首页 > 最新文献

CLASSICAL QUARTERLY最新文献

英文 中文
N. HEINSIUS'S FRAGMENTVM CAESENAS OF OVID'S METAMORPHOSES REDISCOVERED 1 N.海因修斯的碎片vm重新发现了奥维德变形的凯撒1
IF 0.2 3区 历史学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2016-04-20 DOI: 10.1017/S0009838816000264
Luis Rivero García
Among the manuscripts of Ovid's Metamorphoses used by N. Heinsius (1620–1681) and as yet unidentified or given up for lost is the so-called fragmentum Caesenas (Cs), the collation of which was not carried out by Heinsius himself but provided for him by the Hamburg jurist Lucas Langermann (1625–1686), who was a correspondent of Heinsius, Gronovius and Vossius, among others. According to M.D. Reeve, he was also responsible for adding these notes, using the siglum c, to Oxon. Bodl. Auct. S.V.5, which also includes the collations—by another hand—of A (= Vrbinas ueterrimus, our V2) and B (= Berneggerianus, our P2). The variants provided by this fragment affect lines 9.235–11.169 and 13.1–403, although this does not imply that these were the exact limits of its content, as we shall see below. Some of these variants ended up in the notes of the editions by Heinsius himself and by those who continued his work (the most prominent example being the admirable edition of Ovid by P. Burman, in 1727), and it was D.A. Slater who rescued the collation of Bodl. Auct. S.V.5 from obscurity when he included the greater part of the readings of c (the siglum he himself retains) among the rich store of information presented in his work. F. Munari included the fragment in his catalogue, clearly pointing to the uncertainty surrounding its dating (‘aetatis incertae’, the same expression as used by Slater) while adding the information that it was not at that time to be found in Cesena. The succinct information offered by Slater is used by I. Marahrens for her dissertation and by W.S. Anderson for his edition. R.J. Tarrant, in turn, explicitly states that the fragment is now lost. In the following pages, however, I will attempt to show that this fragment is not lost, but still preserved in the Biblioteca Malatestiana in Cesena.
在n·海因修斯(1620-1681)使用的奥维德的《变形集》手稿中,有一份尚未确定身份或因丢失而被放弃的所谓的《碎片》(fragmentum Caesenas, c),其整理工作并非由海因修斯本人完成,而是由汉堡法学家卢卡斯·朗格曼(Lucas Langermann, 1625-1686)提供的,他是海因修斯、格罗诺维乌斯和沃西乌斯等人的通讯记者。根据里夫博士的说法,他还负责在Oxon上添加这些注释,使用sigum c。Bodl。辅助变流器。S.V.5,它也包括由另一只手整理的A (= Vrbinas ueterrimus,我们的V2)和B (= Berneggerianus,我们的P2)。这个片段提供的变体影响了第9.235-11.169和13.1-403行,尽管这并不意味着这些是其内容的确切限制,我们将在下面看到。其中一些变体最后出现在海因修斯本人和那些继续他的工作的人的版本的注释中(最突出的例子是1727年P.伯曼(P. Burman)的奥维德(Ovid)的令人钦佩的版本),是D.A.斯莱特(D.A. Slater)挽救了波德的校勘。辅助变流器。当他将c(他自己保留的siglum)的大部分读数包含在他作品中呈现的丰富信息中时,S.V.5从默默无闻中脱颖而出。穆纳里将碎片列入他的目录,明确指出其年代的不确定性(“aetatis incertae”,与斯莱特使用的表达方式相同),同时补充说,当时在切塞纳没有发现它。斯莱特提供的简洁信息被马拉伦斯用于她的论文,被安德森用于他的版本。而R.J.塔兰特则明确表示,碎片现在已经丢失了。然而,在接下来的几页中,我将试图证明这个片段并没有丢失,而是仍然保存在切塞纳的马拉提斯蒂亚纳图书馆中。
{"title":"N. HEINSIUS'S FRAGMENTVM CAESENAS OF OVID'S METAMORPHOSES REDISCOVERED 1","authors":"Luis Rivero García","doi":"10.1017/S0009838816000264","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838816000264","url":null,"abstract":"Among the manuscripts of Ovid's Metamorphoses used by N. Heinsius (1620–1681) and as yet unidentified or given up for lost is the so-called fragmentum Caesenas (Cs), the collation of which was not carried out by Heinsius himself but provided for him by the Hamburg jurist Lucas Langermann (1625–1686), who was a correspondent of Heinsius, Gronovius and Vossius, among others. According to M.D. Reeve, he was also responsible for adding these notes, using the siglum c, to Oxon. Bodl. Auct. S.V.5, which also includes the collations—by another hand—of A (= Vrbinas ueterrimus, our V2) and B (= Berneggerianus, our P2). The variants provided by this fragment affect lines 9.235–11.169 and 13.1–403, although this does not imply that these were the exact limits of its content, as we shall see below. Some of these variants ended up in the notes of the editions by Heinsius himself and by those who continued his work (the most prominent example being the admirable edition of Ovid by P. Burman, in 1727), and it was D.A. Slater who rescued the collation of Bodl. Auct. S.V.5 from obscurity when he included the greater part of the readings of c (the siglum he himself retains) among the rich store of information presented in his work. F. Munari included the fragment in his catalogue, clearly pointing to the uncertainty surrounding its dating (‘aetatis incertae’, the same expression as used by Slater) while adding the information that it was not at that time to be found in Cesena. The succinct information offered by Slater is used by I. Marahrens for her dissertation and by W.S. Anderson for his edition. R.J. Tarrant, in turn, explicitly states that the fragment is now lost. In the following pages, however, I will attempt to show that this fragment is not lost, but still preserved in the Biblioteca Malatestiana in Cesena.","PeriodicalId":47185,"journal":{"name":"CLASSICAL QUARTERLY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2016-04-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1017/S0009838816000264","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"56743990","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
MOUSIKÊ AND MYSTERIES: A NIETZSCHEAN READING OF AESCHYLUS’ BASSARIDES MousikÊ与奥秘:尼采式解读埃斯库罗斯的巴萨里德
IF 0.2 3区 历史学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2015-10-01 DOI: 10.1017/S0009838815000154
Sarah Burges Watson
In chapter 12 of Birth of Tragedy, Nietzsche describes Socrates as the new Orpheus, who rises up against Dionysus and murders tragedy: … in league with Socrates, Euripides dared to be the herald of a new kind of artistic creation. If this caused the older tragedy to perish, then aesthetic Socratism is the murderous principle; but in so far as the fight was directed against the Dionysiac nature of the older art, we may identify Socrates as the opponent of Dionysos, the new Orpheus who rises up against Dionysos and who, although fated to be torn apart by the maenads of the Athenian court of justice, nevertheless forces the great and mighty god himself to flee. As before, when he fled from Lycurgus, King of the Edonians, Dionysos now sought refuge in the depths of the sea, namely in the mystical waters of a secret cult which gradually spread across the entire world. (Trans. R. Speirs) (Cambridge, 1999), 64
在《悲剧的诞生》第12章,尼采将苏格拉底描述为新的俄耳甫斯,他奋起反抗酒神,谋杀悲剧:……欧里庇得斯与苏格拉底结盟,敢于成为一种新的艺术创作的先驱。如果这导致了旧悲剧的灭亡,那么美学苏格拉底主义就是杀人的原则;但是,就苏格拉底与旧艺术的酒神本性的斗争而言,我们可以把他看作是酒神的对手,看作是奋起反抗酒神的新俄耳甫斯,他虽然注定要被雅典法庭上的女侍们撕成两半,但却迫使这位伟大的神自己逃走了。和以前一样,当他逃离伊多尼亚国王莱库格斯时,狄奥尼索斯现在在深海中寻求庇护,也就是在一个逐渐传遍全世界的秘密崇拜的神秘水域中。(反式。R. Speirs)(剑桥,1999),64
{"title":"MOUSIKÊ AND MYSTERIES: A NIETZSCHEAN READING OF AESCHYLUS’ BASSARIDES","authors":"Sarah Burges Watson","doi":"10.1017/S0009838815000154","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838815000154","url":null,"abstract":"In chapter 12 of Birth of Tragedy, Nietzsche describes Socrates as the new Orpheus, who rises up against Dionysus and murders tragedy: … in league with Socrates, Euripides dared to be the herald of a new kind of artistic creation. If this caused the older tragedy to perish, then aesthetic Socratism is the murderous principle; but in so far as the fight was directed against the Dionysiac nature of the older art, we may identify Socrates as the opponent of Dionysos, the new Orpheus who rises up against Dionysos and who, although fated to be torn apart by the maenads of the Athenian court of justice, nevertheless forces the great and mighty god himself to flee. As before, when he fled from Lycurgus, King of the Edonians, Dionysos now sought refuge in the depths of the sea, namely in the mystical waters of a secret cult which gradually spread across the entire world. (Trans. R. Speirs) (Cambridge, 1999), 64","PeriodicalId":47185,"journal":{"name":"CLASSICAL QUARTERLY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2015-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1017/S0009838815000154","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"56743966","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
A TEXTUAL NOTE TO PLATO, GORGIAS 465a4* 给柏拉图的文本注释,高尔吉亚465a4*
IF 0.2 3区 历史学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2015-09-07 DOI: 10.1017/S0009838815000269
Marco Romani Mistretta
Gorgias 465a2-7 τέχνην δὲ αὐτὴν οὔ φημι εἶναι ἀλλ’ ἐμπειρίαν, ὅτι οὐκ ἔχει λόγον οὐδένα ᾧ προσφέρει ἃ προσφέρει ὁποῖ’ ἄττα τὴν φύσιν ἐστίν, ὥστε τὴν αἰτίαν ἑκάστου μὴ ἔχειν εἰπεῖν. ἐγὼ δὲ τέχνην οὐ καλῶ ὃ ἂν ᾖ ἄλογον πρᾶγμα· τούτων δὲ πέρι εἰ ἀμφισβητεῖς, ἐθέλω ὑποσχεῖν λόγον.
然而,Gorgias 465a2-7,这门艺术既不是名声,也不是经验,因为没有人有理由向他提供他所提供的自然,这样他就不必说出每个人的要求。但我并不认为艺术是一种不正当的行为。但在这些行为中,如果你有疑问,我会坚持下去。
{"title":"A TEXTUAL NOTE TO PLATO, GORGIAS 465a4*","authors":"Marco Romani Mistretta","doi":"10.1017/S0009838815000269","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838815000269","url":null,"abstract":"Gorgias 465a2-7 τέχνην δὲ αὐτὴν οὔ φημι εἶναι ἀλλ’ ἐμπειρίαν, ὅτι οὐκ ἔχει λόγον οὐδένα ᾧ προσφέρει ἃ προσφέρει ὁποῖ’ ἄττα τὴν φύσιν ἐστίν, ὥστε τὴν αἰτίαν ἑκάστου μὴ ἔχειν εἰπεῖν. ἐγὼ δὲ τέχνην οὐ καλῶ ὃ ἂν ᾖ ἄλογον πρᾶγμα· τούτων δὲ πέρι εἰ ἀμφισβητεῖς, ἐθέλω ὑποσχεῖν λόγον.","PeriodicalId":47185,"journal":{"name":"CLASSICAL QUARTERLY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2015-09-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1017/S0009838815000269","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"56743978","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
TWO TEXTUAL PROBLEMS IN BOOK 7 OF VARRO'S DE LINGVA LATINA* 瓦罗的《拉丁语》第7卷中的两个文本问题*
IF 0.2 3区 历史学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2015-04-02 DOI: 10.1017/S0009838814000019
W. D. De melo
In this contribution I wish to tackle two corruptions in Book 7 of Varro's De lingua Latina that have hitherto gone unnoticed or been corrected inadequately.
在这篇文章中,我希望解决瓦罗的《拉丁语》第7卷中的两个迄今未被注意或未得到充分纠正的错误。
{"title":"TWO TEXTUAL PROBLEMS IN BOOK 7 OF VARRO'S DE LINGVA LATINA*","authors":"W. D. De melo","doi":"10.1017/S0009838814000019","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838814000019","url":null,"abstract":"In this contribution I wish to tackle two corruptions in Book 7 of Varro's De lingua Latina that have hitherto gone unnoticed or been corrected inadequately.","PeriodicalId":47185,"journal":{"name":"CLASSICAL QUARTERLY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2015-04-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1017/S0009838814000019","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"56743911","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
AEQVOR: THE SEA OF PROPHECIES IN VIRGIL'S AENEID* 埃克沃尔:维吉尔的《埃涅伊德》中的预言之海
IF 0.2 3区 历史学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2014-11-20 DOI: 10.1017/S0009838814000159
M. G. García Ruiz
In a well-known article, Hodnett pointed out that Virgil emphasizes the peacefulness and quiet of the sea, its immensity and limitlessness, in contrast to the view articulated by the Roman poets of the Republic, which presents the sea as deceptive and fearsome. Among the many terms used in the Aeneid to denote the sea, aequor stands out precisely because it is the term most frequently used by Virgil in place of the word mare.
在一篇著名的文章中,霍德尼特指出,维吉尔强调大海的和平与宁静,它的无边无际,与共和国时期罗马诗人所表达的观点形成鲜明对比,他们认为大海具有欺骗性和可怖性。在《埃涅阿斯纪》中用来表示海洋的许多术语中,aequor尤为突出,因为它是维吉尔最常用来代替mare这个词的术语。
{"title":"AEQVOR: THE SEA OF PROPHECIES IN VIRGIL'S AENEID*","authors":"M. G. García Ruiz","doi":"10.1017/S0009838814000159","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838814000159","url":null,"abstract":"In a well-known article, Hodnett pointed out that Virgil emphasizes the peacefulness and quiet of the sea, its immensity and limitlessness, in contrast to the view articulated by the Roman poets of the Republic, which presents the sea as deceptive and fearsome. Among the many terms used in the Aeneid to denote the sea, aequor stands out precisely because it is the term most frequently used by Virgil in place of the word mare.","PeriodicalId":47185,"journal":{"name":"CLASSICAL QUARTERLY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2014-11-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1017/S0009838814000159","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"56743917","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
THE NORMAL ROAD TO GEOMETRY: δή IN EUCLID'S ELEMENTS AND THE MATHEMATICAL COMPETENCE OF HIS AUDIENCE* 通往几何的正常道路:欧几里得的元素和他的听众的数学能力之间的δή *
IF 0.2 3区 历史学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2014-11-20 DOI: 10.1017/S0009838814000457
S. L. van der Pas
Euclid famously stated that there is no royal road to geometry, but his use of δή does give an indication of the minimum level of knowledge and understanding which he required from his audience. The aim of this article is to gain insight into his interaction with his audience through a characterization of the use of δή in the Elements. I will argue that the primary use of δή indicates a lively interaction between Euclid and his audience. Furthermore, the specific contexts in which δή occurs reveal the considerable mathematical competence that Euclid expected from his audience.
欧几里得有一个著名的说法,那就是没有通往几何的捷径,但是他对δή的使用确实表明了他对听众的最低知识和理解水平的要求。本文的目的是通过描述“δή”在《要素》中的使用,深入了解他与听众之间的互动。我将论证δή这个词的主要使用表明欧几里得和他的听众之间有一种生动的互动。此外,δή发生的特定情境显示欧几里得期望他的听众具有相当的数学能力。
{"title":"THE NORMAL ROAD TO GEOMETRY: δή IN EUCLID'S ELEMENTS AND THE MATHEMATICAL COMPETENCE OF HIS AUDIENCE*","authors":"S. L. van der Pas","doi":"10.1017/S0009838814000457","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838814000457","url":null,"abstract":"Euclid famously stated that there is no royal road to geometry, but his use of δή does give an indication of the minimum level of knowledge and understanding which he required from his audience. The aim of this article is to gain insight into his interaction with his audience through a characterization of the use of δή in the Elements. I will argue that the primary use of δή indicates a lively interaction between Euclid and his audience. Furthermore, the specific contexts in which δή occurs reveal the considerable mathematical competence that Euclid expected from his audience.","PeriodicalId":47185,"journal":{"name":"CLASSICAL QUARTERLY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2014-11-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1017/S0009838814000457","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"56743927","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
INTRATEXT, DECLAMATION AND DRAMATIC ARGUMENT IN TACITUS' DIALOGUS DE ORATORIBUS 塔克图斯《演说家对话》中的文本内、朗诵与戏剧性论证
IF 0.2 3区 历史学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2014-04-16 DOI: 10.1017/S0009838813000736
Christopher S. van den Berg
Tacitus' Dialogus de oratoribus (c. 100 c.e.) may be the most perplexing of the extant Roman dialogues, quite possibly, of the entire Greco-Roman tradition. Despite advances in the rhetorical and literary appreciation of ancient dialogues, this text continues to elude understanding. Oddly, the difficulties stem neither from obscurities of subject matter and presentation nor from any anomalism vis-à-vis the norms of the genre. Six compelling speeches lucidly detail the value, history and development of eloquentia (‘skilled speech’) from the perspective of the late first and early second centuries c.e. They provide convincing accounts of rhetoric and its evolution: the social and political efficacy of eloquentia (Marcus Aper's and Curiatius Maternus' prescriptions on how best to assert oneself with and against the powerful, and the famous yet notoriously tumultuous oratory of the Late Republic), evaluative categories for rhetoric, including the competing discourses that prized renown and canonical status (Vipstanus Messalla's praise of the ancients), or external and absolute aesthetic criteria; and lastly, exemplary instances (e.g. past luminaries) or suitable models for imitation (ancient and modern orators and poets). The richness of these diverse emphases, along with the complex and ambiguous reworking of literary forerunners, not to mention the open-endedness at the work's conclusion, all conspire against the expectation of a uniform message.
塔西佗的《口述对话》(约公元100年)可能是现存的罗马对话中最令人困惑的,很可能是整个希腊罗马传统中最令人困惑的。尽管在古代对话的修辞和文学欣赏方面取得了进步,但这种文本仍然难以理解。奇怪的是,这些困难既不是源于主题和表现的模糊,也不是源于与-à-vis类型规范的任何异常。六篇引人入胜的演讲从公元一世纪末和二世纪初的角度,清晰地详细介绍了口才(“熟练的演讲”)的价值、历史和发展。他们提供了令人信服的修辞及其演变的描述:口才的社会和政治功效(Marcus Aper和curatius Maternus关于如何最好地维护自己与权力和反对权力的处方,以及共和晚期著名但臭名昭著的喧嚣演讲),修辞的评估类别,包括重视声誉和规范地位的竞争话语(Vipstanus Messalla对古代的赞美),或外部和绝对的美学标准;最后,是典型的例子(如过去的名人)或适合模仿的榜样(古代和现代的演说家和诗人)。这些不同重点的丰富性,以及对文学先驱的复杂而模糊的改造,更不用说作品结尾的开放性,所有这些都与人们对统一信息的期望背道而驰。
{"title":"INTRATEXT, DECLAMATION AND DRAMATIC ARGUMENT IN TACITUS' DIALOGUS DE ORATORIBUS","authors":"Christopher S. van den Berg","doi":"10.1017/S0009838813000736","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838813000736","url":null,"abstract":"Tacitus' Dialogus de oratoribus (c. 100 c.e.) may be the most perplexing of the extant Roman dialogues, quite possibly, of the entire Greco-Roman tradition. Despite advances in the rhetorical and literary appreciation of ancient dialogues, this text continues to elude understanding. Oddly, the difficulties stem neither from obscurities of subject matter and presentation nor from any anomalism vis-à-vis the norms of the genre. Six compelling speeches lucidly detail the value, history and development of eloquentia (‘skilled speech’) from the perspective of the late first and early second centuries c.e. They provide convincing accounts of rhetoric and its evolution: the social and political efficacy of eloquentia (Marcus Aper's and Curiatius Maternus' prescriptions on how best to assert oneself with and against the powerful, and the famous yet notoriously tumultuous oratory of the Late Republic), evaluative categories for rhetoric, including the competing discourses that prized renown and canonical status (Vipstanus Messalla's praise of the ancients), or external and absolute aesthetic criteria; and lastly, exemplary instances (e.g. past luminaries) or suitable models for imitation (ancient and modern orators and poets). The richness of these diverse emphases, along with the complex and ambiguous reworking of literary forerunners, not to mention the open-endedness at the work's conclusion, all conspire against the expectation of a uniform message.","PeriodicalId":47185,"journal":{"name":"CLASSICAL QUARTERLY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2014-04-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1017/S0009838813000736","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"56743488","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 10
GALEN, DIVINATION AND THE STATUS OF MEDICINE1 盖伦、占卜与医学的地位
IF 0.2 3区 历史学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2014-04-16 DOI: 10.1017/S0009838813000761
Peter van Nuffelen
Galen's stories about his successes in predicting the development of an illness belong to the best-known anecdotes drawn from his writings. Brilliant pieces of self-presentation, they set Galen apart from his peers, who tried to cover up their ignorance by levelling accusations of magic and divination against their superior colleague. These accusations are usually interpreted as very real threats, as Roman law punished illicit magic and divination. Pointing out that Galen sometimes likes to present himself as a mantis and a prophet, others have suggested that the accusations against Galen and his own self-presentation indicate that the border line between medicine and religion was still fluid. Both approaches correctly draw attention to the social reality that the accusations betray: they suggest that Galen belongs to a group of healers of dubious standing that populated the empire and thus show that medicine did not have a monopoly on healing. Yet such a socio-historical approach may not be sufficient. For one thing, both explanations have their limitations. Regarding the former, it can be said that Augustus' prohibition of divination aimed at controlling prediction about the emperor and one can doubt that a widespread clampdown of all forms of divination ever was intended. A possible objection to the second view is that throughout his oeuvre Galen emphasizes his medicine as a rational undertaking, even as a science (epistêmê). If one takes his self-presentation as a mantis to be more than metaphorical and to indicate the not yet fully crystallized identity of medicine as a separate scientific discipline, then Galen's usual way of understanding his own craft as a ‘science’ is in need of explanation. Besides such possible objections, a different set of questions still needs to be asked: why precisely were accusations of practising magic and divination levelled against Galen and why do they recur so frequently in his writings? Why divination and not, say, poisoning?
盖伦成功预测疾病发展的故事是他作品中最著名的轶事。这些精彩的自我展示,使盖伦与他的同伴们区别开来,他们试图通过指责他们的上级同事使用魔法和占卜来掩盖自己的无知。这些指控通常被解释为非常真实的威胁,因为罗马法惩罚非法魔法和占卜。有人指出,盖伦有时喜欢把自己描绘成螳螂和先知,其他人则认为,对盖伦的指控和他自己的自我表现表明,医学和宗教之间的界限仍然是不确定的。这两种方法都正确地将人们的注意力引向了指控所暴露的社会现实:它们表明盖伦属于一群身份可疑的治疗师,他们在帝国中占据着一席之地,因此表明医学并没有垄断治疗。然而,这样的社会历史方法可能还不够。首先,这两种解释都有其局限性。关于前者,可以说奥古斯都禁止占卜是为了控制对皇帝的预言,人们可以怀疑广泛取缔各种形式的占卜的意图。对第二种观点的一个可能的反对意见是,在他的全部作品中,盖伦强调他的医学是一项理性的事业,甚至是一门科学(epistêmê)。如果有人认为他作为螳螂的自我表现不仅仅是隐喻,而且表明医学作为一门独立的科学学科尚未完全明确的身份,那么盖伦通常将自己的工艺理解为一门“科学”的方式需要解释。除了这些可能的反对意见之外,还需要提出一系列不同的问题:为什么对盖伦练习魔法和占卜的指控是针对他的,为什么这些指控在他的作品中如此频繁地出现?为什么是占卜,而不是下毒?
{"title":"GALEN, DIVINATION AND THE STATUS OF MEDICINE1","authors":"Peter van Nuffelen","doi":"10.1017/S0009838813000761","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838813000761","url":null,"abstract":"Galen's stories about his successes in predicting the development of an illness belong to the best-known anecdotes drawn from his writings. Brilliant pieces of self-presentation, they set Galen apart from his peers, who tried to cover up their ignorance by levelling accusations of magic and divination against their superior colleague. These accusations are usually interpreted as very real threats, as Roman law punished illicit magic and divination. Pointing out that Galen sometimes likes to present himself as a mantis and a prophet, others have suggested that the accusations against Galen and his own self-presentation indicate that the border line between medicine and religion was still fluid. Both approaches correctly draw attention to the social reality that the accusations betray: they suggest that Galen belongs to a group of healers of dubious standing that populated the empire and thus show that medicine did not have a monopoly on healing. Yet such a socio-historical approach may not be sufficient. For one thing, both explanations have their limitations. Regarding the former, it can be said that Augustus' prohibition of divination aimed at controlling prediction about the emperor and one can doubt that a widespread clampdown of all forms of divination ever was intended. A possible objection to the second view is that throughout his oeuvre Galen emphasizes his medicine as a rational undertaking, even as a science (epistêmê). If one takes his self-presentation as a mantis to be more than metaphorical and to indicate the not yet fully crystallized identity of medicine as a separate scientific discipline, then Galen's usual way of understanding his own craft as a ‘science’ is in need of explanation. Besides such possible objections, a different set of questions still needs to be asked: why precisely were accusations of practising magic and divination levelled against Galen and why do they recur so frequently in his writings? Why divination and not, say, poisoning?","PeriodicalId":47185,"journal":{"name":"CLASSICAL QUARTERLY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2014-04-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1017/S0009838813000761","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"56743537","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 8
PROCLUS ON HESIOD'S WORKS AND DAYS AND ‘DIDACTIC’ POETRY 接着是赫西奥德的作品和日子,以及“说教”诗歌
IF 0.2 3区 历史学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2014-04-16 DOI: 10.1017/S0009838813000773
R. M. van den Berg
In their introduction to the recent excellent volume Plato & Hesiod, the editors G.R. Boys-Stones and J.H. Haubold observe that when we think about the problematic relationship between Plato and the poets, we tend to narrow this down to that between Plato and Homer. Hesiod is practically ignored. Unjustly so, the editors argue. Hesiod provides a good opportunity to start thinking more broadly about Plato's interaction with poets and poetry, not in the least because the ‘second poet’ of Greece represents a different type of poetry from Homer's heroic epics, that of didactic poetry. What goes for Plato and Hesiod goes for Proclus and Hesiod. Proclus (a.d. 410/12–85), the productive head of the Neoplatonic school in Athens, took a great interest in poetry to which he was far more positively disposed than Plato had ever been. He wrote, for example, two lengthy treatises in reaction to Socrates' devastating criticism of poetry in the Republic as part of his commentary on that work in which he tries to keep the poets within the Platonic pale. This intriguing aspect of Proclus' thought has, as one might expect, not failed to attract scholarly attention. In Proclus' case too, however, discussions tend to concentrate on his attitude towards Homer (one need only think here of Robert Lamberton's stimulating book Homer the Theologian). To some extent this is only to be expected, since much of the discussion in the Commentary on the Republic centres on passages from Homer. Proclus did not, however, disregard Hesiod: we still possess his scholia on the Works and Days, now available in a recent edition by Patrizia Marzillo.
在最近出版的优秀著作《柏拉图与赫西奥德》的导言中,编辑G.R. Boys-Stones和J.H. Haubold指出,当我们思考柏拉图与诗人之间有问题的关系时,我们倾向于将其缩小到柏拉图与荷马之间的关系。赫西奥德实际上被忽略了。编辑们认为这是不公平的。赫西奥德提供了一个很好的机会,让我们开始更广泛地思考柏拉图与诗人和诗歌的互动,至少是因为希腊的“第二诗人”代表了一种不同于荷马英雄史诗的诗歌类型,即说教诗歌。对柏拉图和赫西奥德有利的,对普罗克劳斯和赫西奥德有利。普罗克劳斯(公元410/12-85年)是雅典新柏拉图学派的多产领袖,他对诗歌有着极大的兴趣,他比柏拉图更积极地对待诗歌。例如,他写了两篇冗长的论文来回应苏格拉底在《理想国》中对诗歌的猛烈批评,作为他对那部作品的评论的一部分,他试图让诗人保持在柏拉图主义的范围内。普罗克罗斯思想中这个有趣的方面,正如人们所预料的那样,引起了学者们的注意。然而,在普罗克罗斯的案例中,讨论也倾向于集中在他对荷马的态度上(这里只需要想想罗伯特·兰伯顿令人振奋的著作《神学家荷马》)。在某种程度上,这是意料之中的,因为《理想国注释》中的大部分讨论都集中在荷马的段落上。然而,普罗克劳斯并没有忽视赫西奥德:我们仍然拥有他的著作《工作与日子》,现在在帕特里齐亚·马尔齐罗的最新版本中可以找到。
{"title":"PROCLUS ON HESIOD'S WORKS AND DAYS AND ‘DIDACTIC’ POETRY","authors":"R. M. van den Berg","doi":"10.1017/S0009838813000773","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838813000773","url":null,"abstract":"In their introduction to the recent excellent volume Plato & Hesiod, the editors G.R. Boys-Stones and J.H. Haubold observe that when we think about the problematic relationship between Plato and the poets, we tend to narrow this down to that between Plato and Homer. Hesiod is practically ignored. Unjustly so, the editors argue. Hesiod provides a good opportunity to start thinking more broadly about Plato's interaction with poets and poetry, not in the least because the ‘second poet’ of Greece represents a different type of poetry from Homer's heroic epics, that of didactic poetry. What goes for Plato and Hesiod goes for Proclus and Hesiod. Proclus (a.d. 410/12–85), the productive head of the Neoplatonic school in Athens, took a great interest in poetry to which he was far more positively disposed than Plato had ever been. He wrote, for example, two lengthy treatises in reaction to Socrates' devastating criticism of poetry in the Republic as part of his commentary on that work in which he tries to keep the poets within the Platonic pale. This intriguing aspect of Proclus' thought has, as one might expect, not failed to attract scholarly attention. In Proclus' case too, however, discussions tend to concentrate on his attitude towards Homer (one need only think here of Robert Lamberton's stimulating book Homer the Theologian). To some extent this is only to be expected, since much of the discussion in the Commentary on the Republic centres on passages from Homer. Proclus did not, however, disregard Hesiod: we still possess his scholia on the Works and Days, now available in a recent edition by Patrizia Marzillo.","PeriodicalId":47185,"journal":{"name":"CLASSICAL QUARTERLY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2014-04-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1017/S0009838813000773","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"56743900","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
THE ARISTOTELIAN CORPUS AND THE RHODIAN TRADITION: NEW LIGHT FROM POSIDONIUS ON THE TRANSMISSION OF ARISTOTLE'S WORKS* 亚里斯多德语料库与罗得斯传统:波西多尼乌斯对亚里斯多德作品传播的新光*
IF 0.2 3区 历史学 Q1 Arts and Humanities Pub Date : 2013-11-08 DOI: 10.1017/S0009838813000207
Irene Pajón Leyra
The ancient sources tell a particular story about the destiny of the works of Aristotle and Theophrastus after Theophrastus' death. According to information provided mainly by Strabo and Plutarch, the texts produced by the Peripatetic school were lost and unavailable during a period of more than two hundred years, from the time of Neleus, the heir of Theophrastus' library, until Sulla's victory in Athens, in 86 b.c., at the end of his campaign against Mithridates. That was the point at which the private library of a famous bibliophile was confiscated: Apellicon of Teos, who at some time at the beginning of the first century b.c. had acquired the autograph papyri that contained the only copies of Aristotle's and his disciple's works. Sulla, so these sources maintain, recovered then for later generations the so-called ‘esoteric writings’ of Aristotle, and this prepared the ground for the general diffusion of Aristotelian thought, and for the work of Andronicus of Rhodes, whose name has gone down in history as the author of the editio princeps of the Aristotelian Corpus.
古代资料讲述了一个关于亚里士多德和泰奥弗拉斯托斯死后作品命运的特殊故事。根据主要由斯特拉波和普鲁塔克提供的信息,从泰奥弗拉斯托斯图书馆的继承人内琉斯时代起,直到公元前86年苏拉在雅典战胜米特拉达梯的战役结束,在两百多年的时间里,逍遥学派的文本丢失了,无法获得。就在这个时候,一位著名的藏书家的私人图书馆被没收了。这位藏书家名叫提奥斯的阿佩利康,在公元前一世纪初的某个时候,他得到了一份亲笔签名的纸莎草纸,里面有亚里士多德及其弟子作品的唯一副本。这些资料认为,苏拉为后人恢复了亚里士多德所谓的"深奥著作",这为亚里士多德思想的广泛传播奠定了基础,也为罗德岛的安德洛尼克斯的著作奠定了基础,后者的名字因撰写了亚里士多德文集的《基本原则》而名留史册。
{"title":"THE ARISTOTELIAN CORPUS AND THE RHODIAN TRADITION: NEW LIGHT FROM POSIDONIUS ON THE TRANSMISSION OF ARISTOTLE'S WORKS*","authors":"Irene Pajón Leyra","doi":"10.1017/S0009838813000207","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838813000207","url":null,"abstract":"The ancient sources tell a particular story about the destiny of the works of Aristotle and Theophrastus after Theophrastus' death. According to information provided mainly by Strabo and Plutarch, the texts produced by the Peripatetic school were lost and unavailable during a period of more than two hundred years, from the time of Neleus, the heir of Theophrastus' library, until Sulla's victory in Athens, in 86 b.c., at the end of his campaign against Mithridates. That was the point at which the private library of a famous bibliophile was confiscated: Apellicon of Teos, who at some time at the beginning of the first century b.c. had acquired the autograph papyri that contained the only copies of Aristotle's and his disciple's works. Sulla, so these sources maintain, recovered then for later generations the so-called ‘esoteric writings’ of Aristotle, and this prepared the ground for the general diffusion of Aristotelian thought, and for the work of Andronicus of Rhodes, whose name has gone down in history as the author of the editio princeps of the Aristotelian Corpus.","PeriodicalId":47185,"journal":{"name":"CLASSICAL QUARTERLY","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2013-11-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1017/S0009838813000207","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"56743433","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"历史学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 11
期刊
CLASSICAL QUARTERLY
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1