首页 > 最新文献

Stanford Law Review最新文献

英文 中文
Genomics and toxic torts: dismantling the risk-injury divide. 基因组学和有毒侵权:消除风险-伤害鸿沟。
IF 4.9 1区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2007-04-01
Jamie A Grodsky

Emerging genetic and molecular technologies are revolutionizing our understanding of the relationship between genes and the environment. This Article develops an innovative framework for understanding the implications of the genomic revolution for the law of toxic torts. Professor Grodsky demonstrates how new technologies are poised to challenge longstanding distinctions between legally inconsequential "risk" and remediable "injury," and how the U.S. legal system will need to adapt to this emerging reality. If the law remains wedded to conventional notions of injury, it will ignore the fruits of a scientific revolution and thus may forego new remedial opportunities as yet unimagined. This is particularly significant given that twenty-first century medicine strives to "go beyond the limitations of biology" and detect, prevent, and treat disease at the molecular level. The transformative and rapidly evolving technologies of the genomic era will present herculean challenges for the legal system. But opportunities to fashion new remedies and create new efficiencies must not be overlooked in the process. Professor Grodsky recommends legal approaches to balance the goals of deterrence and legal restraint in an age of accelerating scientific change.

新兴的遗传和分子技术正在彻底改变我们对基因和环境之间关系的理解。这篇文章发展了一个创新的框架来理解基因组革命对有毒侵权法的影响。格罗兹基教授展示了新技术如何准备挑战法律上无关紧要的“风险”和可补救的“伤害”之间长期存在的区别,以及美国法律体系将如何适应这一新兴现实。如果法律仍然固守传统的伤害观念,它将忽视科学革命的成果,从而可能放弃迄今无法想象的新的补救机会。考虑到21世纪医学努力“超越生物学的限制”,在分子水平上检测、预防和治疗疾病,这一点尤为重要。基因组时代的变革性和快速发展的技术将对法律制度提出巨大的挑战。但在这一过程中,决不能忽视制定新补救措施和创造新效率的机会。格罗兹基教授建议,在一个加速科学变革的时代,采取法律手段来平衡威慑和法律约束的目标。
{"title":"Genomics and toxic torts: dismantling the risk-injury divide.","authors":"Jamie A Grodsky","doi":"","DOIUrl":"","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Emerging genetic and molecular technologies are revolutionizing our understanding of the relationship between genes and the environment. This Article develops an innovative framework for understanding the implications of the genomic revolution for the law of toxic torts. Professor Grodsky demonstrates how new technologies are poised to challenge longstanding distinctions between legally inconsequential \"risk\" and remediable \"injury,\" and how the U.S. legal system will need to adapt to this emerging reality. If the law remains wedded to conventional notions of injury, it will ignore the fruits of a scientific revolution and thus may forego new remedial opportunities as yet unimagined. This is particularly significant given that twenty-first century medicine strives to \"go beyond the limitations of biology\" and detect, prevent, and treat disease at the molecular level. The transformative and rapidly evolving technologies of the genomic era will present herculean challenges for the legal system. But opportunities to fashion new remedies and create new efficiencies must not be overlooked in the process. Professor Grodsky recommends legal approaches to balance the goals of deterrence and legal restraint in an age of accelerating scientific change.</p>","PeriodicalId":51386,"journal":{"name":"Stanford Law Review","volume":"59 6","pages":"1671-734"},"PeriodicalIF":4.9,"publicationDate":"2007-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"26798148","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Immunity for immunizations: tort liability, biodefense, and Bioshield II. 免疫免疫:侵权责任、生物防御和生物盾II。
IF 4.9 1区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2007-04-01
Lincoln Mayer
{"title":"Immunity for immunizations: tort liability, biodefense, and Bioshield II.","authors":"Lincoln Mayer","doi":"","DOIUrl":"","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":51386,"journal":{"name":"Stanford Law Review","volume":"59 6","pages":"1753-90"},"PeriodicalIF":4.9,"publicationDate":"2007-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"26798149","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Taking Compensation Private 将薪酬私有化
IF 4.9 1区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2007-02-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.806164
Abraham Bell, Gideon Parchomovsky
In light of the expansive interpretation of the public use requirement, the payment of just compensation remains the only meaningful limit on the government's eminent domain power and, correspondingly, the only safeguard of private property owners' rights against abusive takings. Yet, the current compensation regime is suboptimal. While both efficiency and fairness require paying full compensation for seizures by eminent domain, current law limits the compensation to market value. Despite the virtual consensus about the inadequacy of market compensation, courts adhere to it for a purely practical reason: there is no way to measure the true subjective value of property to its owner. Subjective value is neither observable nor verifiable to third parties and courts cannot rely upon owners' reports of the value they attach to their properties. To date, the challenge of screening truthful from exaggerated evaluation has proven insurmountable.This Article solves the undercompensation conundrum. It offers a novel self-assessment mechanism that enables the payment of full compensation at subjective value when private property is taken by eminent domain. Under the proposed mechanism, property owners would get to set the price of the property designated for condemnation. The government could then either take the property at the designated price, or abstain, leaving the property subject to two new proposed restrictions. First, for the life of the owner, the property could not be sold for less than the self-assessed price, adjusted on the basis of the local housing price index. Second, the self-assessed price - discounted to take account of the peculiarities of property tax assessments - would become the new benchmark for the owner's property tax liability. The Article shows that under most conditions, these restrictions will induce honest reporting by owners, while reducing the transaction costs created by the compensation process. The result is a dramatically more efficient law of eminent domain that is also far more respectful of private property rights.
鉴于对公共使用要求的广泛解释,支付公正补偿仍然是对政府征用权的唯一有意义的限制,相应地,也是私有财产所有者权利免受滥用征用的唯一保障。然而,目前的薪酬制度并不理想。虽然效率和公平都要求为征用土地支付全额赔偿,但现行法律将赔偿限制在市场价值上。尽管对市场补偿的不足达成了实质上的共识,但法院出于纯粹的实际原因坚持这一点:没有办法衡量财产对其所有者的真实主观价值。主观价值既不能被第三方观察到,也不能被证实,法院不能依赖业主对其财产价值的报告。迄今为止,从夸大的评价中甄别真实的评价已被证明是难以克服的挑战。本文解决了薪酬不足的难题。它提供了一种新的自我评估机制,当私有财产被征用时,可以根据主观价值支付全额补偿。在拟议的机制下,业主将有权为指定的拆迁物业设定价格。然后,政府要么以指定价格收购这些房产,要么弃权,让这些房产受到两项新提议的限制。首先,对于业主的生命,房产不得低于根据当地房价指数调整的自评价格出售。第二,考虑到物业税评估的特殊性,自行评估的价格将成为业主物业税负债的新基准。文章表明,在大多数情况下,这些限制将促使业主诚实报告,同时降低补偿过程产生的交易成本。其结果是,土地征用法的效率显著提高,对私有产权的尊重也大大提高。
{"title":"Taking Compensation Private","authors":"Abraham Bell, Gideon Parchomovsky","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.806164","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.806164","url":null,"abstract":"In light of the expansive interpretation of the \u001cpublic use\u001d requirement, the payment of \u001cjust compensation\u001d remains the only meaningful limit on the government's eminent domain power and, correspondingly, the only safeguard of private property owners' rights against abusive takings. Yet, the current compensation regime is suboptimal. While both efficiency and fairness require paying full compensation for seizures by eminent domain, current law limits the compensation to market value. Despite the virtual consensus about the inadequacy of market compensation, courts adhere to it for a purely practical reason: there is no way to measure the true subjective value of property to its owner. Subjective value is neither observable nor verifiable to third parties and courts cannot rely upon owners' reports of the value they attach to their properties. To date, the challenge of screening truthful from exaggerated evaluation has proven insurmountable.This Article solves the undercompensation conundrum. It offers a novel self-assessment mechanism that enables the payment of full compensation at subjective value when private property is taken by eminent domain. Under the proposed mechanism, property owners would get to set the price of the property designated for condemnation. The government could then either take the property at the designated price, or abstain, leaving the property subject to two new proposed restrictions. First, for the life of the owner, the property could not be sold for less than the self-assessed price, adjusted on the basis of the local housing price index. Second, the self-assessed price - discounted to take account of the peculiarities of property tax assessments - would become the new benchmark for the owner's property tax liability. The Article shows that under most conditions, these restrictions will induce honest reporting by owners, while reducing the transaction costs created by the compensation process. The result is a dramatically more efficient law of eminent domain that is also far more respectful of private property rights.","PeriodicalId":51386,"journal":{"name":"Stanford Law Review","volume":"59 1","pages":"871"},"PeriodicalIF":4.9,"publicationDate":"2007-02-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67833624","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 29
If People Would Be Outraged by Their Rulings, Should Judges Care? 如果人们对他们的裁决感到愤怒,法官应该在意吗?
IF 4.9 1区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2007-02-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.965581
C. Sunstein
At first glance, it is puzzling to suggest that courts should care whether the public would be outraged by their decisions; judicial anticipation of public outrage and its effects seems incompatible with judicial independence. Nonetheless, judges might be affected by the prospect of outrage for both consequentialist and epistemic reasons. If a judicial ruling would undermine the cause it is meant to promote or impose serious social harms, judges have reason to hesitate on consequentialist grounds. The prospect of public outrage might also suggest that the Court's ruling would be incorrect on the merits; if most people disagree with the Court's decision, perhaps the Court is wrong. Those who adopt a method on consequentialist grounds are more likely to want to consider outrage than are those who adopt an interpretive method on nonconsequentialist grounds (including some originalists). The epistemic argument for attention to outrage is greatly weakened if people suffer from a systematic bias or if the public view is a product of an informational, moral, or legal cascade. There is also a strong argument for banning consideration of the effects of public outrage on rule-consequentialist grounds. Judges might be poorly suited to make the relevant inquiries, and consideration of outrage might produce undue timidity. These points have general implications for those who favor popular constitutionalism, or judicial restraint, on democratic grounds. An understanding of the consequentialist and epistemic grounds for judicial attention to public outrage also offers lessons for the decisions of other public officials, including presidents, governors, and mayors, who might be inclined to make decisions that will produce public outrage.
乍一看,法院应该关心公众是否会被他们的决定激怒的说法令人费解;司法对公愤及其影响的预期似乎与司法独立不相容。尽管如此,出于结果主义和认识论的原因,法官可能会受到愤怒前景的影响。如果一项司法裁决会破坏其本意是促进或造成严重社会危害的原因,法官就有理由基于结果主义的理由而犹豫不决。公众愤怒的前景也可能表明,法院的裁决在案情上是不正确的;如果大多数人不同意法院的裁决,也许法院错了。那些采用结果主义方法的人比那些采用非结果主义解释方法的人(包括一些原旨主义者)更愿意考虑愤怒。如果人们遭受系统性偏见,或者公众观点是信息、道德或法律级联的产物,那么关注愤怒的认识论论点就会大大削弱。还有一个强有力的理由是,禁止基于规则后果主义的理由考虑公愤的影响。法官可能不太适合进行相关的调查,考虑到愤怒可能会产生过度的胆怯。这些观点对那些在民主基础上支持大众宪政或司法约束的人具有普遍意义。对司法关注公愤的结果主义和认识论基础的理解,也为其他政府官员的决策提供了经验教训,包括总统、州长和市长,他们可能倾向于做出会引起公愤的决定。
{"title":"If People Would Be Outraged by Their Rulings, Should Judges Care?","authors":"C. Sunstein","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.965581","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.965581","url":null,"abstract":"At first glance, it is puzzling to suggest that courts should care whether the public would be outraged by their decisions; judicial anticipation of public outrage and its effects seems incompatible with judicial independence. Nonetheless, judges might be affected by the prospect of outrage for both consequentialist and epistemic reasons. If a judicial ruling would undermine the cause it is meant to promote or impose serious social harms, judges have reason to hesitate on consequentialist grounds. The prospect of public outrage might also suggest that the Court's ruling would be incorrect on the merits; if most people disagree with the Court's decision, perhaps the Court is wrong. Those who adopt a method on consequentialist grounds are more likely to want to consider outrage than are those who adopt an interpretive method on nonconsequentialist grounds (including some originalists). The epistemic argument for attention to outrage is greatly weakened if people suffer from a systematic bias or if the public view is a product of an informational, moral, or legal cascade. There is also a strong argument for banning consideration of the effects of public outrage on rule-consequentialist grounds. Judges might be poorly suited to make the relevant inquiries, and consideration of outrage might produce undue timidity. These points have general implications for those who favor popular constitutionalism, or judicial restraint, on democratic grounds. An understanding of the consequentialist and epistemic grounds for judicial attention to public outrage also offers lessons for the decisions of other public officials, including presidents, governors, and mayors, who might be inclined to make decisions that will produce public outrage.","PeriodicalId":51386,"journal":{"name":"Stanford Law Review","volume":"60 1","pages":"155"},"PeriodicalIF":4.9,"publicationDate":"2007-02-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67913288","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 174
Should We Have Lay Justices 我们应该有外行法官吗
IF 4.9 1区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2006-11-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.943369
Adrian Vermeule
By "lay justices" I mean justices of the Supreme Court of the United States who are not accredited lawyers. Currently the number of lay justices is zero, although there is no constitutional or statutory rule that requires this. Commentators who urge that the Supreme Court should be diverse on all sorts of margins - methodological diversity, ideological diversity, and racial or ethnic or gender diversity - say little or nothing about professional diversity on the Court. I argue that the optimal number of lay justices is greater than zero. In the strong form of the argument, an historian, economist, doctor, accountant, soldier or some other nonlawyer professional should be appointed to the Court. In a weaker form of the argument, we should at least appoint dual-competent justices - lawyers who also have a degree or some other real expertise in another body of knowledge or skill.
所谓“非专业法官”,我指的是美国最高法院的法官,他们不是经过认证的律师。目前非专业法官的数量为零,尽管没有宪法或法律规定要求这样做。那些敦促最高法院在各种边缘上多样化的评论家——方法的多样性、意识形态的多样性、种族、民族或性别的多样性——很少或根本没有提到最高法院的专业多样性。我认为非专业法官的最佳数量大于零。在强有力的论证中,应该任命一名历史学家、经济学家、医生、会计、士兵或其他非律师专业人员担任最高法院法官。在较弱的论证形式中,我们至少应该任命具有双重能力的法官——在另一个知识或技能领域拥有学位或其他真正专业知识的律师。
{"title":"Should We Have Lay Justices","authors":"Adrian Vermeule","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.943369","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.943369","url":null,"abstract":"By \"lay justices\" I mean justices of the Supreme Court of the United States who are not accredited lawyers. Currently the number of lay justices is zero, although there is no constitutional or statutory rule that requires this. Commentators who urge that the Supreme Court should be diverse on all sorts of margins - methodological diversity, ideological diversity, and racial or ethnic or gender diversity - say little or nothing about professional diversity on the Court. I argue that the optimal number of lay justices is greater than zero. In the strong form of the argument, an historian, economist, doctor, accountant, soldier or some other nonlawyer professional should be appointed to the Court. In a weaker form of the argument, we should at least appoint dual-competent justices - lawyers who also have a degree or some other real expertise in another body of knowledge or skill.","PeriodicalId":51386,"journal":{"name":"Stanford Law Review","volume":"59 1","pages":"1569"},"PeriodicalIF":4.9,"publicationDate":"2006-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67901650","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 13
The case against blanket First Amendment protection of scientific research: articulating a more limited scope of protection. 反对第一修正案对科学研究的全面保护的案例:阐明一个更有限的保护范围。
IF 4.9 1区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2006-10-01
Steve Keane
{"title":"The case against blanket First Amendment protection of scientific research: articulating a more limited scope of protection.","authors":"Steve Keane","doi":"","DOIUrl":"","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":51386,"journal":{"name":"Stanford Law Review","volume":"59 2","pages":"505-50"},"PeriodicalIF":4.9,"publicationDate":"2006-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"26484920","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Less Stigma or More Financial Distress: An Empirical Analysis of the Extraordinary Increase in Bankruptcy Filings 更少的污名或更多的财务困境:破产申请异常增长的实证分析
IF 4.9 1区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2006-05-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.903355
T. Sullivan, E. Warren, J. L. Westbrook
A central concern in domestic economic policy has been the great increase in consumer bankruptcy filings since 1980. That concern was a major cause of the adoption of the 2005 amendments to the Bankruptcy Code. We analyze the data from three studies of consumer bankruptcy over twenty years to learn more about the causes of that increase. One consistent claim has been that a decline in reputational loss (stigma) has made filing for bankruptcy easier, thus explaining the rise in filings. The principal competing claim has been that increased filings arise from increased financial distress. We find that the declining-stigma hypothesis is implausible because the data show that consumer bankrupts are even more indebted now than their counterparts were in 1981 and 1991 and that there is no identifiable group of less-indebted bankrupts that were tempted into bankruptcy by reduced reputational costs. Those data and other factors support an inference that the stigma of bankruptcy may have increased over the past twenty years.
国内经济政策的一个中心问题是,自1980年以来,消费者破产申请的大幅增加。这种担忧是2005年通过《破产法》修正案的一个主要原因。我们分析了二十多年来关于消费者破产的三项研究的数据,以了解这种增长的原因。一种一致的说法是,名誉损失(污名)的减少使申请破产变得更容易,从而解释了申请破产的数量上升。主要的竞争性主张是,申请量的增加是由于财政困境的加剧。我们发现,污名下降假说是不可信的,因为数据显示,消费者破产者现在比1981年和1991年的同行负债更多,而且没有可识别的负债较少的破产者群体被降低的声誉成本所诱惑而破产。这些数据和其他因素支持一个推论,即破产的污名可能在过去二十年中有所增加。
{"title":"Less Stigma or More Financial Distress: An Empirical Analysis of the Extraordinary Increase in Bankruptcy Filings","authors":"T. Sullivan, E. Warren, J. L. Westbrook","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.903355","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.903355","url":null,"abstract":"A central concern in domestic economic policy has been the great increase in consumer bankruptcy filings since 1980. That concern was a major cause of the adoption of the 2005 amendments to the Bankruptcy Code. We analyze the data from three studies of consumer bankruptcy over twenty years to learn more about the causes of that increase. One consistent claim has been that a decline in reputational loss (stigma) has made filing for bankruptcy easier, thus explaining the rise in filings. The principal competing claim has been that increased filings arise from increased financial distress. We find that the declining-stigma hypothesis is implausible because the data show that consumer bankrupts are even more indebted now than their counterparts were in 1981 and 1991 and that there is no identifiable group of less-indebted bankrupts that were tempted into bankruptcy by reduced reputational costs. Those data and other factors support an inference that the stigma of bankruptcy may have increased over the past twenty years.","PeriodicalId":51386,"journal":{"name":"Stanford Law Review","volume":"59 1","pages":"213-256"},"PeriodicalIF":4.9,"publicationDate":"2006-05-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.903355","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67868635","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 87
Realizing two-tiered innovation policy through drug regulation. 通过药品监管实现双层创新政策。
IF 4.9 1区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2006-02-01
William E Ridgway
{"title":"Realizing two-tiered innovation policy through drug regulation.","authors":"William E Ridgway","doi":"","DOIUrl":"","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":51386,"journal":{"name":"Stanford Law Review","volume":"58 4","pages":"1221-50"},"PeriodicalIF":4.9,"publicationDate":"2006-02-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"26011327","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Defining the boundaries of "personal injury": Rainer v. Union Carbide Corp. 界定“人身伤害”的界限:Rainer诉联合碳化物公司案。
IF 4.9 1区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2006-02-01
Maya Sen
{"title":"Defining the boundaries of \"personal injury\": Rainer v. Union Carbide Corp.","authors":"Maya Sen","doi":"","DOIUrl":"","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":51386,"journal":{"name":"Stanford Law Review","volume":"58 4","pages":"1251-66"},"PeriodicalIF":4.9,"publicationDate":"2006-02-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"26011328","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
What the Right of Publicity Can Learn from Trademark Law 商标法对形象权的启示
IF 4.9 1区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2005-12-01 DOI: 10.31235/osf.io/r8pvh
Stacey L. Dogan, Mark A. Lemley
{"title":"What the Right of Publicity Can Learn from Trademark Law","authors":"Stacey L. Dogan, Mark A. Lemley","doi":"10.31235/osf.io/r8pvh","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.31235/osf.io/r8pvh","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":51386,"journal":{"name":"Stanford Law Review","volume":"58 1","pages":"1161-1220"},"PeriodicalIF":4.9,"publicationDate":"2005-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"69652914","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 23
期刊
Stanford Law Review
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1