Pub Date : 2022-04-02DOI: 10.1007/s11166-022-09373-0
Laura K. Globig, Bastien Blain, Tali Sharot
When faced with a global threat peoples’ perception of risk guides their response. When danger is to the self as well as to others two risk estimates are generated—to the self and to others. Here, we set out to examine how people’s perceptions of health risk to the self and others are related to their psychological well-being and behavioral response. To that end, we surveyed a large representative sample of Americans facing the COVID-19 pandemic at two times (N1 = 1145, N2 = 683). We found that people perceived their own risk to be relatively low, while estimating the risk to others as relatively high. These risk estimates were differentially associated with psychological well-being and behavior. In particular, perceived personal but not public risk was associated with people’s happiness, while both were predictive of anxiety. In contrast, the tendency to engage in protective behaviors were predicted by peoples’ estimated risk to the population, but not to themselves. This raises the possibility that people were predominantly engaging in protective behaviors for the benefit of others. The findings can inform public policy aimed at protecting people’s psychological well-being and physical health during global threats.
{"title":"Perceptions of personal and public risk: Dissociable effects on behavior and well-being","authors":"Laura K. Globig, Bastien Blain, Tali Sharot","doi":"10.1007/s11166-022-09373-0","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-022-09373-0","url":null,"abstract":"<p>When faced with a global threat peoples’ perception of risk guides their response. When danger is to the self as well as to others two risk estimates are generated—to the self and to others. Here, we set out to examine how people’s perceptions of health risk to the self and others are related to their psychological well-being and behavioral response. To that end, we surveyed a large representative sample of Americans facing the COVID-19 pandemic at two times (N<sub>1</sub> = 1145, N<sub>2</sub> = 683). We found that people perceived their own risk to be relatively low, while estimating the risk to others as relatively high. These risk estimates were differentially associated with psychological well-being and behavior. In particular, perceived personal but not public risk was associated with people’s happiness, while both were predictive of anxiety. In contrast, the tendency to engage in protective behaviors were predicted by peoples’ estimated risk to the population, but not to themselves. This raises the possibility that people were predominantly engaging in protective behaviors for the benefit of others. The findings can inform public policy aimed at protecting people’s psychological well-being and physical health during global threats.</p>","PeriodicalId":48066,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Risk and Uncertainty","volume":"244 1‐2","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":4.7,"publicationDate":"2022-04-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"138496256","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"经济学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2022-04-01DOI: 10.1007/s11166-022-09379-8
Dhaval M. Dave, Joseph J. Sabia, Samuel Safford
{"title":"The limits of reopening policy to alter economic behavior: New evidence from Texas","authors":"Dhaval M. Dave, Joseph J. Sabia, Samuel Safford","doi":"10.1007/s11166-022-09379-8","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-022-09379-8","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":48066,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Risk and Uncertainty","volume":"64 1","pages":"109 - 145"},"PeriodicalIF":4.7,"publicationDate":"2022-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46222285","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"经济学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2022-03-22DOI: 10.1007/s11166-022-09374-z
Y. Tsutsui, I. Tsutsui-Kimura
{"title":"How does risk preference change under the stress of COVID-19? Evidence from Japan","authors":"Y. Tsutsui, I. Tsutsui-Kimura","doi":"10.1007/s11166-022-09374-z","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-022-09374-z","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":48066,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Risk and Uncertainty","volume":"64 1","pages":"191 - 212"},"PeriodicalIF":4.7,"publicationDate":"2022-03-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"52529969","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"经济学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2022-03-01DOI: 10.1007/s11166-022-09378-9
Michael E Darden, R. Kaestner
{"title":"Smoking, selection, and medical care expenditures","authors":"Michael E Darden, R. Kaestner","doi":"10.1007/s11166-022-09378-9","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-022-09378-9","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":48066,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Risk and Uncertainty","volume":"64 1","pages":"251 - 285"},"PeriodicalIF":4.7,"publicationDate":"2022-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48100001","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"经济学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2022-02-01DOI: 10.1007/s11166-022-09369-w
Zhihua Li, G. Loomes
{"title":"Revisiting the diagnosis of intertemporal preference reversals","authors":"Zhihua Li, G. Loomes","doi":"10.1007/s11166-022-09369-w","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-022-09369-w","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":48066,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Risk and Uncertainty","volume":"64 1","pages":"19 - 41"},"PeriodicalIF":4.7,"publicationDate":"2022-02-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45167187","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"经济学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2022-02-01DOI: 10.1007/s11166-022-09371-2
A. Baillon, Aleli D Kraft, O. O’Donnell, K. van Wilgenburg
{"title":"A behavioral decomposition of willingness to pay for health insurance","authors":"A. Baillon, Aleli D Kraft, O. O’Donnell, K. van Wilgenburg","doi":"10.1007/s11166-022-09371-2","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-022-09371-2","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":48066,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Risk and Uncertainty","volume":"64 1","pages":"43 - 87"},"PeriodicalIF":4.7,"publicationDate":"2022-02-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43831301","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"经济学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2022-01-25DOI: 10.1007/s11166-022-09370-3
Pavlo R. Blavatskyy
Intertemporal choice involves outcomes that are received in different moments of time. This paper presents a new framework for analyzing intertemporal choice as a tradeoff between the cumulative payoff of a stream of intertemporal outcomes and its average delay (similar to the mean–variance approach in modelling risk preferences). Ceteris paribus, a decision maker prefers a stream of intertemporal payoffs with a higher cumulative payoff and a lower average delay. A decision maker with such time preferences always dislikes a partial delay in consumption (splitting one payoff into two, one of which is slightly delayed in time). In contrast, many existing models (e.g. discounted utility, quasi-hyperbolic discounting, generalized hyperbolic discounting or liminal discounting) imply a preference for partial delay. Our proposed model is compatible with the common difference effect (corresponding to a horizontal fanning-out of indifference curves) and the absolute magnitude effect (corresponding to a vertical fanning-in of indifference curves). The proposed model is applied to the standard consumption-savings problem with a constant interest rate. A simple experimental test of the proposed model vs. discounted utility and quasi-hyperbolic discounting is presented.
{"title":"Intertemporal choice as a tradeoff between cumulative payoff and average delay","authors":"Pavlo R. Blavatskyy","doi":"10.1007/s11166-022-09370-3","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-022-09370-3","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Intertemporal choice involves outcomes that are received in different moments of time. This paper presents a new framework for analyzing intertemporal choice as a tradeoff between the cumulative payoff of a stream of intertemporal outcomes and its average delay (similar to the mean–variance approach in modelling risk preferences). <i>Ceteris paribus</i>, a decision maker prefers a stream of intertemporal payoffs with a higher cumulative payoff and a lower average delay. A decision maker with such time preferences always dislikes a partial delay in consumption (splitting one payoff into two, one of which is slightly delayed in time). In contrast, many existing models (<i>e.g</i>. discounted utility, quasi-hyperbolic discounting, generalized hyperbolic discounting or liminal discounting) imply a preference for partial delay. Our proposed model is compatible with the common difference effect (corresponding to a horizontal fanning-out of indifference curves) and the absolute magnitude effect (corresponding to a vertical fanning-in of indifference curves). The proposed model is applied to the standard consumption-savings problem with a constant interest rate. A simple experimental test of the proposed model <i>vs</i>. discounted utility and quasi-hyperbolic discounting is presented.</p>","PeriodicalId":48066,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Risk and Uncertainty","volume":"246 3","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":4.7,"publicationDate":"2022-01-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"138496237","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"经济学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2022-01-24DOI: 10.1007/s11166-021-09366-5
Fabien Perez, Guillaume Hollard, Radu Vranceanu
This paper analyzes within-session test/retest data from four different tasks used to elicit risk attitudes. Maximum-likelihood and non-parametric estimations on 16 datasets reveal that, irrespective of the task, measurement error accounts for approximately 50% of the variance of the observed variable capturing risk attitudes. The consequences of this large noise element are evaluated by means of simulations. First, as predicted by theory, the coefficient on the risk measure in univariate OLS regressions is attenuated to approximately half of its true value, irrespective of the sample size. Second, the risk-attitude measure may spuriously appear to be insignificant, especially in small samples. Unlike the measurement error arising from within-individual variability, rounding has little influence on significance and biases. In the last part, we show that instrumental-variable estimation and the ORIV method, developed by Gillen et al. (2019), both of which require test/retest data, can eliminate the attenuation bias, but do not fully solve the insignificance problem in small samples. Increasing the number of observations to N=500 removes most of the insignificance issues.
{"title":"How serious is the measurement-error problem in risk-aversion tasks?","authors":"Fabien Perez, Guillaume Hollard, Radu Vranceanu","doi":"10.1007/s11166-021-09366-5","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-021-09366-5","url":null,"abstract":"<p>This paper analyzes within-session test/retest data from four different tasks used to elicit risk attitudes. Maximum-likelihood and non-parametric estimations on 16 datasets reveal that, irrespective of the task, measurement error accounts for approximately 50% of the variance of the observed variable capturing risk attitudes. The consequences of this large noise element are evaluated by means of simulations. First, as predicted by theory, the coefficient on the risk measure in univariate OLS regressions is attenuated to approximately half of its true value, irrespective of the sample size. Second, the risk-attitude measure may spuriously appear to be insignificant, especially in small samples. Unlike the measurement error arising from within-individual variability, rounding has little influence on significance and biases. In the last part, we show that instrumental-variable estimation and the ORIV method, developed by Gillen et al. (2019), both of which require test/retest data, can eliminate the attenuation bias, but do not fully solve the insignificance problem in small samples. Increasing the number of observations to N=500 removes most of the insignificance issues.</p>","PeriodicalId":48066,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Risk and Uncertainty","volume":"247 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":4.7,"publicationDate":"2022-01-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"138496236","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"经济学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2022-01-01Epub Date: 2022-06-02DOI: 10.1007/s11166-022-09375-y
Jesper Akesson, Sam Ashworth-Hayes, Robert Hahn, Robert Metcalfe, Itzhak Rasooly
Little is known about how people's beliefs concerning the Coronavirus Disease 2019 (COVID-19) influence their behavior. To shed light on this, we conduct an online experiment ( ) with US and UK residents. Participants are randomly allocated to a control group or to one of two treatment groups. The treatment groups are shown upper- or lower-bound expert estimates of the infectiousness of the virus. We present three main empirical findings. First, individuals dramatically overestimate the dangerousness and infectiousness of COVID-19 relative to expert opinion. Second, providing people with expert information partially corrects their beliefs about the virus. Third, the more infectious people believe that COVID-19 is, the less willing they are to take protective measures, a finding we dub the "fatalism effect". We develop a formal model that can explain the fatalism effect and discuss its implications for optimal policy during the pandemic.
{"title":"Fatalism, beliefs, and behaviors during the COVID-19 pandemic.","authors":"Jesper Akesson, Sam Ashworth-Hayes, Robert Hahn, Robert Metcalfe, Itzhak Rasooly","doi":"10.1007/s11166-022-09375-y","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s11166-022-09375-y","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Little is known about how people's beliefs concerning the Coronavirus Disease 2019 (COVID-19) influence their behavior. To shed light on this, we conduct an online experiment ( <math><mrow><mi>n</mi> <mo>=</mo> <mn>3</mn> <mo>,</mo> <mn>610</mn></mrow> </math> ) with US and UK residents. Participants are randomly allocated to a control group or to one of two treatment groups. The treatment groups are shown upper- or lower-bound expert estimates of the infectiousness of the virus. We present three main empirical findings. First, individuals dramatically overestimate the dangerousness and infectiousness of COVID-19 relative to expert opinion. Second, providing people with expert information partially corrects their beliefs about the virus. Third, the more infectious people believe that COVID-19 is, the less willing they are to take protective measures, a finding we dub the \"fatalism effect\". We develop a formal model that can explain the fatalism effect and discuss its implications for optimal policy during the pandemic.</p>","PeriodicalId":48066,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Risk and Uncertainty","volume":"64 1","pages":"147-190"},"PeriodicalIF":1.3,"publicationDate":"2022-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC9161200/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42587301","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"经济学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
Pub Date : 2022-01-01Epub Date: 2022-07-22DOI: 10.1007/s11166-022-09388-7
Simone Ferrari-Toniolo, Leo Chi U Seak, Wolfram Schultz
Expected Utility Theory (EUT) provides axioms for maximizing utility in risky choice. The Independence Axiom (IA) is its most demanding axiom: preferences between two options should not change when altering both options equally by mixing them with a common gamble. We tested common consequence (CC) and common ratio (CR) violations of the IA over several months in thousands of stochastic choices using a large variety of binary option sets. Three monkeys showed consistently few outright Preference Reversals (8%) but substantial graded Preference Changes (46%) between the initial preferred gamble and the corresponding altered gamble. Linear Discriminant Analysis (LDA) indicated that gamble probabilities predicted most Preference Changes in CC (72%) and CR (88%) tests. The Akaike Information Criterion indicated that probability weighting within Cumulative Prospect Theory (CPT) explained choices better than models using Expected Value (EV) or EUT. Fitting by utility and probability weighting functions of CPT resulted in nonlinear and non-parallel indifference curves (IC) in the Marschak-Machina triangle and suggested IA non-compliance of models using EV or EUT. Indeed, CPT models predicted Preference Changes better than EV and EUT models. Indifference points in out-of-sample tests were closer to CPT-estimated ICs than EV and EUT ICs. Finally, while the few outright Preference Reversals may reflect the long experience of our monkeys, their more graded Preference Changes corresponded to those reported for humans. In benefitting from the wide testing possibilities in monkeys, our stringent axiomatic tests contribute critical information about risky decision-making and serves as basis for investigating neuronal decision mechanisms.
Supplementary information: The online version contains supplementary material available at 10.1007/s11166-022-09388-7.
期望效用理论(EUT)提供了在风险选择中实现效用最大化的公理。独立公理(IA)是其最苛刻的公理:通过将两个选项与共同的赌博混合在一起,从而平等地改变两个选项时,两个选项之间的偏好不应该发生变化。几个月来,我们使用多种二元期权组合,在数千次随机选择中测试了违反独立公理的共同后果(CC)和共同比率(CR)。三只猴子在最初偏好的赌局和相应的改变赌局之间一直表现出很少的直接偏好逆转(8%),但却有很大的分级偏好变化(46%)。线性判别分析(LDA)表明,在CC(72%)和CR(88%)测试中,赌博概率预测了大部分偏好变化。阿凯克信息标准(Akaike Information Criterion)表明,累积前景理论(CPT)中的概率加权比使用期望值(EV)或 EUT 的模型更能解释选择。用 CPT 的效用和概率加权函数拟合后,在马沙克-马奇纳三角形中出现了非线性和非平行的偏好曲线 (IC),这表明使用期望值或 EUT 的模型不符合 IA 标准。事实上,CPT 模型比 EV 和 EUT 模型更能预测偏好变化。样本外测试中的偏好点更接近 CPT 估算的 IC,而不是 EV 和 EUT IC。最后,虽然只有少数几个明显的偏好逆转可能反映了我们的猴子的长期经验,但它们更多的分级偏好变化与报告的人类偏好变化是一致的。得益于猴子广泛的测试可能性,我们严格的公理测试为风险决策提供了重要信息,并为研究神经元决策机制提供了基础:在线版本包含补充材料,可在10.1007/s11166-022-09388-7上查阅。
{"title":"Risky choice: Probability weighting explains independence axiom violations in monkeys.","authors":"Simone Ferrari-Toniolo, Leo Chi U Seak, Wolfram Schultz","doi":"10.1007/s11166-022-09388-7","DOIUrl":"10.1007/s11166-022-09388-7","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Expected Utility Theory (EUT) provides axioms for maximizing utility in risky choice. The Independence Axiom (IA) is its most demanding axiom: preferences between two options should not change when altering both options equally by mixing them with a common gamble. We tested common consequence (CC) and common ratio (CR) violations of the IA over several months in thousands of stochastic choices using a large variety of binary option sets. Three monkeys showed consistently few outright <i>Preference Reversals</i> (8%) but substantial graded <i>Preference Changes</i> (46%) between the initial preferred gamble and the corresponding altered gamble. Linear Discriminant Analysis (LDA) indicated that gamble probabilities predicted most <i>Preference Changes</i> in CC (72%) and CR (88%) tests. The Akaike Information Criterion indicated that probability weighting within Cumulative Prospect Theory (CPT) explained choices better than models using Expected Value (EV) or EUT. Fitting by utility and probability weighting functions of CPT resulted in nonlinear and non-parallel indifference curves (IC) in the Marschak-Machina triangle and suggested IA non-compliance of models using EV or EUT. Indeed, CPT models predicted <i>Preference Changes</i> better than EV and EUT models. Indifference points in out-of-sample tests were closer to CPT-estimated ICs than EV and EUT ICs. Finally, while the few outright <i>Preference Reversals</i> may reflect the long experience of our monkeys, their more graded <i>Preference Changes</i> corresponded to those reported for humans. In benefitting from the wide testing possibilities in monkeys, our stringent axiomatic tests contribute critical information about risky decision-making and serves as basis for investigating neuronal decision mechanisms.</p><p><strong>Supplementary information: </strong>The online version contains supplementary material available at 10.1007/s11166-022-09388-7.</p>","PeriodicalId":48066,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Risk and Uncertainty","volume":"65 3","pages":"319-351"},"PeriodicalIF":4.7,"publicationDate":"2022-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC9840594/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"10548409","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"经济学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}