has been to argue that various nonoriginalist considerations indicate that the executive’s broad interpretation should be followed. In this article, I examine the principal nonoriginalist arguments that might be made and show that none of them provides a persuasive case for departing from the original meaning. A common argument made against following the original meaning of a provision is based on living constitutionalism. Under this approach, the original Constitution is seen as an old, potentially outdated document and judges are viewed as having the power to update its provisions to take into account modern values and circumstances. And it is clearly true that the circumstances governing appointments have changed since the late 18th century, when antiquated transportation methods generally led the Senate to take recesses of between 6 to 9 months. But these changes in circumstances argue for narrower, not broader recess appointment authority. In a world with airplanes, Senate recesses are shorter and therefore there is less need to allow the President to make unilateral appointments. Moreover, modern appointment practices indicate that appointments take a long time, with on average nominations taking 4 months and appointments taking 5 to 6 months. This evidence suggests that short recesses of 10 or 30 days, which delay appointments by only a fraction of the ordinary appointment process, do not justify bypassing the senatorial confirmation requirement. The most common and probably the strongest argument for departing from the original meaning is based on historical practice. Defenders of the executive branch’s view of the Clause argue that the political branches have followed a practice allowing broad recess appointment power and that this practice has either been agreed to or acquiesced in by the legislature. This Article reviews the recess appointment practice and argues that this account of the practice is mistaken. It shows that Congress has passed statutes in 1863 and 1940 that have rejected the executive’s broad view. The executive, however, has mistakenly interpreted the latter statute to allow it broad authority. As the executive has asserted recess appointment power more aggressively in recent years, the legisla
宪法规定,官员的任命必须经过总统提名和参议院同意的程序,但休会任命条款允许总统在参议院休会期间单独进行临时任命。这样,即使参议院无法确认被提名人,总统也可以填补职位空缺。一个关键问题是总统的休会任命权限有多大。在2005年的一篇文章中,我认为该条款最初的含义是赋予总统狭隘的权力。然而,行政部门对该条款的解释要宽泛得多。如果行政部门的解释与最初的含义不一致,那么它的辩护者如何寻求为其辩护?主要的方法是争辩说,各种非原旨主义的考虑表明,应该遵循行政长官的广义解释。在本文中,我考察了可能提出的主要的非原旨主义论点,并表明它们都没有提供偏离原意的有说服力的理由。反对遵循条款原意的常见论点是基于现行的宪政主义。在这种做法下,最初的宪法被视为一份旧的、可能过时的文件,法官被视为有权更新其条款,以考虑到现代价值观和环境。而且很明显,自18世纪末以来,有关任命的情况已经发生了变化,当时过时的交通方式通常导致参议院休会6到9个月。但这些情况的变化要求缩小休会任命的权限,而不是扩大休会任命的权限。在一个有飞机的世界里,参议院的休会时间更短,因此不太需要允许总统单方面任命。此外,现代任命做法表明,任命需要很长时间,平均提名需要4个月,任命需要5至6个月。这一证据表明,10天或30天的短暂休会,只是普通任命程序的一小部分,不能成为绕过参议院确认要求的理由。背离原意的最常见也可能是最有力的论据是基于历史实践的。为行政部门对该条款的看法辩护的人认为,政治部门遵循了一种允许广泛休会任命权力的做法,这种做法要么得到了立法机关的同意,要么得到了默许。本文回顾了休会任命的做法,并认为这种说法是错误的。它表明,国会在1863年和1940年通过的法规拒绝了行政部门的广泛观点。然而,行政部门错误地解释了后一项法规,使其具有广泛的权力。近年来,随着行政部门更积极地行使休会任命权力,立法院通过举行形式会议来抵制这种权力。但是,即使行政部门对该条款的解释得到历史实践的支持,我认为这也不能成为偏离其原意的理由。国会或参议院的同意或默许不足以成为背离宪法的理由。如果参议院同意扩大总统的休会任命权力,那么从总统和参议院的角度来看,该协议可能是一种可取的安排。但宪法的目的是保护人民,而不是促进政治分支的利益,参议院的同意是这种保护的一个重要方面。注:这篇文章的初稿写于2013年夏天,在诺埃尔·坎宁案的摘要提交给最高法院之前。2013年10月,司法部副部长提交了简报,其中包括大量此前未被披露的休会期间任命。这篇文章随后被修改,以考虑到这些新发现的休会任命。
{"title":"Why Nonoriginalism Does Not Justify Departing from the Original Meaning of the Recess Appointments Clause","authors":"Michael B. Rappaport","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2374563","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2374563","url":null,"abstract":"The Constitution requires officers to be appointed through a process of presidential nomination and senatorial consent, but the Recess Appointments Clause allows the President alone to make temporary appointments during Senate recesses. In this way, the President can fill offices even if the Senate is not available to confirm a nominee. A key question is how broad the President’s recess appointment authority is. In a 2005 article, I argued that the original meaning of the Clause provides narrow authority to the President. The executive branch, however, interprets the Clause much more broadly. If the executive’s interpretation is inconsistent with the original meaning, then how do its defenders seek to justify it? The main method has been to argue that various nonoriginalist considerations indicate that the executive’s broad interpretation should be followed. In this article, I examine the principal nonoriginalist arguments that might be made and show that none of them provides a persuasive case for departing from the original meaning. A common argument made against following the original meaning of a provision is based on living constitutionalism. Under this approach, the original Constitution is seen as an old, potentially outdated document and judges are viewed as having the power to update its provisions to take into account modern values and circumstances. And it is clearly true that the circumstances governing appointments have changed since the late 18th century, when antiquated transportation methods generally led the Senate to take recesses of between 6 to 9 months. But these changes in circumstances argue for narrower, not broader recess appointment authority. In a world with airplanes, Senate recesses are shorter and therefore there is less need to allow the President to make unilateral appointments. Moreover, modern appointment practices indicate that appointments take a long time, with on average nominations taking 4 months and appointments taking 5 to 6 months. This evidence suggests that short recesses of 10 or 30 days, which delay appointments by only a fraction of the ordinary appointment process, do not justify bypassing the senatorial confirmation requirement. The most common and probably the strongest argument for departing from the original meaning is based on historical practice. Defenders of the executive branch’s view of the Clause argue that the political branches have followed a practice allowing broad recess appointment power and that this practice has either been agreed to or acquiesced in by the legislature. This Article reviews the recess appointment practice and argues that this account of the practice is mistaken. It shows that Congress has passed statutes in 1863 and 1940 that have rejected the executive’s broad view. The executive, however, has mistakenly interpreted the latter statute to allow it broad authority. As the executive has asserted recess appointment power more aggressively in recent years, the legisla","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"189 11 1","pages":"889"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2014-01-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68152112","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Treaty Law Through a Military Lens: A 'Full Spectrum' Insight into US Treaty Practice 军事视角下的条约法:对美国条约实践的“全光谱”洞察
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2014-01-01 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.2399917
G. Corn, Dru Brenner-Beck
{"title":"Treaty Law Through a Military Lens: A 'Full Spectrum' Insight into US Treaty Practice","authors":"G. Corn, Dru Brenner-Beck","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.2399917","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2399917","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2014-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68181720","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Toward Improved Intellectual Diversity in Law Schools 改善法学院的智力多样性
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2013-09-10 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2324281
G. Dent
Law school faculties tilt heavily to the left. There is no plausible explanation for this tilt other than discrimination against scholars who are politically incorrect. This imbalance is a serious problem for law students, who do not get the full range of views in important contemporary debates, and for legal scholarship, which would profit from an unbiased marketplace of ideas. The purpose of this paper is to discuss practical steps that might be taken to achieve a fairer representation of conservatives and libertarians in law schools. These include measures to induce the Association of American Law Schools abide by its professed commitment to viewpoint diversity; to improve viewpoint diversity at individual schools; and efforts directed at law schools generally.This paper is based on a presentation at a conference, Intellectual Diversity and the Legal Academy, held at Harvard Law School on April 5, 2013. It is scheduled to be published in a symposium issue of the Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy.
法学院的师资力量严重偏左。对于这种倾向,除了对政治不正确的学者的歧视之外,没有其他合理的解释。这种不平衡对法学院学生来说是一个严重的问题,因为他们无法在重要的当代辩论中获得全面的观点,而对法律学术来说,这将从一个公正的思想市场中受益。本文的目的是讨论可能采取的实际步骤,以实现保守派和自由意志主义者在法学院的更公平的代表。这些措施包括促使美国法学院协会(Association of American Law Schools)遵守其公开承诺的观点多样性;改善个别学校的观点多样性;以及针对法学院的努力。本文基于2013年4月5日在哈佛法学院举行的“智力多样性与法律学院”会议上的演讲。这篇文章将在《哈佛法律与公共政策杂志》的一期研讨会上发表。
{"title":"Toward Improved Intellectual Diversity in Law Schools","authors":"G. Dent","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2324281","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2324281","url":null,"abstract":"Law school faculties tilt heavily to the left. There is no plausible explanation for this tilt other than discrimination against scholars who are politically incorrect. This imbalance is a serious problem for law students, who do not get the full range of views in important contemporary debates, and for legal scholarship, which would profit from an unbiased marketplace of ideas. The purpose of this paper is to discuss practical steps that might be taken to achieve a fairer representation of conservatives and libertarians in law schools. These include measures to induce the Association of American Law Schools abide by its professed commitment to viewpoint diversity; to improve viewpoint diversity at individual schools; and efforts directed at law schools generally.This paper is based on a presentation at a conference, Intellectual Diversity and the Legal Academy, held at Harvard Law School on April 5, 2013. It is scheduled to be published in a symposium issue of the Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"37 1","pages":"165"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2013-09-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68104232","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
On the Majesty of the Law 论法律的威严
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2013-01-01 DOI: 10.2307/j.ctv1210128.41
H. Mansfield
In the choice of my topic, I unknowingly filched the title of Justice Sandra Day O'Connor's memoirs. I meant to call upon what is awesome and venerable in the law, as I think the good Justice did as well. Majesty is not in our style of democratic informality, in which everything is open to change in the hope of reform. But we are still attached to the formality of procedure and the solemnity of judicial garb designed to maintain respect for the law. We do not need regal magnificence in our judges, but we do require republican assurances that public justice is serious business. Above all, any appearance that the law can be circumvented by private approach or by interested calculation --and this warning is directed to professors--is to be avoided. What happens behind the scenes must stay behind the scenes. Against this intimation of majesty practiced in our time is the movement of thought known as "legal realism." I will argue in my brief that majesty is good and that legal realism is inadequate. Legal realism is not all wrong, but the view that it is enough is all wrong. Legal realism has several modes, but they all declare that something other than, and more powerful than, law is the cause of law. The "realism" consists of seeing through mere appearances and establishing the fact of this more powerful force. Once established, that fact must be published, taught, and spread. Legal realism is expected to bring good to society by its inventors, who quickly become, if they were not from the first, its advocates. It asserts that our law will be better if through clear thinking we dispense with its irrational majesty. This realism is really idealism. In the old days, when philosophy was young, the pre-Socratic philosophers thought that laws were made for the convenience of rulers and nothing good was to be expected from politics. They thought that was realism. In America, advocates of legal realism have arisen from the Progressive tradition, joined now by libertarian conservatives, who claim public good will result from their public unmasking of law. Despite the fact (as they maintain) that no one aims for the public good, they believe it does exist; Socrates was right about that. The sort of thinking our legal realists recommend can be seen in the famous prisoner's dilemma that is the essence of game theory, the most fashionable mode of legal realism. The prisoner's dilemma posits a situation in which a prisoner must choose between defecting from a fellow prisoner and cooperating with him. We do not know whether the prisoner is guilty and should therefore confess his crimes. We do not know whether the law he may or may not have violated deserves to be respected. But the example is not as neutral as it seems. One's sympathies are unjustifiably enlisted on the side of the prisoner by adopting his point of view. From the standpoint of the law, he is defecting from the law instead of cooperating with it by confessing, as is his duty. The example substitut
在选题上,我无意中取了大法官桑德拉·戴·奥康纳回忆录的标题。我的意思是诉诸法律中令人敬畏和可敬的东西,我想这位善良的大法官也是这样做的。陛下不是我们那种民主的随意性,在这种随意性中,一切都可以在改革的希望中改变。但是,我们仍然执著于程序的正式性和为维护对法律的尊重而设计的司法服装的严肃性。我们不需要法官有帝王般的威严,但我们确实需要共和政体的保证,即公共司法是一件严肃的事情。最重要的是,任何可以通过私人手段或利益计算来规避法律的表象——这个警告是针对教授们的——都是要避免的。幕后发生的事必须留在幕后。在我们这个时代,与这种威严的暗示相对立的是一种被称为“法律现实主义”的思想运动。我将在我的简报中说明,威严是好的,法律现实主义是不够的。法律现实主义并非完全错误,但认为法律现实主义已经足够的观点是完全错误的。法律现实主义有几种模式,但它们都宣称,法律之外的、比法律更强大的东西是法律的原因。“现实主义”包括透过表象去观察,并确立这一更强大力量的事实。这一事实一经确立,就必须予以公布、教授和传播。法律现实主义的发明者被期望为社会带来好处,如果他们不是一开始就成为法律现实主义的倡导者,那么他们很快就会成为法律现实主义的倡导者。它断言,如果我们通过清晰的思考摒弃其非理性的威严,我们的法律将会更好。这种现实主义其实就是理想主义。在古代,当哲学还很年轻的时候,前苏格拉底时代的哲学家们认为法律是为了方便统治者而制定的,不能指望从政治中得到什么好处。他们认为这是现实主义。在美国,法律现实主义的倡导者来自进步主义传统,现在加入了自由主义保守派,他们声称公开揭露法律将带来公共利益。尽管事实上(正如他们所坚持的)没有人以公共利益为目标,但他们相信它确实存在;苏格拉底是对的。我们的法律现实主义者推荐的这种思维可以在著名的囚徒困境中看到,这是博弈论的精髓,是法律现实主义最流行的模式。囚徒困境是指囚犯必须在背叛同伴和与同伴合作之间做出选择。我们不知道这个囚犯是否有罪,因此应该承认他的罪行。我们不知道他是否违反了法律,是否值得尊重。但这个例子并不像看起来那么中立。通过采纳囚犯的观点,一个人毫无道理地把自己的同情心拉到囚犯一边。从法律的角度来看,他是在背叛法律,而不是通过认罪与法律合作,这是他的义务。这个例子用计算代替了责任,实际上是关于如何在有利的情况下逃避法律。质疑这种所谓中立战略的连贯性并非没有道理。它如何与尊重法律相一致?难道人们不应该相信两个杀人犯,两只老鼠,应该互相出卖对方吗?“rat out”这个短语表达了一种高尚的蔑视,这是杀人犯没有资格得到的。有人可能会反对说,只有当法律对我们有利时,我们才应该尊重法律。但如果这是正确的,人们只会做对他们有益的事,结果就会和谐,就不需要法律了。法律似乎需要看起来是好的,即使它可能不是;正如我们所说,它需要合法性。合法性是否需要威严才能赋予它权威?到目前为止,我一直在谈论“法律”,好像法律是一个整体。即使是在多元化的美国,我们也使用这个表达。然而,法律由法律组成,每一个法律都是独立的,并不一定与其他法律相一致。...
{"title":"On the Majesty of the Law","authors":"H. Mansfield","doi":"10.2307/j.ctv1210128.41","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2307/j.ctv1210128.41","url":null,"abstract":"In the choice of my topic, I unknowingly filched the title of Justice Sandra Day O'Connor's memoirs. I meant to call upon what is awesome and venerable in the law, as I think the good Justice did as well. Majesty is not in our style of democratic informality, in which everything is open to change in the hope of reform. But we are still attached to the formality of procedure and the solemnity of judicial garb designed to maintain respect for the law. We do not need regal magnificence in our judges, but we do require republican assurances that public justice is serious business. Above all, any appearance that the law can be circumvented by private approach or by interested calculation --and this warning is directed to professors--is to be avoided. What happens behind the scenes must stay behind the scenes. Against this intimation of majesty practiced in our time is the movement of thought known as \"legal realism.\" I will argue in my brief that majesty is good and that legal realism is inadequate. Legal realism is not all wrong, but the view that it is enough is all wrong. Legal realism has several modes, but they all declare that something other than, and more powerful than, law is the cause of law. The \"realism\" consists of seeing through mere appearances and establishing the fact of this more powerful force. Once established, that fact must be published, taught, and spread. Legal realism is expected to bring good to society by its inventors, who quickly become, if they were not from the first, its advocates. It asserts that our law will be better if through clear thinking we dispense with its irrational majesty. This realism is really idealism. In the old days, when philosophy was young, the pre-Socratic philosophers thought that laws were made for the convenience of rulers and nothing good was to be expected from politics. They thought that was realism. In America, advocates of legal realism have arisen from the Progressive tradition, joined now by libertarian conservatives, who claim public good will result from their public unmasking of law. Despite the fact (as they maintain) that no one aims for the public good, they believe it does exist; Socrates was right about that. The sort of thinking our legal realists recommend can be seen in the famous prisoner's dilemma that is the essence of game theory, the most fashionable mode of legal realism. The prisoner's dilemma posits a situation in which a prisoner must choose between defecting from a fellow prisoner and cooperating with him. We do not know whether the prisoner is guilty and should therefore confess his crimes. We do not know whether the law he may or may not have violated deserves to be respected. But the example is not as neutral as it seems. One's sympathies are unjustifiably enlisted on the side of the prisoner by adopting his point of view. From the standpoint of the law, he is defecting from the law instead of cooperating with it by confessing, as is his duty. The example substitut","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"36 1","pages":"117"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2013-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68772267","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 8
The Rule of Law and the Inevitability of Discretion 法治与自由裁量权的必然性
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2013-01-01 DOI: 10.31228/osf.io/savny
P. Shane
Responding to Richard Epstein's writings on the rule of law in the administrative state, this paper argues that it is impossible to advance a compelling conception of the rule of law that relies entirely on confining government discretion through clear rules. What is needed is a conception of the rule of law rooted in institutional practice, in which the written documents of law [are] buttressed by a set of norms, conventional expectations, and routine behaviors that lead officials to behave as if they are accountable to the public interest and to legitimate sources of legal and political authority, even when relevant rules are vague and enforcement prospects are remote. Administrative rule-making may well advance these values better than congressional legislation.
在回应理查德·爱泼斯坦(Richard Epstein)关于行政国家法治的著作时,本文认为,不可能提出一个完全依赖于通过明确的规则限制政府自由裁量权的令人信服的法治概念。我们需要的是一种植根于制度实践的法治观念,在这种法治观念中,法律的书面文件得到一套规范、传统期望和日常行为的支持,这些规范、传统期望和日常行为使官员表现得好像他们对公共利益和合法的法律和政治权威来源负责,即使相关规则含糊不清,执行前景渺茫。行政法规的制定可能比国会立法更好地推进这些价值观。
{"title":"The Rule of Law and the Inevitability of Discretion","authors":"P. Shane","doi":"10.31228/osf.io/savny","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.31228/osf.io/savny","url":null,"abstract":"Responding to Richard Epstein's writings on the rule of law in the administrative state, this paper argues that it is impossible to advance a compelling conception of the rule of law that relies entirely on confining government discretion through clear rules. What is needed is a conception of the rule of law rooted in institutional practice, in which the written documents of law [are] buttressed by a set of norms, conventional expectations, and routine behaviors that lead officials to behave as if they are accountable to the public interest and to legitimate sources of legal and political authority, even when relevant rules are vague and enforcement prospects are remote. Administrative rule-making may well advance these values better than congressional legislation.","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"36 1","pages":"21"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2013-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"69640693","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 5
The Obama Administration and the War on Terror 奥巴马政府和反恐战争
IF 0.6 4区 社会学 Q3 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2010-06-22 DOI: 10.1057/9781137380364.0010
M. B. Mukasey
{"title":"The Obama Administration and the War on Terror","authors":"M. B. Mukasey","doi":"10.1057/9781137380364.0010","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137380364.0010","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46083,"journal":{"name":"Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy","volume":"33 1","pages":"953"},"PeriodicalIF":0.6,"publicationDate":"2010-06-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"58220831","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1