首页 > 最新文献

European Journal for Philosophy of Science最新文献

英文 中文
The replication crisis is less of a “crisis” in Lakatos’ philosophy of science than it is in Popper’s 复制危机在拉卡托斯的科学哲学中不像在波普尔的科学哲学中那样是一个“危机”
IF 1.5 1区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2025-01-09 DOI: 10.1007/s13194-024-00629-x
Mark Rubin

Popper’s (1983, 2002) philosophy of science has enjoyed something of a renaissance in the wake of the replication crisis, offering a philosophical basis for the ensuing science reform movement. However, adherence to Popper’s approach may also be at least partly responsible for the sense of “crisis” that has developed following multiple unexpected replication failures. In this article, I contrast Popper’s approach with that of Lakatos (1978) as well as with a related but problematic approach called naïve methodological falsificationism (NMF; Lakatos, 1978). The Popperian approach is powerful because it is based on logical refutations, but its theories are noncausal and, therefore, potentially lacking in scientific value. In contrast, the Lakatosian approach considers causal theories, but it concedes that these theories are not logically refutable. Finally, NMF represents a hybrid approach that subjects Lakatosian causal theories to Popperian logical refutations. However, its tactic of temporarily accepting a ceteris paribus clause during theory testing may be viewed as scientifically inappropriate, epistemically inconsistent, and “completely redundant” (Lakatos, 1978, p. 40). I conclude that the replication “crisis” makes the most sense in the context of the Popperian and NMF approaches because it is only in these two approaches that the failure to replicate a previously corroborated theory represents a logical refutation of that theory. In contrast, such replication failures are less problematic in the Lakatosian approach because they do not logically refute theories. Indeed, in the Lakatosian approach, replication failures can be temporarily ignored or used to motivate theory development.

波普尔(1983,2002)的科学哲学在复制危机之后获得了某种程度的复兴,为随后的科学改革运动提供了哲学基础。然而,坚持波普尔的方法也可能至少在一定程度上导致了在多次意外的复制失败后产生的“危机感”。在本文中,我将波普尔的方法与拉卡托斯(Lakatos, 1978)的方法以及一种相关但存在问题的方法naïve方法论证伪主义(NMF;拉卡托斯,1978)。波普尔的方法是强大的,因为它是基于逻辑反驳,但它的理论是非因果的,因此,潜在地缺乏科学价值。相反,拉卡托斯的方法考虑因果理论,但它承认这些理论在逻辑上是不可反驳的。最后,NMF代表了一种混合方法,使拉卡托斯因果理论受到波普尔逻辑的反驳。然而,其在理论检验过程中暂时接受地物不一致条款的策略可能被视为科学上不恰当、认知上不一致和“完全多余”(Lakatos, 1978, p. 40)。我的结论是,复制“危机”在波普尔和NMF方法的背景下最有意义,因为只有在这两种方法中,未能复制先前证实的理论才代表了对该理论的逻辑反驳。相比之下,这种复制失败在拉卡托斯方法中问题较少,因为它们不会在逻辑上反驳理论。事实上,在拉卡托斯的方法中,复制失败可以暂时被忽略,或者用来激励理论的发展。
{"title":"The replication crisis is less of a “crisis” in Lakatos’ philosophy of science than it is in Popper’s","authors":"Mark Rubin","doi":"10.1007/s13194-024-00629-x","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-024-00629-x","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Popper’s (1983, 2002) philosophy of science has enjoyed something of a renaissance in the wake of the replication crisis, offering a philosophical basis for the ensuing science reform movement. However, adherence to Popper’s approach may also be at least partly responsible for the sense of “crisis” that has developed following multiple unexpected replication failures. In this article, I contrast Popper’s approach with that of Lakatos (1978) as well as with a related but problematic approach called <i>naïve methodological falsificationism</i> (NMF; Lakatos, 1978). The Popperian approach is powerful because it is based on logical refutations, but its theories are noncausal and, therefore, potentially lacking in scientific value. In contrast, the Lakatosian approach considers causal theories, but it concedes that these theories are not logically refutable. Finally, NMF represents a hybrid approach that subjects Lakatosian causal theories to Popperian logical refutations. However, its tactic of temporarily accepting a ceteris paribus clause during theory testing may be viewed as scientifically inappropriate, epistemically inconsistent, and “completely redundant” (Lakatos, 1978, p. 40). I conclude that the replication “crisis” makes the most sense in the context of the Popperian and NMF approaches because it is only in these two approaches that the failure to replicate a previously corroborated theory represents a logical refutation of that theory. In contrast, such replication failures are less problematic in the Lakatosian approach because they do not logically refute theories. Indeed, in the Lakatosian approach, replication failures can be temporarily ignored or used to motivate theory development.</p>","PeriodicalId":48832,"journal":{"name":"European Journal for Philosophy of Science","volume":"82 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2025-01-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142936687","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Stopping rule and Bayesian confirmation theory 停止规则和贝叶斯确认理论
IF 1.5 1区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-12-28 DOI: 10.1007/s13194-024-00630-4
Yunbing Li, Yongfeng Yuan

This article mainly investigates whether common Bayesian confirmation measures are affected by stopping rules. The results indicate that difference measure d, log-ratio measure r, and log-likelihood measure l are not affected by non-informative stopping rules, but affected by informative stopping rules. In contrast, Carnap measure (tau ), normalized difference measure n, and Mortimer measure m are affected by (non-)informative stopping rules sometimes but sometimes aren’t. Besides, we use two examples to further illustrate that confirmation measures d, r, and l are better than (tau ,n), and m.

本文主要研究一般的贝叶斯确认措施是否受到停止规则的影响。结果表明,差异测度d、对数比测度r和对数似然测度l不受非信息性停止规则的影响,而受信息性停止规则的影响。相比之下,Carnap测度(tau )、归一化差分测度n和Mortimer测度m有时受到(非)信息性停止规则的影响,有时不受影响。此外,我们用两个例子进一步说明确认测度d、r和l优于(tau ,n)和m。
{"title":"Stopping rule and Bayesian confirmation theory","authors":"Yunbing Li, Yongfeng Yuan","doi":"10.1007/s13194-024-00630-4","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-024-00630-4","url":null,"abstract":"<p>This article mainly investigates whether common Bayesian confirmation measures are affected by stopping rules. The results indicate that difference measure <i>d</i>, log-ratio measure <i>r</i>, and log-likelihood measure <i>l</i> are not affected by non-informative stopping rules, but affected by informative stopping rules. In contrast, Carnap measure <span>(tau )</span>, normalized difference measure <i>n</i>, and Mortimer measure <i>m</i> are affected by (non-)informative stopping rules sometimes but sometimes aren’t. Besides, we use two examples to further illustrate that confirmation measures <i>d</i>, <i>r</i>, and <i>l</i> are better than <span>(tau ,n)</span>, and <i>m</i>.</p>","PeriodicalId":48832,"journal":{"name":"European Journal for Philosophy of Science","volume":"87 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2024-12-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142887426","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Another philosophical look at twistor theory 从哲学角度看扭体理论
IF 1.5 1区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-12-18 DOI: 10.1007/s13194-024-00627-z
Gregor Gajic, Nikesh Lilani, James Read

Despite its being one of Roger Penrose’s greatest contributions to spacetime physics, there is a dearth of philosophical literature on twistor theory. The one exception to this is Bain (2006)—but although excellent, there remains much to be said on the foundations and philosophy of twistor theory. In this article, we (a) present for philosophers an introduction to twistor theory, (b) consider how the spacetime–twistor correspondence interacts with the philosophical literature on theoretical equivalence, and (c) explore the bearing which twistor theory might have on philosophical issues such as the status of dynamics, the geometrisation of physics, spacetime ontology, the emergence of spacetime, and symmetry-to-reality inferences. We close with an elaboration of a variety of further opportunities for philosophical investigation into twistor theory.

尽管扭体理论是罗杰-彭罗斯对时空物理学的最大贡献之一,但有关扭体理论的哲学文献却十分匮乏。唯一的例外是贝恩(Bain,2006 年)--不过,尽管贝恩的文章非常出色,但关于扭体理论的基础和哲学仍有许多值得探讨的地方。在本文中,我们将(a)为哲学家介绍扭论,(b)考虑时空-扭论对应关系如何与理论等价性的哲学文献互动,以及(c)探讨扭论对动力学地位、物理学几何化、时空本体论、时空的出现以及对称性-现实性推论等哲学问题可能产生的影响。最后,我们阐述了对扭体理论进行哲学研究的各种进一步机会。
{"title":"Another philosophical look at twistor theory","authors":"Gregor Gajic, Nikesh Lilani, James Read","doi":"10.1007/s13194-024-00627-z","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-024-00627-z","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Despite its being one of Roger Penrose’s greatest contributions to spacetime physics, there is a dearth of philosophical literature on twistor theory. The one exception to this is Bain (2006)—but although excellent, there remains much to be said on the foundations and philosophy of twistor theory. In this article, we (a) present for philosophers an introduction to twistor theory, (b) consider how the spacetime–twistor correspondence interacts with the philosophical literature on theoretical equivalence, and (c) explore the bearing which twistor theory might have on philosophical issues such as the status of dynamics, the geometrisation of physics, spacetime ontology, the emergence of spacetime, and symmetry-to-reality inferences. We close with an elaboration of a variety of further opportunities for philosophical investigation into twistor theory.</p>","PeriodicalId":48832,"journal":{"name":"European Journal for Philosophy of Science","volume":"115 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2024-12-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142841955","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
What you can do for evolutionary developmental linguistics 你能为进化发展语言学做些什么
IF 1.5 1区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-12-16 DOI: 10.1007/s13194-024-00628-y
William C. Bausman, Marcel Weber

A growing number of linguistic attempts to explain how languages change use cultural-evolutionary models involving selection or drift. Developmental constraints and biases, which take center stage in evolutionary developmental biology or evo-devo, seem to be absent within this framework, even though linguistics is home to numerous notions of constraint. In this paper, we show how these evo-devo concepts could be applied to linguistic change and why they should. This requires some conceptual groundwork, due to important differences between linguistic and biotic evolution. In biological evolution, development generates the organism's variable traits on which selection and drift act. In linguistic evolution by analogy, we say development generates the linguistic variants on which selection and drift can act. “Linguistic development” then picks out how individual speakers produce and comprehend language. It involves much more than just learning. Using this broad notion of development, we distinguish between different types of bias that could operate in the processes of linguistic innovation and transmission, which correspond to genetic mutation and biological reproduction, respectively. Having thus sharpened our conceptual toolbox, we then reanalyze two well-documented cases of linguistic change and show that, in both these cases, linguists have only considered Neo-Darwinian evolutionary explanations, falsely deploying an exclusive disjunction of selection and drift. We show that there is at least a third relevant alternative in these examples, namely developmental constraint or bias in the sense we explicate here.

越来越多的语言学家试图用涉及选择或漂移的文化进化模型来解释语言是如何变化的。在进化发展生物学或 evo-devo 中占据中心位置的发展制约和偏差似乎并没有出现在这一框架中,尽管语言学中存在大量的制约概念。在本文中,我们将展示如何将这些进化-变形概念应用于语言变化,以及为什么要这样做。这需要一些概念上的基础工作,因为语言进化与生物进化之间存在重要差异。在生物进化中,生物的发展产生了可变的性状,而选择和漂移作用于这些性状。类比到语言进化中,我们说发展产生了语言变体,选择和漂移可以作用于语言变体。然后,"语言的发展 "就会挑出个体说话者是如何产生和理解语言的。它涉及的不仅仅是学习。利用这一广义的发展概念,我们区分了在语言创新和传播过程中可能出现的不同类型的偏差,它们分别对应于基因突变和生物繁殖。在完善了我们的概念工具箱之后,我们重新分析了两个有据可查的语言变化案例,并表明在这两个案例中,语言学家都只考虑了新达尔文进化论的解释,错误地将选择和漂移割裂开来。我们表明,在这些案例中至少还有第三种相关的选择,即我们在此所阐释的发展制约或偏差。
{"title":"What you can do for evolutionary developmental linguistics","authors":"William C. Bausman, Marcel Weber","doi":"10.1007/s13194-024-00628-y","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-024-00628-y","url":null,"abstract":"<p>A growing number of linguistic attempts to explain how languages change use cultural-evolutionary models involving selection or drift. Developmental constraints and biases, which take center stage in evolutionary developmental biology or evo-devo, seem to be absent within this framework, even though linguistics is home to numerous notions of constraint. In this paper, we show how these evo-devo concepts could be applied to linguistic change and why they should. This requires some conceptual groundwork, due to important differences between linguistic and biotic evolution. In biological evolution, <i>development</i> generates the <i>organism's</i> variable traits on which selection and drift act. In linguistic evolution by analogy, we say development generates the <i>linguistic</i> variants on which selection and drift can act. “Linguistic development” then picks out how individual speakers produce and comprehend language. It involves much more than just learning. Using this broad notion of development, we distinguish between different types of <i>bias</i> that could operate in the processes of linguistic innovation and transmission, which correspond to genetic mutation and biological reproduction, respectively. Having thus sharpened our conceptual toolbox, we then reanalyze two well-documented cases of linguistic change and show that, in both these cases, linguists have only considered Neo-Darwinian evolutionary explanations, falsely deploying an exclusive disjunction of selection and drift. We show that there is at least a third relevant alternative in these examples, namely developmental constraint or bias in the sense we explicate here.</p>","PeriodicalId":48832,"journal":{"name":"European Journal for Philosophy of Science","volume":"200 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2024-12-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142825127","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Between theory and experiment: model use in dark matter detection 理论与实验之间:模型在暗物质探测中的应用
IF 1.5 1区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-12-05 DOI: 10.1007/s13194-024-00623-3
Rami Jreige

There is a complex interplay between the models in dark matter detection experiments that have led to a difficulty in interpreting the results of the experiments and ascertain whether we have detected the particle or not. The aim of this paper is to categorise and explore the different models used in said experiments, by emphasizing the distinctions and dependencies among different types of models used in this field. With a background theory, models are categorised into four distinct types: background theory, theoretical, phenomenological, experimental and data. This taxonomy highlights how each model serves a unique purpose and operates under varying degrees of independence from their respective frameworks. A key focus is on the experimental model, which is shown to rely on constraints from both data and phenomenological ones. The article argues that while theoretical models provide a backdrop for understanding the nature of dark matter, the experimental models must stand independently, particularly in their methodological approaches. This is done via a discussion of the inherent challenges in dark matter detection, such as inconsistent results and difficulties in cross-comparison, stemming from the diverse modelling approaches.

暗物质探测实验中的模型之间存在复杂的相互作用,这导致了解释实验结果和确定我们是否探测到粒子的困难。本文的目的是通过强调该领域中使用的不同类型模型之间的区别和依赖关系,对上述实验中使用的不同模型进行分类和探索。有了背景理论,模型被分为四种不同的类型:背景理论、理论、现象学、实验和数据。这种分类法强调了每个模型如何服务于独特的目的,并在不同程度上独立于各自的框架进行操作。一个关键的焦点是实验模型,它被证明依赖于数据和现象学的约束。这篇文章认为,虽然理论模型为理解暗物质的本质提供了一个背景,但实验模型必须是独立的,特别是在它们的方法方法上。这是通过讨论暗物质探测的固有挑战来完成的,比如不一致的结果和交叉比较的困难,源于不同的建模方法。
{"title":"Between theory and experiment: model use in dark matter detection","authors":"Rami Jreige","doi":"10.1007/s13194-024-00623-3","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-024-00623-3","url":null,"abstract":"<p>There is a complex interplay between the models in dark matter detection experiments that have led to a difficulty in interpreting the results of the experiments and ascertain whether we have detected the particle or not. The aim of this paper is to categorise and explore the different models used in said experiments, by emphasizing the distinctions and dependencies among different types of models used in this field. With a background theory, models are categorised into four distinct types: background theory, theoretical, phenomenological, experimental and data. This taxonomy highlights how each model serves a unique purpose and operates under varying degrees of independence from their respective frameworks. A key focus is on the experimental model, which is shown to rely on constraints from both data and phenomenological ones. The article argues that while theoretical models provide a backdrop for understanding the nature of dark matter, the experimental models must stand independently, particularly in their methodological approaches. This is done via a discussion of the inherent challenges in dark matter detection, such as inconsistent results and difficulties in cross-comparison, stemming from the diverse modelling approaches.</p>","PeriodicalId":48832,"journal":{"name":"European Journal for Philosophy of Science","volume":"47 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2024-12-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142776612","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Guiding principles in physics 物理学指导原则
IF 1.5 1区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-12-05 DOI: 10.1007/s13194-024-00625-1
Enno Fischer

Guiding principles are central to theory development in physics, especially when there is only limited empirical input available. Here I propose an approach to such principles looking at their heuristic role. I suggest a distinction between two modes of employing scientific principles. Principles of nature make descriptive claims about objects of inquiry, and principles of epistemic action give directives for further research. If a principle is employed as a guiding principle, then its use integrates both modes of employment: guiding principles imply descriptive claims, and they provide directives for further research. By discussing the correspondence principle and the naturalness principle as examples, I explore the consequences for understanding and evaluating current guiding principles in physics. Like principles of nature, guiding principles are evaluated regarding their descriptive implications about the research object. Like principles of epistemic action, guiding principles are evaluated regarding their ability to respond to context-specific needs of the epistemic agent.

指导原则是物理学理论发展的核心,特别是在经验输入有限的情况下。在这里,我提出了一种方法来看待这些原则的启发式作用。我建议区分运用科学原理的两种模式。自然原理对研究对象提出描述性的要求,认知作用原理为进一步的研究提供指导。如果一个原则被用作指导原则,那么它的使用结合了两种使用模式:指导原则意味着描述性的要求,它们为进一步的研究提供了指示。通过讨论对应原理和自然性原理为例,我探讨了理解和评价当前物理学指导原理的后果。像自然原理一样,指导原则是根据其对研究对象的描述性含义来评估的。就像认知行为的原则一样,指导原则是根据它们对认知主体的特定情境需求的响应能力来评估的。
{"title":"Guiding principles in physics","authors":"Enno Fischer","doi":"10.1007/s13194-024-00625-1","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-024-00625-1","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Guiding principles are central to theory development in physics, especially when there is only limited empirical input available. Here I propose an approach to such principles looking at their heuristic role. I suggest a distinction between two modes of employing scientific principles. Principles of nature make descriptive claims about objects of inquiry, and principles of epistemic action give directives for further research. If a principle is employed as a guiding principle, then its use integrates both modes of employment: guiding principles imply descriptive claims, and they provide directives for further research. By discussing the correspondence principle and the naturalness principle as examples, I explore the consequences for understanding and evaluating current guiding principles in physics. Like principles of nature, guiding principles are evaluated regarding their descriptive implications about the research object. Like principles of epistemic action, guiding principles are evaluated regarding their ability to respond to context-specific needs of the epistemic agent.</p>","PeriodicalId":48832,"journal":{"name":"European Journal for Philosophy of Science","volume":"215 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2024-12-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142776616","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Recovering particle properties in revisionary ontologies 修正本体中粒子属性的恢复
IF 1.5 1区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-12-04 DOI: 10.1007/s13194-024-00624-2
Sabrina Hao

In this paper, I explore the relation between actual scientific practice and conceptual interpretation of scientific theories by investigating the particle concept in non-relativistic quantum mechanics (NRQM). On the one hand, philosophers have raised various objections against the particle concept within the context of NRQM and proposed alternative ontologies such as wave function realism, Bohmian particles, mass density field, and flashes based on different realist solutions to the measurement problem. On the other hand, scientists continue to communicate, reason, and explain experimental phenomena using particle terms in the relevant regimes. It has been explicitly argued and, for most of the time, implicitly assumed in the philosophical literature that we do not need to take scientists’ particle talk seriously, and recovering position measurement of particles in our ontological accounts is sufficient to make contact with scientific practice. In this paper, I argue that although scientific discourse does not postulate a uniform and coherent ontology, it nevertheless postulates real properties. Our ontological accounts thus need to recover the various properties associated with the NRQM particle concept in scientific discourse. I show that recovering these particle properties is not trivially achievable by pointing out some particular challenges these revisionary ontologies face in the process.

本文通过研究非相对论量子力学中的粒子概念,探讨了实际科学实践与科学理论的概念解释之间的关系。一方面,哲学家们对NRQM背景下的粒子概念提出了各种异议,并基于测量问题的不同实在解提出了波函数实在论、波希曼粒子、质量密度场和闪烁等替代本体。另一方面,科学家们继续在相关制度中使用粒子术语进行交流、推理和解释实验现象。在大多数时间里,哲学文献中明确地论证并隐含地假设,我们不需要认真对待科学家的粒子谈话,并且在我们的本体论中恢复粒子的位置测量足以与科学实践接触。在本文中,我认为,虽然科学话语不假设一个统一的和连贯的本体论,但它仍然假设真实的属性。因此,我们的本体论解释需要在科学话语中恢复与NRQM粒子概念相关的各种属性。通过指出这些修正本体在此过程中面临的一些特殊挑战,我表明恢复这些粒子属性不是轻而易举就能实现的。
{"title":"Recovering particle properties in revisionary ontologies","authors":"Sabrina Hao","doi":"10.1007/s13194-024-00624-2","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-024-00624-2","url":null,"abstract":"<p>In this paper, I explore the relation between actual scientific practice and conceptual interpretation of scientific theories by investigating the particle concept in non-relativistic quantum mechanics (NRQM). On the one hand, philosophers have raised various objections against the particle concept within the context of NRQM and proposed alternative ontologies such as wave function realism, Bohmian particles, mass density field, and flashes based on different realist solutions to the measurement problem. On the other hand, scientists continue to communicate, reason, and explain experimental phenomena using particle terms in the relevant regimes. It has been explicitly argued and, for most of the time, implicitly assumed in the philosophical literature that we do not need to take scientists’ particle talk seriously, and recovering position measurement of particles in our ontological accounts is sufficient to make contact with scientific practice. In this paper, I argue that although scientific discourse does not postulate a uniform and coherent ontology, it nevertheless postulates real properties. Our ontological accounts thus need to recover the various properties associated with the NRQM particle concept in scientific discourse. I show that recovering these particle properties is not trivially achievable by pointing out some particular challenges these revisionary ontologies face in the process.</p>","PeriodicalId":48832,"journal":{"name":"European Journal for Philosophy of Science","volume":"82 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2024-12-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142763422","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Emerging into the rainforest: Emergence and special science ontology 进入雨林:涌现与特殊科学本体论
IF 1.5 1区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-12-04 DOI: 10.1007/s13194-024-00622-4
Alexander Franklin, Katie Robertson

Scientific realists don’t standardly discriminate between, say, biology and fundamental physics when deciding whether the evidence and explanatory power warrant the inclusion of new entities in our ontology. As such, scientific realists are committed to a lush rainforest of special science kinds (Ross, 2000). Viruses certainly inhabit this rainforest – their explanatory power is overwhelming – but viruses’ properties can be explained from the bottom up: reductive explanations involving amino acids are generally available. However, reduction has often been taken to lead to a metaphysical downgrading, so how can viruses keep their place in the rainforest? In this paper, we show how the inhabitants of the rainforest can be inoculated against the eliminative threat of reduction: by demonstrating that they are emergent. According to our account, emergence involves a screening off condition as well as novelty. We go on to demonstrate that this account of emergence, which is compatible with theoretical reducibility, satisfies common intuitions concerning what should and shouldn’t count as real: viruses are emergent, as are trout and turkeys, but philosophically gerrymandered objects like trout-turkeys do not qualify.

科学现实主义者在决定证据和解释力是否保证在我们的本体论中包含新实体时,不会标准地区分生物学和基础物理学。因此,科学现实主义者致力于一个特殊科学种类的郁郁葱葱的雨林(Ross, 2000)。病毒确实栖息在这片雨林中——它们的解释力是压倒性的——但病毒的特性可以由下而上解释:涉及氨基酸的简化解释通常是可用的。然而,减少常常被认为是一种形而上的降级,那么病毒如何在雨林中保持自己的位置呢?在这篇论文中,我们展示了热带雨林的居民如何通过证明他们是紧急的,来预防减少的消除性威胁。根据我们的说法,涌现包括了一种筛选条件和新奇性。我们继续证明,这种对涌现的解释,与理论的可简化性是相容的,满足了关于什么应该算真实、什么不应该算真实的共同直觉:病毒、鳟鱼和火鸡都是涌现的,但在哲学上被不公正划分的物体,比如鳟鱼和火鸡,不符合条件。
{"title":"Emerging into the rainforest: Emergence and special science ontology","authors":"Alexander Franklin, Katie Robertson","doi":"10.1007/s13194-024-00622-4","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-024-00622-4","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Scientific realists don’t standardly discriminate between, say, biology and fundamental physics when deciding whether the evidence and explanatory power warrant the inclusion of new entities in our ontology. As such, scientific realists are committed to a lush rainforest of special science kinds (Ross, 2000). Viruses certainly inhabit this rainforest – their explanatory power is overwhelming – but viruses’ properties can be explained from the bottom up: reductive explanations involving amino acids are generally available. However, reduction has often been taken to lead to a metaphysical downgrading, so how can viruses keep their place in the rainforest? In this paper, we show how the inhabitants of the rainforest can be inoculated against the eliminative threat of reduction: by demonstrating that they are emergent. According to our account, emergence involves a screening off condition as well as novelty. We go on to demonstrate that this account of emergence, which is compatible with theoretical reducibility, satisfies common intuitions concerning what should and shouldn’t count as real: viruses are emergent, as are trout and turkeys, but philosophically gerrymandered objects like trout-turkeys do not qualify.</p>","PeriodicalId":48832,"journal":{"name":"European Journal for Philosophy of Science","volume":"18 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2024-12-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142763421","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The quantum gravity seeds for laws of nature 量子引力为自然定律埋下了种子
IF 1.5 1区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-12-04 DOI: 10.1007/s13194-024-00626-0
Vincent Lam, Daniele Oriti

We discuss the challenges that the standard (Humean and non-Humean) accounts of laws face within the framework of quantum gravity where space and time may not be fundamental. This paper identifies core (meta)physical features that cut across a number of quantum gravity approaches and formalisms and that provide seeds for articulating updated conceptions that could account for QG laws not involving any spatio-temporal notions. To this aim, we will in particular highlight the constitutive roles of quantum entanglement, quantum transition amplitudes and quantum causal histories. These features also stress the fruitful overlap between quantum gravity and quantum information theory.

我们讨论了标准(休谟和非休谟)定律在量子引力框架内面临的挑战,其中空间和时间可能不是基本的。本文确定了跨越许多量子引力方法和形式化的核心(元)物理特征,并为阐明可以解释不涉及任何时空概念的量子引力定律的更新概念提供了种子。为此,我们将特别强调量子纠缠、量子跃迁振幅和量子因果史的构成作用。这些特征也强调了量子引力和量子信息论之间卓有成效的重叠。
{"title":"The quantum gravity seeds for laws of nature","authors":"Vincent Lam, Daniele Oriti","doi":"10.1007/s13194-024-00626-0","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-024-00626-0","url":null,"abstract":"<p>We discuss the challenges that the standard (Humean and non-Humean) accounts of laws face within the framework of quantum gravity where space and time may not be fundamental. This paper identifies core (meta)physical features that cut across a number of quantum gravity approaches and formalisms and that provide seeds for articulating updated conceptions that could account for QG laws not involving any spatio-temporal notions. To this aim, we will in particular highlight the constitutive roles of quantum entanglement, quantum transition amplitudes and quantum causal histories. These features also stress the fruitful overlap between quantum gravity and quantum information theory.</p>","PeriodicalId":48832,"journal":{"name":"European Journal for Philosophy of Science","volume":"87 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2024-12-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142763423","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Mapping the philosophy and neuroscience nexus through citation analysis 通过引文分析绘制哲学和神经科学的联系
IF 1.5 1区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2024-12-04 DOI: 10.1007/s13194-024-00621-5
Eugenio Petrovich, Marco Viola

We provide a quantitative analysis of the philosophy-neuroscience nexus using citation analysis. Combining bibliometric indicators of cross-field visibility with journal citation mapping techniques, we investigate four dimensions of the nexus: how the visibility of neuroscience in philosophy and of philosophy in neuroscience has changed over time, which areas of philosophy are more interested in neuroscience, which areas of neuroscience are more interested in philosophy, and how the trading zone between the two fields is configured. We also discuss two hypotheses: the supposed occurrence of a neuro-revolution in philosophy and the role of psychology as the disciplinary link between neuroscience and philosophy. Both the visibility of neuroscience in philosophy and the visibility of philosophy in neuroscience have increased significantly from 1980 to 2020, albeit the latter remains an order of magnitude lower than the former. Neuroscience is particularly visible in philosophy of mind, applied ethics, philosophy of science, but not in ‘core’ areas of analytic philosophy. Philosophy is particularly visible in cognitive and systems neuroscience and neuropsychiatry, but not in biomedical neuroscience. As for the trading zone between philosophy and neuroscience, our data show that it works differently in philosophy and in neuroscience. While some philosophy journals are active loci of bidirectional communication, neuroscience journals are divided between journals ‘importing’ philosophy in neuroscience and journals ‘exporting’ neuroscience to philosophy. Lastly, data do not support the hypothesis that a widespread neuro-revolution has transformed philosophy radically, but support the hypothesis that psychology functions as a mediating disciplinary link between philosophy and neuroscience.

我们使用引文分析对哲学与神经科学的联系进行定量分析。结合文献计量学的跨领域可见性指标和期刊引文映射技术,我们研究了这种联系的四个维度:神经科学在哲学中的可见性和哲学在神经科学中的可见性如何随着时间的推移而变化,哪些哲学领域对神经科学更感兴趣,哪些神经科学领域对哲学更感兴趣,以及这两个领域之间的贸易区是如何配置的。我们还讨论了两个假设:假设哲学中神经革命的发生以及心理学作为神经科学和哲学之间学科联系的作用。从1980年到2020年,神经科学在哲学中的可见度和哲学在神经科学中的可见度都有了显著的提高,尽管后者仍然比前者低一个数量级。神经科学在心灵哲学、应用伦理学、科学哲学中尤其明显,但在分析哲学的“核心”领域却不明显。哲学在认知神经科学和系统神经科学以及神经精神病学中尤其明显,但在生物医学神经科学中则不明显。至于哲学和神经科学之间的交易区,我们的数据显示,哲学和神经科学的运作方式不同。虽然一些哲学期刊是双向交流的活跃位点,但神经科学期刊分为两类:在神经科学领域“引进”哲学的期刊和在哲学领域“输出”神经科学的期刊。最后,数据不支持广泛的神经革命从根本上改变了哲学的假设,但支持心理学作为哲学和神经科学之间的中介学科联系的假设。
{"title":"Mapping the philosophy and neuroscience nexus through citation analysis","authors":"Eugenio Petrovich, Marco Viola","doi":"10.1007/s13194-024-00621-5","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-024-00621-5","url":null,"abstract":"<p>We provide a quantitative analysis of the philosophy-neuroscience nexus using citation analysis. Combining bibliometric indicators of cross-field visibility with journal citation mapping techniques, we investigate four dimensions of the nexus: how the visibility of neuroscience in philosophy and of philosophy in neuroscience has changed over time, which areas of philosophy are more interested in neuroscience, which areas of neuroscience are more interested in philosophy, and how the trading zone between the two fields is configured. We also discuss two hypotheses: the supposed occurrence of a neuro-revolution in philosophy and the role of psychology as the disciplinary link between neuroscience and philosophy. Both the visibility of neuroscience in philosophy and the visibility of philosophy in neuroscience have increased significantly from 1980 to 2020, albeit the latter remains an order of magnitude lower than the former. Neuroscience is particularly visible in philosophy of mind, applied ethics, philosophy of science, but not in ‘core’ areas of analytic philosophy. Philosophy is particularly visible in cognitive and systems neuroscience and neuropsychiatry, but not in biomedical neuroscience. As for the trading zone between philosophy and neuroscience, our data show that it works differently in philosophy and in neuroscience. While some philosophy journals are active loci of bidirectional communication, neuroscience journals are divided between journals ‘importing’ philosophy in neuroscience and journals ‘exporting’ neuroscience to philosophy. Lastly, data do not support the hypothesis that a widespread neuro-revolution has transformed philosophy radically, but support the hypothesis that psychology functions as a mediating disciplinary link between philosophy and neuroscience.</p>","PeriodicalId":48832,"journal":{"name":"European Journal for Philosophy of Science","volume":"34 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.5,"publicationDate":"2024-12-04","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"142763420","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
European Journal for Philosophy of Science
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1