Pub Date : 2024-08-16DOI: 10.1007/s11050-024-09222-7
Orin Percus, Yael Sharvit
We argue that copular constructions that relate two referring expressions are based on small clauses with an asymmetrical semantics. The small clauses in question are headed by a relational item that selects for an individual and an individual concept, along the lines proposed by Heycock (Canadian Journal of Linguistics/Revue canadienne de linguistique 57: 209–240, 2012). Our analysis allows us to explain the asymmetric properties of these constructions when they occur as complements to think. Additional motivation comes from facts that involve questions based on copular clauses.
我们认为,将两个指称表达式联系起来的共语结构是以语义不对称的小分句为基础的。根据 Heycock(《加拿大语言学杂志》(Canadian Journal of Linguistics/Revue canadienne de linguistique 57: 209-240,2012 年)提出的思路,这些小分句由一个选择个体和个体概念的关系项引导。我们的分析使我们能够解释这些结构在作为think的补语出现时的不对称特性。额外的动机来自涉及基于 copular 分句的问题的事实。
{"title":"Copular asymmetries in belief reports","authors":"Orin Percus, Yael Sharvit","doi":"10.1007/s11050-024-09222-7","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-024-09222-7","url":null,"abstract":"<p>We argue that copular constructions that relate two referring expressions are based on small clauses with an asymmetrical semantics. The small clauses in question are headed by a relational item that selects for an individual and an individual concept, along the lines proposed by Heycock (Canadian Journal of Linguistics/Revue canadienne de linguistique 57: 209–240, 2012). Our analysis allows us to explain the asymmetric properties of these constructions when they occur as complements to <i>think</i>. Additional motivation comes from facts that involve questions based on copular clauses.</p>","PeriodicalId":47108,"journal":{"name":"Natural Language Semantics","volume":"17 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.1,"publicationDate":"2024-08-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142183277","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2024-04-05DOI: 10.1007/s11050-024-09221-8
Ryan Walter Smith
Persian possesses a number of stative complex predicates with dâshtan ‘to have’ that express certain kinds of mental state. I propose that these possessive experiencer complex predicates be given a formal semantic treatment involving possession of a portion of an abstract quality by an individual, as in the analysis of property concept lexemes due to Francez and Koontz-Garboden (Language 91(3):533–563, 2015; Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 34:93–106, 2016; Semantics and morphosyntactic variation: Qualities and the grammar of property concepts, Oxford University Press, 2017). Augmented with an analysis of prepositional phrases introducing the target of the mental state and an approach to gradability in terms of measure functions (Wellwood in Measuring predicates, PhD dissertation, University of Maryland, College Park, 2014), the analysis explains various properties of possessive experiencer complex predicates, including the behavior of target phrases, the ability of the non-verbal element to be modified by a range of adjectives, the direct participation of the non-verbal element in comparative constructions, and the ability of degree expressions to modify both the non-verbal element and the VP containing the complex predicate. Theoretically, the analysis ties transitive mental state expressions to the grammar and semantics of property concept sentences, which are expressed via possessive morphosyntax cross-linguistically, and connects with syntactic proposals that independently argue for a universal underlyingly possessive morphosyntax for mental state predicates (Noonan in Case and syntactic geometry, PhD dissertation, McGill University, 1992; Hale and Keyser in Prolegomenon to a theory of argument structure, MIT Press, 2002). The work here also motivates modifications to Francez and Koontz-Garboden’s original proposal, and opens new questions in the original empirical domain of the analysis of possessive predicating strategies for the expression of property concept sentences.
波斯语中存在许多带有 dâshtan '拥有'的陈述复合谓词,它们表达了某些类型的心理状态。我建议对这些拥有经验者复合谓词进行正式的语义处理,涉及个体对部分抽象品质的拥有,正如 Francez 和 Koontz-Garboden 对属性概念词素的分析(《语言》91(3):533-563,2015;《自然语言和语言学理论》34:93-106,2016;《语义学和形态句法变异》:素质和属性概念的语法》,牛津大学出版社,2017 年)。通过对介绍心理状态目标的介词短语的分析以及从度量函数角度分析可渐变性的方法(Wellwood 在《度量谓词》中,马里兰大学学院帕克分校博士论文,2014 年),该分析解释了拥有经验者复合谓词的各种属性、包括目标短语的行为、非言语成分被一系列形容词修饰的能力、非言语成分直接参与比较结构,以及程度表达同时修饰非言语成分和包含复合谓词的 VP 的能力。从理论上讲,该分析将及物心理状态表达式与属性概念句的语法和语义联系起来,而属性概念句在跨语言中是通过占有性语法来表达的;该分析还与一些句法提议相联系,这些提议独立地论证了心理状态谓词的普遍潜在占有性语法(Noonan 在 Case and syntactic geometry 一文中,麦吉尔大学博士论文,1992 年;Hale 和 Keyser 在 Prolegomenon to a theory of argument structure 一文中,麻省理工学院出版社,2002 年)。本文的研究还促使我们对 Francez 和 Koontz-Garboden 最初的提议进行了修改,并在最初的实证领域提出了新的问题,即分析表达属性概念句的占有性谓词策略。
{"title":"Mental states via possessive predication: the grammar of possessive experiencer complex predicates in Persian","authors":"Ryan Walter Smith","doi":"10.1007/s11050-024-09221-8","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-024-09221-8","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Persian possesses a number of stative complex predicates with <i>dâshtan</i> ‘to have’ that express certain kinds of mental state. I propose that these <i>possessive experiencer complex predicates</i> be given a formal semantic treatment involving possession of a portion of an abstract quality by an individual, as in the analysis of property concept lexemes due to Francez and Koontz-Garboden (Language 91(3):533–563, 2015; Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 34:93–106, 2016; Semantics and morphosyntactic variation: Qualities and the grammar of property concepts, Oxford University Press, 2017). Augmented with an analysis of prepositional phrases introducing the target of the mental state and an approach to gradability in terms of measure functions (Wellwood in Measuring predicates, PhD dissertation, University of Maryland, College Park, 2014), the analysis explains various properties of possessive experiencer complex predicates, including the behavior of target phrases, the ability of the non-verbal element to be modified by a range of adjectives, the direct participation of the non-verbal element in comparative constructions, and the ability of degree expressions to modify both the non-verbal element and the VP containing the complex predicate. Theoretically, the analysis ties transitive mental state expressions to the grammar and semantics of property concept sentences, which are expressed via possessive morphosyntax cross-linguistically, and connects with syntactic proposals that independently argue for a universal underlyingly possessive morphosyntax for mental state predicates (Noonan in Case and syntactic geometry, PhD dissertation, McGill University, 1992; Hale and Keyser in Prolegomenon to a theory of argument structure, MIT Press, 2002). The work here also motivates modifications to Francez and Koontz-Garboden’s original proposal, and opens new questions in the original empirical domain of the analysis of possessive predicating strategies for the expression of property concept sentences.</p>","PeriodicalId":47108,"journal":{"name":"Natural Language Semantics","volume":"17 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.1,"publicationDate":"2024-04-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"140589291","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2024-02-19DOI: 10.1007/s11050-023-09218-9
Luis Alonso-Ovalle, Paula Menéndez-Benito, Aynat Rubinstein
How do modal expressions determine which possibilities they range over? According to the Modal Anchor Hypothesis (Kratzer in The language-cognition interface: Actes du 19econgrès international des linguistes, Libraire Droz, Genève, 179–199, 2013), modal expressions determine their domain of quantification from particulars (events, situations, or individuals). This paper presents novel evidence for this hypothesis, focusing on a class of Spanish relative clauses that host verbs inflected in the subjunctive. Subjunctive in Romance is standardly taken to be licensed only in a subset of intensional contexts. However, in our relative clauses, subjunctive is exceptionally licensed in extensional contexts. At the same time, the interpretation of these relative clauses still involves modality, a type of modality that targets the goals of the agent of the main event. We argue that the pattern displayed by these relative clauses follows straightforwardly if subjunctive is associated with a modal operator that, like modal indefinites (Alonso-Ovalle and Menéndez-Benito in Journal of Semantics 35(1):1–41, 2017), can project its domain from a volitional event. Overall, our proposal supports the event-based analysis of mood (Kratzer in Evidential mood in attitude and speech reports. Talk delivered at the 1st Syncart Workshop, Siena, July 13, 2016; Portner and Rubinstein in Natural Language Semantics 28:343–393, 2020) and extends its application beyond attitudinal and modal complements.
模态表达式如何确定其范围?根据 "模态锚假设"(Kratzer,载于《语言-认知界面》:Actes du 19e congrès international des linguistes,Libraire Droz,Genève,179-199,2013),模态表达式根据具体情况(事件、情况或个人)确定其量化领域。本文为这一假设提供了新的证据,重点研究了一类承载有从句动词的西班牙语相对从句。在罗曼语中,标点符号通常被认为只在一部分内向语境中被许可使用。然而,在我们的相对从句中,从句在外延语境中是例外地被许可的。同时,这些相对从句的解释仍然涉及模态,一种针对主要事件代理人目标的模态。我们认为,如果从句与模态运算符相关联,那么这些相对从句所显示的模式就可以直接得出,而模态运算符与模态不定式(Alonso-Ovalle 和 Menéndez-Benito 在《语义学杂志》35(1):1-41,2017 年)一样,可以从意志事件中投射其领域。总之,我们的建议支持基于事件的情绪分析(Kratzer,载于《态度和言语报告中的证据性情绪》。在第一届 Syncart 研讨会上的演讲,锡耶纳,2016 年 7 月 13 日;Portner 和 Rubinstein 在《自然语言语义学》28:343-393,2020 年),并将其应用扩展到态度和模态补语之外。
{"title":"Eventive modal projection: the case of Spanish subjunctive relative clauses","authors":"Luis Alonso-Ovalle, Paula Menéndez-Benito, Aynat Rubinstein","doi":"10.1007/s11050-023-09218-9","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-023-09218-9","url":null,"abstract":"<p>How do modal expressions determine which possibilities they range over? According to the Modal Anchor Hypothesis (Kratzer in <i>The language-cognition interface: Actes du 19</i><sup><i>e</i></sup> <i>congrès international des linguistes</i>, Libraire Droz, Genève, 179–199, 2013), modal expressions determine their domain of quantification from particulars (events, situations, or individuals). This paper presents novel evidence for this hypothesis, focusing on a class of Spanish relative clauses that host verbs inflected in the subjunctive. Subjunctive in Romance is standardly taken to be licensed only in a subset of intensional contexts. However, in our relative clauses, subjunctive is exceptionally licensed in extensional contexts. At the same time, the interpretation of these relative clauses still involves modality, a type of modality that targets the goals of the agent of the main event. We argue that the pattern displayed by these relative clauses follows straightforwardly if subjunctive is associated with a modal operator that, like modal indefinites (Alonso-Ovalle and Menéndez-Benito in <i>Journal of Semantics</i> 35(1):1–41, 2017), can project its domain from a volitional event. Overall, our proposal supports the event-based analysis of mood (Kratzer in Evidential mood in attitude and speech reports. Talk delivered at the 1st Syncart Workshop, Siena, July 13, 2016; Portner and Rubinstein in <i>Natural Language Semantics</i> 28:343–393, 2020) and extends its application beyond attitudinal and modal complements.</p>","PeriodicalId":47108,"journal":{"name":"Natural Language Semantics","volume":"12 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.1,"publicationDate":"2024-02-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139910426","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2024-02-05DOI: 10.1007/s11050-023-09219-8
Jess H.-K. Law, Haoze Li, Diti Bhadra
This paper investigates force shift, a phenomenon in which the canonical discourse conventions, or force, associated with a clause type can be overridden to yield polar questions with the help of additional force-indicating devices. Previous studies attribute force shift to the presence of a complex question force component operating on semantic content. Based on utterance particles and particle clusters in Cantonese, we analyze force shift as resulting from compositional operations on force-bearing expressions. We propose that a simplex force, such as assertion or question, denotes unanchored sentence acts, while a force-shifting particle like Cantonese ho2 is an anchoring function anchoring a sentence act to the speaker while querying whether or not the addressee can perform the sentence act. The proposed semantics makes predictions about ho2’s interactions with addressee-changing operations and imperatives, as well as about a larger family of force shift phenomena.
{"title":"Force shift: a case study of Cantonese ho2 particle clusters","authors":"Jess H.-K. Law, Haoze Li, Diti Bhadra","doi":"10.1007/s11050-023-09219-8","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-023-09219-8","url":null,"abstract":"<p>This paper investigates force shift, a phenomenon in which the canonical discourse conventions, or force, associated with a clause type can be overridden to yield polar questions with the help of additional force-indicating devices. Previous studies attribute force shift to the presence of a complex question force component operating on semantic content. Based on utterance particles and particle clusters in Cantonese, we analyze force shift as resulting from compositional operations on force-bearing expressions. We propose that a simplex force, such as assertion or question, denotes unanchored sentence acts, while a force-shifting particle like Cantonese <i>ho2</i> is an anchoring function anchoring a sentence act to the speaker while querying whether or not the addressee can perform the sentence act. The proposed semantics makes predictions about <i>ho2</i>’s interactions with addressee-changing operations and imperatives, as well as about a larger family of force shift phenomena.</p>","PeriodicalId":47108,"journal":{"name":"Natural Language Semantics","volume":"134 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.1,"publicationDate":"2024-02-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139766943","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2024-01-22DOI: 10.1007/s11050-023-09220-1
Gabriel Martínez Vera
This paper discusses the discourse contrasts that arise in connection to direct evidentiality in Southern Aymara (henceforth, Aymara), an understudied Andean language. Aymara has two direct evidentials, the enclitic =wa and the covert morpheme -∅, which are used whenever the speaker has the best possible grounds for some proposition. I make the novel observation that a sentence with =wa can be felicitously uttered if the speaker attempts to update the common ground by addressing an issue on the table. In fact, the sentence with =wa that is uttered must be congruent with prior discourse; I tie this to the claim that =wa is a (presentational) focus marker (Proulx in Language Sciences 9(1):91–102, 1987). This paper thus claims that =wa is a marker that combines evidentiality and focus. In contrast, uttering a sentence with -∅ entails that the speaker’s contribution is already in the common ground, which likens this evidential to common ground management operators—there is no congruence requirement in this case. I identify which construction can be used in different discourse settings (conversation openers and telling anecdotes). I implement a formal analysis based on Farkas and Bruce (Journal of Semantics 27:81–118, 2010) and Faller (Semantics and Pragmatics 12(8):1–53, 2019) that links evidentiality and discourse.
本文讨论了南艾马拉语(以下简称艾马拉语)中与直接证据性有关的话语对比,艾马拉语是一种未被充分研究的安第斯语言。艾马拉语有两个直接证据性,即外显词 =wa 和隐性词素 -∅,当说话者有最好的理由支持某个命题时,就会使用这两个直接证据性。我提出了一个新颖的观点,即如果说话者试图通过解决桌面上的一个问题来更新共同点,那么带有 =wa 的句子就能被恰当地表达出来。事实上,带有 =wa 的句子必须与先前的话语一致;我将这一点与 =wa 是(陈述性)焦点标记的说法联系起来(Proulx in Language Sciences 9(1):91-102,1987)。因此,本文认为 =wa 是一个结合了证据性和焦点性的标记。与此相反,用-∅说出一个句子就意味着说话人的贡献已经在共同语中,这就把这种证据性与共同语管理运算符相提并论--在这种情况下没有同位要求。我确定了哪种结构可用于不同的话语环境(对话开场白和讲述轶事)。我根据 Farkas 和 Bruce(《语义学杂志》27:81-118,2010 年)以及 Faller(《语义学与语用学》12(8):1-53,2019 年)的观点进行了形式分析,将证据性与话语联系起来。
{"title":"Direct evidentiality and discourse in Southern Aymara","authors":"Gabriel Martínez Vera","doi":"10.1007/s11050-023-09220-1","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-023-09220-1","url":null,"abstract":"<p>This paper discusses the discourse contrasts that arise in connection to direct evidentiality in Southern Aymara (henceforth, Aymara), an understudied Andean language. Aymara has two direct evidentials, the enclitic <i>=wa</i> and the covert morpheme <i>-</i>∅, which are used whenever the speaker has the best possible grounds for some proposition. I make the novel observation that a sentence with <i>=wa</i> can be felicitously uttered if the speaker attempts to update the common ground by addressing an issue on the table. In fact, the sentence with <i>=wa</i> that is uttered must be congruent with prior discourse; I tie this to the claim that <i>=wa</i> is a (presentational) focus marker (Proulx in Language Sciences 9(1):91–102, 1987). This paper thus claims that <i>=wa</i> is a marker that combines evidentiality and focus. In contrast, uttering a sentence with <i>-</i>∅ entails that the speaker’s contribution is already in the common ground, which likens this evidential to common ground management operators—there is no congruence requirement in this case. I identify which construction can be used in different discourse settings (conversation openers and telling anecdotes). I implement a formal analysis based on Farkas and Bruce (Journal of Semantics 27:81–118, 2010) and Faller (Semantics and Pragmatics 12(8):1–53, 2019) that links evidentiality and discourse.</p>","PeriodicalId":47108,"journal":{"name":"Natural Language Semantics","volume":"6 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.1,"publicationDate":"2024-01-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139518487","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2024-01-17DOI: 10.1007/s11050-023-09217-w
Ying Gong, Elizabeth Coppock
Mandarin Chinese, along with Japanese, Yorùbá, Mòoré, and Samoan, has been argued to lack ‘degree abstraction’, a configuration at LF involving lambda abstraction over a degree variable. These languages are claimed to have a negative setting for a hypothesized ‘Degree Abstraction Parameter’. Recent work, however, has argued for degree abstraction in Japanese and Yorùbá, and degree abstraction has been detected in a number of additional languages. Could it in fact be universal? Here, we focus on the case of Mandarin, and argue that Mandarin has degree abstraction too. We offer three arguments in favor of degree abstraction in Mandarin, based on attributive comparatives, comparatives with embedded predicates, and scope interactions with modals. We also rebut prior arguments for the lack of degree abstraction in Mandarin, considering degree questions, measure phrases, and negative island effects. Taken together, these results show that degree abstraction is not a parameter along which Mandarin and English vary, and suggest rather that degree abstraction may be universally available.
汉语普通话与日语、约鲁巴语、摩尔语和萨摩亚语一样,被认为缺乏 "程度抽象",即在 LF 中对程度变量进行λ 抽象的构型。这些语言被认为具有假定的 "程度抽象参数 "的负设置。然而,最近的研究证明日语和 Yorùbá 中存在程度抽象,而且在其他一些语言中也发现了程度抽象。事实上,度抽象是否具有普遍性?在此,我们将重点讨论普通话的情况,并论证普通话也有程度抽象。我们提出了三个支持普通话中程度抽象的论点,它们分别基于属性比较级、嵌入谓词的比较级以及与情态动词的范围互动。我们还反驳了之前关于普通话缺乏程度抽象的论点,包括程度问题、量词短语和负岛效应。总之,这些结果表明,程度抽象并不是普通话和英语之间存在差异的参数,而是表明程度抽象可能是普遍存在的。
{"title":"Is degree abstraction a parameter or a universal? Evidence from Mandarin Chinese","authors":"Ying Gong, Elizabeth Coppock","doi":"10.1007/s11050-023-09217-w","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-023-09217-w","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Mandarin Chinese, along with Japanese, Yorùbá, Mòoré, and Samoan, has been argued to lack ‘degree abstraction’, a configuration at LF involving lambda abstraction over a degree variable. These languages are claimed to have a negative setting for a hypothesized ‘Degree Abstraction Parameter’. Recent work, however, has argued for degree abstraction in Japanese and Yorùbá, and degree abstraction has been detected in a number of additional languages. Could it in fact be universal? Here, we focus on the case of Mandarin, and argue that Mandarin has degree abstraction too. We offer three arguments in favor of degree abstraction in Mandarin, based on attributive comparatives, comparatives with embedded predicates, and scope interactions with modals. We also rebut prior arguments for the lack of degree abstraction in Mandarin, considering degree questions, measure phrases, and negative island effects. Taken together, these results show that degree abstraction is not a parameter along which Mandarin and English vary, and suggest rather that degree abstraction may be universally available.</p>","PeriodicalId":47108,"journal":{"name":"Natural Language Semantics","volume":"2 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.1,"publicationDate":"2024-01-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139497225","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2024-01-11DOI: 10.1007/s11050-023-09216-x
Richard K. Larson
{"title":"Quantification, matching and events","authors":"Richard K. Larson","doi":"10.1007/s11050-023-09216-x","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-023-09216-x","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":47108,"journal":{"name":"Natural Language Semantics","volume":"31 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.1,"publicationDate":"2024-01-11","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139459163","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2024-01-01Epub Date: 2024-10-14DOI: 10.1007/s11050-024-09224-5
Nadine Bade, Philippe Schlenker, Emmanuel Chemla
In this paper, we show that native speakers spontaneously divide the complex meaning of a new word into a presuppositional component and an assertive component. These results argue for the existence of a productive triggering algorithm for presuppositions, one that is not based on alternative lexical items nor on contextual salience. On a methodological level, the proposed learning paradigm can be used to test further theories concerned with the interaction of lexical properties and conceptual biases.
{"title":"Word learning tasks as a window into the <i>triggering problem</i> for presuppositions.","authors":"Nadine Bade, Philippe Schlenker, Emmanuel Chemla","doi":"10.1007/s11050-024-09224-5","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-024-09224-5","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>In this paper, we show that native speakers spontaneously divide the complex meaning of a new word into a presuppositional component and an assertive component. These results argue for the existence of a productive triggering algorithm for presuppositions, one that is not based on alternative lexical items nor on contextual salience. On a methodological level, the proposed learning paradigm can be used to test further theories concerned with the interaction of lexical properties and conceptual biases.</p>","PeriodicalId":47108,"journal":{"name":"Natural Language Semantics","volume":"32 4","pages":"473-503"},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2024-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC11538235/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142607015","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2023-12-22DOI: 10.1007/s11050-023-09215-y
Furkan Dikmen, Elena Guerzoni, Ömer Demirok
{"title":"When tense shifts presuppositions: hani and monstrous semantics","authors":"Furkan Dikmen, Elena Guerzoni, Ömer Demirok","doi":"10.1007/s11050-023-09215-y","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-023-09215-y","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":47108,"journal":{"name":"Natural Language Semantics","volume":"9 19","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.1,"publicationDate":"2023-12-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"138943939","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2023-11-21DOI: 10.1007/s11050-023-09214-z
Roni Katzir
The sensitivity of focus to context has often been analyzed in terms of focus-based anaphoric relations between sentences and surrounding discourse. The literature, however, has also noted empirical difficulties for the anaphoric approach, and my goal in the present paper is to investigate what happens if we abandon the anaphoric view altogether. Instead of anaphoric felicity conditions, I propose that focus leads to infelicity only indirectly, when the semantic processes that it feeds—in particular, exhaustification and question formation—make an inappropriate contribution to discourse. I outline such an account, in line with Roberts (In Papers in semantics, Vol. 49 of Working papers in linguistics, 91–136, The Ohio State University, 1996) and incorporating recent insights from Büring (In Questions in discourse, Vol. 36 of Current research in the semantics/pragmatics interface, 6–44, Leiden: Brill, 2019) and Fox (In Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 22, 403–434, 2019). This account, which I motivate on conceptual grounds, has no anaphoric conditions on focus placement and has only an economy condition as a potential felicity condition on focus. However, there are cases where the fine control offered by anaphoricity seems needed, either to block deaccenting that would be licensed by a question or to allow local deaccenting that is not warranted by a question. Such cases challenge non-anaphoric accounts such as the present one and appear to support recent anaphoric proposals such as Schwarzschild (In Making worlds accessible. Essays in honor of Angelika Kratzer, 167–192, 2020), Wagner (In The Wiley Blackwell companion to semantics, Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2020), and Goodhue (Journal of Semantics 39: 117–158, 2022). I argue that this potential motivation for anaphoricity is only apparent and that to the extent that anaphoric conditions on focus from the literature are not inert, they are in fact harmful.
{"title":"On the roles of anaphoricity and questions in free focus","authors":"Roni Katzir","doi":"10.1007/s11050-023-09214-z","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-023-09214-z","url":null,"abstract":"<p>The sensitivity of focus to context has often been analyzed in terms of focus-based anaphoric relations between sentences and surrounding discourse. The literature, however, has also noted empirical difficulties for the anaphoric approach, and my goal in the present paper is to investigate what happens if we abandon the anaphoric view altogether. Instead of anaphoric felicity conditions, I propose that focus leads to infelicity only indirectly, when the semantic processes that it feeds—in particular, exhaustification and question formation—make an inappropriate contribution to discourse. I outline such an account, in line with Roberts (In Papers in semantics, Vol. 49 of Working papers in linguistics, 91–136, The Ohio State University, 1996) and incorporating recent insights from Büring (In Questions in discourse, Vol. 36 of Current research in the semantics/pragmatics interface, 6–44, Leiden: Brill, 2019) and Fox (In Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 22, 403–434, 2019). This account, which I motivate on conceptual grounds, has no anaphoric conditions on focus placement and has only an economy condition as a potential felicity condition on focus. However, there are cases where the fine control offered by anaphoricity seems needed, either to block deaccenting that would be licensed by a question or to allow local deaccenting that is not warranted by a question. Such cases challenge non-anaphoric accounts such as the present one and appear to support recent anaphoric proposals such as Schwarzschild (In Making worlds accessible. Essays in honor of Angelika Kratzer, 167–192, 2020), Wagner (In The Wiley Blackwell companion to semantics, Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2020), and Goodhue (Journal of Semantics 39: 117–158, 2022). I argue that this potential motivation for anaphoricity is only apparent and that to the extent that anaphoric conditions on focus from the literature are not inert, they are in fact harmful.</p>","PeriodicalId":47108,"journal":{"name":"Natural Language Semantics","volume":"16 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.1,"publicationDate":"2023-11-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"138520791","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}