首页 > 最新文献

EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY最新文献

英文 中文
The Dissatisfactions of Self-Consciousness 自我意识的不满
IF 0.7 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-09-30 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.13002
Joseph K. Schear

Robert Pippin has long defended the Hegelian ‘satisfactions of self-consciousness’ against virtually all attacks, including Heidegger's. He now concedes in a striking reversal that ‘Heidegger is right’. Pippin diagnoses his past allegiance to the Western rationalist tradition culminating in Hegel as resting on ‘a misplaced confidence in the inescapably self-reflective character of any orientation or attunement to the meaningfulness of Being’. What were once the satisfactions of self-consciousness have become its dissatisfactions. But does Pippin's presentation of the rationalist position ultimately make it too easy for Heidegger to topple it? Will the rationalist impulse, interpreted more charitably, rest undisturbed by Pippin's Heideggerian challenge? I identify three assumptions Pippin's Heidegger makes about the role of reason in our orientation towards the world. If these assumptions are considered not only optional but falsifying by any sound rationalist, this will damage the power of Pippin's Heidegerrian critique. For it is only against the background of a credible picture of the presence of reason in human life that the dissatisfactions of self-consciousness can emerge to reveal a genuine alternative.

长期以来,罗伯特-皮平一直在为黑格尔的 "自我意识的满足 "辩护,反对几乎所有的攻击,包括海德格尔的攻击。现在,他惊人地反过来承认 "海德格尔是对的"。皮平诊断说,他过去对以黑格尔为顶峰的西方理性主义传统的忠诚,是建立在 "一种错误的自信之上,这种自信认为,对存在的意义性的任何取向或调适,都不可避免地具有自我反思的特征"。自我意识曾经是令人满意的,但现在却成了令人不满意的。但是,皮平对理性主义立场的表述最终是否会使海德格尔太容易推翻这一立场呢?皮平的海德格尔式挑战是否会使理性主义的冲动在得到更为善意的诠释后安然无恙?我指出了皮平笔下的海德格尔对理性在我们面向世界时所扮演的角色所做的三个假设。如果任何健全的理性主义者都认为这些假设不仅是可有可无的,而且是可以证伪的,那么这将损害皮平的海德格尔式批判的力量。因为只有在人类生活中理性存在的可信图景的背景下,自我意识的不满才能显现出来,从而揭示出真正的替代方案。
{"title":"The Dissatisfactions of Self-Consciousness","authors":"Joseph K. Schear","doi":"10.1111/ejop.13002","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.13002","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Robert Pippin has long defended the Hegelian ‘satisfactions of self-consciousness’ against virtually all attacks, including Heidegger's. He now concedes in a striking reversal that ‘Heidegger is right’. Pippin diagnoses his past allegiance to the Western rationalist tradition culminating in Hegel as resting on ‘a misplaced confidence in the inescapably self-reflective character of any orientation or attunement to the meaningfulness of Being’. What were once the satisfactions of self-consciousness have become its dissatisfactions. But does Pippin's presentation of the rationalist position ultimately make it too easy for Heidegger to topple it? Will the rationalist impulse, interpreted more charitably, rest undisturbed by Pippin's Heideggerian challenge? I identify three assumptions Pippin's Heidegger makes about the role of reason in our orientation towards the world. If these assumptions are considered not only optional but falsifying by any sound rationalist, this will damage the power of Pippin's Heidegerrian critique. For it is only against the background of a credible picture of the presence of reason in human life that the dissatisfactions of self-consciousness can emerge to reveal a genuine alternative.</p>","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"32 3","pages":"919-925"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-09-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/ejop.13002","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142404778","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Bradley's Regress and a Problem in Action Theory 布拉德利的回归与行动理论中的一个问题
IF 0.7 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-09-30 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.13016
Helen Steward
<p>There is a problem which often arises during the course of various discussions in action theory and related fields about how exactly we are to characterise the relation which obtains between an agent and her (token) actions. An agent is a particular individual; it is often assumed that any token action of hers must be another.<sup>1</sup> But what is the relation between these two particulars, when the agent is the agent of the action in question? Obviously, one asymmetric relation between them is this: the agent, S, <i>is the agent of</i> the action, A. But is there a <i>further</i> relation between agent and action <i>in virtue of which</i> it is correct to say that A is S's action? The idea that agency must be reducible to something assumed to be more basic, such as causation, has sometimes tempted philosophers to think so – and there are also fairly common locutions which can make it seem as though S's being the agent of an action, A might hold in virtue of another, perhaps more basic relationship – ‘execution’ or ‘performance’, or simply ‘doing’, for example. But as I shall try to show below, it is not at all easy to make any of these ideas work.</p><p>In order to have a handy label for the problem which attaches to this search for a relation to undergird propositions of the form ‘S is the agent of A', I am going to call it the ‘agent-action problem’. The problem has rarely been acknowledged as a <i>general</i> difficulty – although it gives rise to various sub-problems, which have been often enough remarked upon.<sup>2</sup> Moreover, even when the sub-problems are observed, they are sometimes noted merely as passing curiosities which perhaps constitute nothing more than minor linguistic inconveniences to the philosopher of action. In a way, then, neither the sub-problems nor the fundamental problem which in my view underlies the sub-problems has really received any serious, sustained scrutiny of a properly wide-ranging sort. In this paper, I want to suggest, however, that it deserves such scrutiny – and that a failure properly to get to grips with the general form of the problem is indicative of philosophy of action's failure to get a decent ontological understanding of its own subject matter. This failure, I believe, is connected to some of the puzzles in which philosophers find themselves embroiled, with respect to such issues as whether agents are causes of their actions<sup>3</sup>; whether the agent ‘disappears' in a problematic way from certain pictures of what action involves<sup>4</sup>; and which physical events, precisely, compose or constitute our actions.<sup>5</sup> I want to argue that once we understand the true source of the agent-action problem, it can be seen that the problem is related in certain interesting ways to the philosophical difficulty which has come to be known as ‘Bradley's Regress'. The range of options for responding to it can, I think, therefore be usefully illuminated by reflecting on those that have be
我们当然会经常提到人们做的事情,也会谈论我们做过的事情--我们可能会自然而然地认为,我们做的这些事情一定就是我们的行动。但是,正如霍恩斯比在其(1980 年)一书中有力地论证的那样,我们说我们做的这些事情当然不可能是象征性的行为。为了用英语谈论个人行为,哲学家们通常会使用所谓的 "完形助词"--"我举起手臂"、"凯撒越过卢比孔河"、"奥斯瓦尔德射杀肯尼迪 "等形式的表达。这些句子是由我笼统地(并不令人满意地)称之为'动作句'的句子6 (为了目前的目的,我认为这些句子是SUBJ + VERB ± OBJ形式的基本句子--如'我举起了我的手臂'、'凯撒越过了卢比孔河'、'奥斯瓦尔德射杀了肯尼迪'等句子)通过一个我们可以大致这样描述的方法派生出来的:使用动名词结构对动词进行名词化,将主语转换为适当的所有格形容词,并插入一个适当的介词(通常是 "的")来连接句子的宾语(如果有的话)。7通过这种方法,我们可以得出像上面这样的名词性表达式,这类表达式似乎是指特定的动作。但这些表达式不能在 "S does/did A "模式中代替 "A"。例如,我没有举起手臂;凯撒没有越过卢比孔河;奥斯瓦尔德没有射杀肯尼迪。这些表达显然不合语法。正如霍恩斯比指出的,我们在 "你做了什么"、"她做了什么 "等语境中使用 "做 "时,应该把它看作是一个图式动词8 。根据对 "行为 "一词的理解,"举起手臂"、"跨过卢比孔河"、"过河"、"向某人开枪"、"向肯尼迪开枪 "都是行为。霍恩斯比(Hornsby)认为,我们所做的事情正是后面这些事情,即行为而非单个行动。但我并没有做铺床、吃早餐和赶火车的事。如果有人在回答 "你做了什么?"这个问题时提供的不是一个完整的命题,而是一个单数词,那么他就会给出一个无穷式结构--"关上大门";"在圣杯里下毒";"点火"。或者考虑一下下面的例子:"凯撒死前要做的是修改他的遗嘱"。(维金斯,1985:285)。在这里,凯撒要做的事(他要做的事情)显然不可能是一个单独的行为,因为 "凯撒要做的事 "这一表述并没有因为凯撒被刺杀而失去所指,因为凯撒被刺杀阻止了任何这种单独的遗嘱改写行为的发生。即使凯撒从未做过,但他仍有事情要做。如果他做了,同样的事情就会变成凯撒做过的事情。但这意味着,如果我们认真对待语法结构,人们所做的事情就必须是事情的类型;它们不可能是单独的行为。此外,由于'做'在这种语境中是一个图式动词,我们与这些行为之间甚至不存在'做'的关系,更不用说我们与我们的象征性行为之间存在这种关系了。例如,"I do raise my arm "是不合语法的(除非 "do "被当作助动词来读,只是为了强调动词 "raise "在英语中一般用现在时的习惯读法,如 "I do raise my arm when I have a question to ask!")。而'Do'则代替了这些其他动词短语,当我们想笼统地谈论行为时,'Do'就代替了它们(例如,'I did lots of things this morning - I made my bed, cleaned the bathroom and prepared lunch')。在这里,"做了很多事情 "是泛指,而 "铺床"、"打扫卫生间 "和 "准备午餐 "提供了相关 "所做事情 "的一些具体说明。因此,即使在这里,"做 "本身也不是行为主体与任何事物的关系。它并没有把行为主体与行为类型联系起来,就像它没有把行为主体与行为标记联系起来一样。哲学家在探讨行为主体与行为之间的关系时,另一个常用的方法是哲学上的多用途工具--"执行"。据说,行为是我们执行的事情。与 "do "不同,"perform "的确可以代表一种关系--就像它在这些句子中所代表的那样:唱诗班演奏了亨德尔的《弥赛亚》;"我表演了福斯伯里空翻";"乔治表演了海姆立克急救法"。
{"title":"Bradley's Regress and a Problem in Action Theory","authors":"Helen Steward","doi":"10.1111/ejop.13016","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.13016","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;p&gt;There is a problem which often arises during the course of various discussions in action theory and related fields about how exactly we are to characterise the relation which obtains between an agent and her (token) actions. An agent is a particular individual; it is often assumed that any token action of hers must be another.&lt;sup&gt;1&lt;/sup&gt; But what is the relation between these two particulars, when the agent is the agent of the action in question? Obviously, one asymmetric relation between them is this: the agent, S, &lt;i&gt;is the agent of&lt;/i&gt; the action, A. But is there a &lt;i&gt;further&lt;/i&gt; relation between agent and action &lt;i&gt;in virtue of which&lt;/i&gt; it is correct to say that A is S's action? The idea that agency must be reducible to something assumed to be more basic, such as causation, has sometimes tempted philosophers to think so – and there are also fairly common locutions which can make it seem as though S's being the agent of an action, A might hold in virtue of another, perhaps more basic relationship – ‘execution’ or ‘performance’, or simply ‘doing’, for example. But as I shall try to show below, it is not at all easy to make any of these ideas work.&lt;/p&gt;&lt;p&gt;In order to have a handy label for the problem which attaches to this search for a relation to undergird propositions of the form ‘S is the agent of A', I am going to call it the ‘agent-action problem’. The problem has rarely been acknowledged as a &lt;i&gt;general&lt;/i&gt; difficulty – although it gives rise to various sub-problems, which have been often enough remarked upon.&lt;sup&gt;2&lt;/sup&gt; Moreover, even when the sub-problems are observed, they are sometimes noted merely as passing curiosities which perhaps constitute nothing more than minor linguistic inconveniences to the philosopher of action. In a way, then, neither the sub-problems nor the fundamental problem which in my view underlies the sub-problems has really received any serious, sustained scrutiny of a properly wide-ranging sort. In this paper, I want to suggest, however, that it deserves such scrutiny – and that a failure properly to get to grips with the general form of the problem is indicative of philosophy of action's failure to get a decent ontological understanding of its own subject matter. This failure, I believe, is connected to some of the puzzles in which philosophers find themselves embroiled, with respect to such issues as whether agents are causes of their actions&lt;sup&gt;3&lt;/sup&gt;; whether the agent ‘disappears' in a problematic way from certain pictures of what action involves&lt;sup&gt;4&lt;/sup&gt;; and which physical events, precisely, compose or constitute our actions.&lt;sup&gt;5&lt;/sup&gt; I want to argue that once we understand the true source of the agent-action problem, it can be seen that the problem is related in certain interesting ways to the philosophical difficulty which has come to be known as ‘Bradley's Regress'. The range of options for responding to it can, I think, therefore be usefully illuminated by reflecting on those that have be","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"32 3","pages":"629-643"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-09-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/ejop.13016","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142404779","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Exteriority of Thinking: Hegel and Heidegger 思维的外部性:黑格尔与海德格尔
IF 0.7 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-09-10 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.13000
Thomas Khurana

In The Culmination, Robert Pippin offers a stunning reassessment of the achievements of absolute idealism. Having developed some of the most persuasive defenses of Hegel's absolute idealism to date, Pippin now argues that Heidegger's trenchant critique of Hegel has revealed a dogmatism at the very heart of absolute idealism: an unwarranted identification of what is with what is discursively knowable. This dogmatic identification leads to a distorted understanding of the meaning of Being, a reifying account of beings, and a neglect of our own finitude. In this article, I defend Hegel against these charges. The upshot of this discussion is twofold. Rather than evading the question of the exteriority of being, I argue, Hegel in fact aims to reveal that this exteriority is internal to thinking itself. And rather than identifying the meaning of being with discursive knowability, Hegel shows that the meaning of being resides in a form of freedom that goes beyond the self-transparency of knowing.

在《终结》一书中,罗伯特-皮平对绝对唯心主义的成就进行了惊人的重新评估。皮平对黑格尔的绝对唯心主义进行了一些最有说服力的辩护,现在他认为,海德格尔对黑格尔的尖锐批判揭示了绝对唯心主义核心的教条主义:将 "是什么 "与 "可辨认的可知之物 "无端地对立起来。这种教条式的认同导致了对 "存在 "意义的扭曲理解、对存在的重化描述,以及对我们自身有限性的忽视。在本文中,我将针对这些指控为黑格尔辩护。这一讨论的结果是双重的。我认为,黑格尔非但没有回避存在的外在性问题,事实上他的目的在于揭示这种外在性是思维本身的内在性。而且,黑格尔并没有把存在的意义与辨证的可知性相提并论,而是表明存在的意义寓于一种超越了知性的自我透明性的自由形式之中。
{"title":"The Exteriority of Thinking: Hegel and Heidegger","authors":"Thomas Khurana","doi":"10.1111/ejop.13000","DOIUrl":"10.1111/ejop.13000","url":null,"abstract":"<p>In <i>The Culmination</i>, Robert Pippin offers a stunning reassessment of the achievements of absolute idealism. Having developed some of the most persuasive defenses of Hegel's absolute idealism to date, Pippin now argues that Heidegger's trenchant critique of Hegel has revealed a dogmatism at the very heart of absolute idealism: an unwarranted identification of what is with what is discursively knowable. This dogmatic identification leads to a distorted understanding of the meaning of Being, a reifying account of beings, and a neglect of our own finitude. In this article, I defend Hegel against these charges. The upshot of this discussion is twofold. Rather than evading the question of the exteriority of being, I argue, Hegel in fact aims to reveal that this exteriority is internal to thinking itself. And rather than identifying the meaning of being with discursive knowability, Hegel shows that the meaning of being resides in a form of freedom that goes beyond the self-transparency of knowing.</p>","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"32 3","pages":"949-958"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-09-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/ejop.13000","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142215332","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Replies to Nicholas Walker, Taylor Carman, and Peter Gordon 对尼古拉斯-沃克、泰勒-卡曼和彼得-戈登的答复
IF 0.7 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-09-10 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.13003
Iain Macdonald

In what follows, I present my replies to Nicholas Walker, Taylor Carman, and Peter Gordon's reflections on my What Would Be Different? Figures of Possibility in Adorno. I begin by summarizing what is at stake in the book. My reply to Nicholas Walker and Taylor Carman focusses on Adorno's criticisms of Heidegger, who claims that the history of metaphysics has blocked our access to an “other beginning” for thinking. This prepares the ground for a comparison of Adorno's and Heidegger's notions of what I call “blocked possibility.” My reply to Peter Gordon clarifies the relation of “blocked possibility” to actuality and, more specifically, to the actuality of happiness in Adorno's writings.

以下是我对尼古拉斯-沃克(Nicholas Walker)、泰勒-卡曼(Taylor Carman)和彼得-戈登(Peter Gordon)就我的《会有什么不同?阿多诺的可能性形象》一书的思考。我首先总结了本书的关键所在。我对尼古拉斯-沃克和泰勒-卡曼的回复主要集中在阿多诺对海德格尔的批评上,海德格尔声称形而上学的历史阻碍了我们进入思维的 "另一个起点"。这为比较阿多诺和海德格尔关于我所说的 "受阻的可能性 "的概念奠定了基础。我给彼得-戈登的回信澄清了 "受阻的可能性 "与现实性的关系,更具体地说,是与阿多诺著作中幸福的现实性的关系。
{"title":"Replies to Nicholas Walker, Taylor Carman, and Peter Gordon","authors":"Iain Macdonald","doi":"10.1111/ejop.13003","DOIUrl":"10.1111/ejop.13003","url":null,"abstract":"<p>In what follows, I present my replies to Nicholas Walker, Taylor Carman, and Peter Gordon's reflections on my <i>What Would Be Different? Figures of Possibility in Adorno.</i> I begin by summarizing what is at stake in the book. My reply to Nicholas Walker and Taylor Carman focusses on Adorno's criticisms of Heidegger, who claims that the history of metaphysics has blocked our access to an “other beginning” for thinking. This prepares the ground for a comparison of Adorno's and Heidegger's notions of what I call “blocked possibility.” My reply to Peter Gordon clarifies the relation of “blocked possibility” to actuality and, more specifically, to the actuality of happiness in Adorno's writings.</p>","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"32 3","pages":"983-992"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-09-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/ejop.13003","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142215333","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Doxastic Agent's Awareness 哆啦A梦的意识
IF 0.9 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-09-09 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.13006
Sophie Keeling
{"title":"Doxastic Agent's Awareness","authors":"Sophie Keeling","doi":"10.1111/ejop.13006","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.13006","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"7 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2024-09-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142215335","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Attention and Attendabilia: The Perception of Attentional Affordances 注意和注意物:注意与注意物:对注意情境的感知
IF 0.9 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-09-09 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.13010
Tom McClelland
Agents are continually faced with two related selection problems: i) the problem of selecting what to do from a space of possible behaviours; ii) the problem of selecting what to attend to from a space of possible attendabilia. We have psychological mechanisms that enable us to solve both types of problem. But do these mechanisms follow different principles or work along the same lines? I argue for the latter. I start from the theory that bodily action is supported by a sensitivity to affordances. Strong evidence suggests that affordances feature in our perception of the world and that affordance perception can trigger the neural preparation of the afforded act. An agent can thus see a teapot as grippable and their doing so can automatically ready a gripping response. Something affords attending for an agent just in case it is a possible target of their focal attention. I argue that we are sensitive to these attentional affordances in much the same way. First I argue that we perceive things as attendable. Second I argue that our doing so can trigger the preparation of shifts in focal attention. My case for this is based on a variety of phenomenological, neurological and behavioural parallels between our sensitivity to bodily affordances and our sensitivity to attentional affordances. This yields a unified account with specific implications for our understanding of attention and affordance perception and general implications for our understanding of how the mind solves selection problems.
代理不断面临着两个相关的选择问题:i) 从可能的行为空间中选择做什么的问题;ii) 从可能的关注空间中选择关注什么的问题。我们拥有能够解决这两类问题的心理机制。但是,这些机制是遵循不同的原则,还是沿着相同的路线工作呢?我认为是后者。我的理论出发点是,身体行动是由对可承受性的敏感性所支持的。有力的证据表明,负担能力是我们感知世界的一个特征,而负担能力感知可以触发神经系统为负担行为做准备。因此,一个人可以把茶壶看作是可以抓握的,而这样做可以自动准备好抓握反应。某样东西能让行为主体注意到它,以防它可能成为其焦点注意力的目标。我认为,我们对这些注意能力的敏感程度与此基本相同。首先,我认为我们将事物视为可关注的。其次,我认为我们这样做会引发焦点注意的准备转移。我的论证基于我们对身体可承受性的敏感性与我们对注意可承受性的敏感性之间的各种现象学、神经学和行为学相似之处。这就产生了一个统一的解释,对我们理解注意力和承受力感知有具体的影响,对我们理解思维如何解决选择问题也有普遍的影响。
{"title":"Attention and Attendabilia: The Perception of Attentional Affordances","authors":"Tom McClelland","doi":"10.1111/ejop.13010","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.13010","url":null,"abstract":"Agents are continually faced with two related selection problems: i) the problem of selecting what to do from a space of possible behaviours; ii) the problem of selecting what to attend to from a space of possible <jats:italic>attendabilia</jats:italic>. We have psychological mechanisms that enable us to solve both types of problem. But do these mechanisms follow different principles or work along the same lines? I argue for the latter. I start from the theory that bodily action is supported by a sensitivity to <jats:italic>affordances</jats:italic>. Strong evidence suggests that affordances feature in our perception of the world and that affordance perception can trigger the neural preparation of the afforded act. An agent can thus see a teapot <jats:italic>as grippable</jats:italic> and their doing so can automatically ready a gripping response. Something affords attending for an agent just in case it is a possible target of their focal attention. I argue that we are sensitive to these attentional affordances in much the same way. First I argue that we perceive things <jats:italic>as attendable</jats:italic>. Second I argue that our doing so can trigger the preparation of shifts in focal attention. My case for this is based on a variety of phenomenological, neurological and behavioural parallels between our sensitivity to bodily affordances and our sensitivity to attentional affordances. This yields a unified account with specific implications for our understanding of attention and affordance perception and general implications for our understanding of how the mind solves selection problems.","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"18 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2024-09-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142215334","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Misinterpreting Negativism: on Peter E. Gordon's A Precarious Happiness: Adorno and the Sources of Normativity 误读否定论:论彼得-E-戈登的《岌岌可危的幸福》:阿多诺与规范性的来源
IF 0.7 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-09-09 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.13005
Fabian Freyenhagen
<p>Adorno scholarship has come a long way in the last twenty years. His philosophy was long overshadowed by the accusation of being too negative. This accusation was made not just from outside of the Frankfurt School research tradition, but crucially also within it, especially from Jürgen Habermas, often portrayed as the leading figure of its “2nd generation”. In Habermas's case the accusation took different forms—sometimes it is about Adorno's theory lacking the standing for social critique; sometimes it is about its lacking normative foundations; and sometimes it is about performative contradiction (between the content of saying that the social world is thoroughly distorted by ideology and the act of saying that). The upshot is meant to be the same in each case: we need a positive normative resource which then provides the standard with which to criticise our social world. That led then to various debates about what that positive standard should be—communicative action, recognition/social freedom, or the right to justification (to name three prominent answers by Habermas, Honneth, and Forst respectively). Especially in the last two decades, there has been more push-back against the accusation (and the purported positive standards). Some—including (full disclosure!) I—have insisted that Adorno's taking a negativistic stance is defensible and, indeed, preferable to the supposedly positive alternatives.</p><p>It is into this context that Gordon seeks to intervene, with his newest book. He rejects the negativistic revival of Adorno, despite accepting that the textual evidence for a negativist interpretation appear to be strong (p. 5). Like Habermas, he thinks we need a positive standard for social critique, but, unlike Habermas, Gordon thinks that such a positive standard can be found in Adorno's work. He is not alone in thinking this – Gordon Finlayson and Martin Seel are among the earlier examples of interpretations which ascribe a positive core to Adorno's philosophy. What is more specific to Gordon, is that he suggests that the ‘source’ of normativity of Adorno's critical theory of society is a ‘maximalist demand for happiness’ in the broad sense of human flourishing (pp. xvi-xviii and <i>passim</i>, especially Chapter 2). It is this demand that animates Adorno's materialist ‘ethics of vulnerability’ (pp. 15, 196–197). The demand for happiness is immanent in the social world, notably in certain experiences and elements that have anticipatory character (pp. 46, 56–57, 70, 210), pointing to complete flourishing and alluding to the good even in the distorted instances of happiness that the wrong social world affords us (pp. 54–57, 70–71). In this way, precarious happiness (or precarious experience of happiness) gives us a glimpse of complete, comprehensive happiness; and is the source for immanent social critique.</p><p>Gordon clearly thinks that an orientation towards human flourishing has much to recommend it, albeit he does not offer an indepen
{"title":"Misinterpreting Negativism: on Peter E. Gordon's A Precarious Happiness: Adorno and the Sources of Normativity","authors":"Fabian Freyenhagen","doi":"10.1111/ejop.13005","DOIUrl":"10.1111/ejop.13005","url":null,"abstract":"&lt;p&gt;Adorno scholarship has come a long way in the last twenty years. His philosophy was long overshadowed by the accusation of being too negative. This accusation was made not just from outside of the Frankfurt School research tradition, but crucially also within it, especially from Jürgen Habermas, often portrayed as the leading figure of its “2nd generation”. In Habermas's case the accusation took different forms—sometimes it is about Adorno's theory lacking the standing for social critique; sometimes it is about its lacking normative foundations; and sometimes it is about performative contradiction (between the content of saying that the social world is thoroughly distorted by ideology and the act of saying that). The upshot is meant to be the same in each case: we need a positive normative resource which then provides the standard with which to criticise our social world. That led then to various debates about what that positive standard should be—communicative action, recognition/social freedom, or the right to justification (to name three prominent answers by Habermas, Honneth, and Forst respectively). Especially in the last two decades, there has been more push-back against the accusation (and the purported positive standards). Some—including (full disclosure!) I—have insisted that Adorno's taking a negativistic stance is defensible and, indeed, preferable to the supposedly positive alternatives.&lt;/p&gt;&lt;p&gt;It is into this context that Gordon seeks to intervene, with his newest book. He rejects the negativistic revival of Adorno, despite accepting that the textual evidence for a negativist interpretation appear to be strong (p. 5). Like Habermas, he thinks we need a positive standard for social critique, but, unlike Habermas, Gordon thinks that such a positive standard can be found in Adorno's work. He is not alone in thinking this – Gordon Finlayson and Martin Seel are among the earlier examples of interpretations which ascribe a positive core to Adorno's philosophy. What is more specific to Gordon, is that he suggests that the ‘source’ of normativity of Adorno's critical theory of society is a ‘maximalist demand for happiness’ in the broad sense of human flourishing (pp. xvi-xviii and &lt;i&gt;passim&lt;/i&gt;, especially Chapter 2). It is this demand that animates Adorno's materialist ‘ethics of vulnerability’ (pp. 15, 196–197). The demand for happiness is immanent in the social world, notably in certain experiences and elements that have anticipatory character (pp. 46, 56–57, 70, 210), pointing to complete flourishing and alluding to the good even in the distorted instances of happiness that the wrong social world affords us (pp. 54–57, 70–71). In this way, precarious happiness (or precarious experience of happiness) gives us a glimpse of complete, comprehensive happiness; and is the source for immanent social critique.&lt;/p&gt;&lt;p&gt;Gordon clearly thinks that an orientation towards human flourishing has much to recommend it, albeit he does not offer an indepen","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"32 4","pages":"1353-1360"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-09-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/ejop.13005","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142215336","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Introspection: First-person access in science and agency: By Maja Spener Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2024. ISBN: 9780198867449 自省:科学与代理中的第一人称访问:牛津大学出版社,2024 年:牛津大学出版社,2024 年。ISBN: 9780198867449
IF 0.7 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-08-23 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.13004
Christopher Mole
{"title":"Introspection: First-person access in science and agency: By Maja Spener Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2024. ISBN: 9780198867449","authors":"Christopher Mole","doi":"10.1111/ejop.13004","DOIUrl":"10.1111/ejop.13004","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"32 4","pages":"1384-1388"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-08-23","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142215337","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Irony, Tragedy, Deception 讽刺、悲剧、欺骗
IF 0.9 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-08-16 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12997
Gregory Currie
Two theories dominate the current debate over the nature of verbal irony: the pretence theory and the echoic theory. It is common ground in this debate that irony is sometimes both echoic and enacted through pretence; my concern here is with such cases. I ask how these features interact with each other within a form of irony that has not so far been the focus of theoretical attention: hidden or deceptive irony. This enables us to see that interesting cases of verbal irony often target an outlook or point of view rather than some real or imagined prior utterance. This, in turn, suggests a move from the idea of echoic irony to irony which invokes a defective outlook. Using the tools constructed thus far, I focus on an exchange in Euripides' Medea, indicating how deceptive verbal irony gives rise to situations of dramatic irony, and provides a showcase for exhibitions of mastery by characters otherwise lacking control of their situations. I ask whether such instances of deceptive irony encourage audience members to see themselves as side‐participants in the dramas they witness. The question has an empirical aspect we are in no good position to answer; I offer a version of the idea which has at least the merit of not falling victim to obvious philosophical objections.
目前关于言语反讽性质的争论主要有两种理论:假装理论和呼应理论。在这场辩论中,人们普遍认为反讽有时既是呼应的,又是通过伪装表现出来的;我在这里关注的就是这种情况。我想知道的是,在迄今为止尚未成为理论关注焦点的一种反讽形式--隐性或欺骗性反讽--中,这些特征是如何相互作用的。这使我们能够看到,有趣的言语反讽案例往往针对的是一种观点或看法,而不是某种真实的或想象的先前话语。这反过来又表明,我们可以从 "呼应式反讽 "的观点转向 "唤起有缺陷的观点的反讽"。利用迄今为止所构建的工具,我将重点讨论欧里庇得斯的《美狄亚》中的一段对话,说明欺骗性语言反讽是如何产生戏剧性反讽的,并为那些原本无法控制自己处境的人物提供了展示自己的舞台。我的问题是,这种欺骗性反讽是否会鼓励观众将自己视为戏剧的旁观者。这个问题具有经验性,我们无法回答;我提出的这个观点至少没有受到明显的哲学反对意见的影响。
{"title":"Irony, Tragedy, Deception","authors":"Gregory Currie","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12997","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12997","url":null,"abstract":"Two theories dominate the current debate over the nature of verbal irony: the pretence theory and the echoic theory. It is common ground in this debate that irony is sometimes both echoic and enacted through pretence; my concern here is with such cases. I ask how these features interact with each other within a form of irony that has not so far been the focus of theoretical attention: hidden or deceptive irony. This enables us to see that interesting cases of verbal irony often target an outlook or point of view rather than some real or imagined prior utterance. This, in turn, suggests a move from the idea of echoic irony to <jats:italic>irony which invokes a defective outlook</jats:italic>. Using the tools constructed thus far, I focus on an exchange in Euripides' <jats:italic>Medea</jats:italic>, indicating how deceptive verbal irony gives rise to situations of dramatic irony, and provides a showcase for exhibitions of mastery by characters otherwise lacking control of their situations. I ask whether such instances of deceptive irony encourage audience members to see themselves as side‐participants in the dramas they witness. The question has an empirical aspect we are in no good position to answer; I offer a version of the idea which has at least the merit of not falling victim to obvious philosophical objections.","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"281 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2024-08-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142215338","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Knowledge Aided by Observation† 通过观察获取知识†
IF 0.7 2区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY Pub Date : 2024-08-14 DOI: 10.1111/ejop.12993
Adrian Haddock

Anscombe seems to think that, even though “the knowledge that a man has of his intentional actions” is not “knowledge by observation”, it can be aided by observation. My aim in this essay is to explain how I think we should understand this thought. I suggest that, in a central class of cases, knowledge of one's intentional action is knowledge whose canonical linguistic expression is an utterance of the form “I am doing something to that G": knowledge in which the subject, at once, knows himself “as self" (and so, not by observation), and knows an outer object “as other” (and so, by observation). To characterise this knowledge either as knowledge by observation, or as knowledge not by observation, is to characterise it in a manner that abstracts away from its fundamental unity.

安斯科姆似乎认为,尽管 "人对其有意行为的知识 "不是 "通过观察获得的知识",但它可以通过观察获得。我在本文中的目的是解释我认为我们应该如何理解这一观点。我认为,在一类重要的情况下,关于一个人的意向性行动的知识是这样一种知识,其典型的语言表达形式是 "我正在对那个 G 做什么 "的话语:在这种知识中,主体同时认识 "作为自我 "的自己(因此,不是通过观察)和认识 "作为他者 "的外部对象(因此,通过观察)。将这种知识描述为通过观察而获得的知识,或描述为不通过观察而获得的知识,都是对其基本统一性的抽象。
{"title":"Knowledge Aided by Observation†","authors":"Adrian Haddock","doi":"10.1111/ejop.12993","DOIUrl":"10.1111/ejop.12993","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Anscombe seems to think that, even though “the knowledge that a man has of his intentional actions” is not “knowledge by observation”, it can be aided by observation. My aim in this essay is to explain how I think we should understand this thought. I suggest that, in a central class of cases, knowledge of one's intentional action is knowledge whose canonical linguistic expression is an utterance of the form “I am doing something to that <i>G</i>\": knowledge in which the subject, at once, knows himself “as self\" (and so, not by observation), and knows an outer object “as other” (and so, by observation). To characterise this knowledge either as knowledge by observation, or as knowledge not by observation, is to characterise it in a manner that abstracts away from its fundamental unity.</p>","PeriodicalId":46958,"journal":{"name":"EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY","volume":"32 3","pages":"716-727"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7,"publicationDate":"2024-08-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142215339","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1