首页 > 最新文献

Stanford Law Review最新文献

英文 中文
Historian in the Cellar 地窖里的历史学家
IF 4.9 1区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2005-11-29 DOI: 10.1017/CBO9780511921629.017
G. Fisher
In 1981 Lawrence Friedman and Robert Percival published The Roots of Justice, their study of the criminal justice system of Alameda County between 1870 and 1910. Working in the sooty port town of Oakland, they unearthed records of prisons, press, courts, and cops. Then they reconstructed the entire criminal justice system, from curbside police discipline to flashlit courtroom morality plays. In honor of the book's twenty-fifth anniversary, this essay follows a short distance in its trail. It reopens the murder trial of Hugh Cull, mentioned by Friedman and Percival in a brief footnote. Cull killed his wife in front of their seven-year-old daughter, but won acquittal when the trial judge deemed the girl incompetent to testify. The case turns out to be much more than another acquittal staked on a legal technicality. Unraveling its elaborate plot requires close attention to Lawrence Friedman's writings - not only Roots of Justice, but also his later studies of marriage and divorce in this era.
1981年,劳伦斯·弗里德曼(Lawrence Friedman)和罗伯特·珀西瓦尔(Robert Percival)出版了《正义的根源》(The Roots of Justice)一书,研究了1870年至1910年间阿拉米达县的刑事司法系统。他们在烟雾弥漫的港口城市奥克兰工作,发现了监狱、媒体、法院和警察的记录。然后他们重建了整个刑事司法系统,从路边的警察纪律到法庭上的道德剧。为了纪念这本书出版25周年,这篇文章沿着它的轨迹走了一小段路。它重新开启了对休·卡尔的谋杀审判,弗里德曼和珀西瓦尔在一个简短的脚注中提到了这一点。卡尔当着七岁女儿的面杀害了自己的妻子,但当初审法官认为女儿没有能力作证时,他获得了无罪释放。事实证明,这起案件远不止是另一起押注在法律技术细节上的无罪释放。要解开其复杂的情节,需要密切关注劳伦斯·弗里德曼的著作——不仅是《正义的根源》,还有他后来对这个时代婚姻和离婚的研究。
{"title":"Historian in the Cellar","authors":"G. Fisher","doi":"10.1017/CBO9780511921629.017","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511921629.017","url":null,"abstract":"In 1981 Lawrence Friedman and Robert Percival published The Roots of Justice, their study of the criminal justice system of Alameda County between 1870 and 1910. Working in the sooty port town of Oakland, they unearthed records of prisons, press, courts, and cops. Then they reconstructed the entire criminal justice system, from curbside police discipline to flashlit courtroom morality plays. In honor of the book's twenty-fifth anniversary, this essay follows a short distance in its trail. It reopens the murder trial of Hugh Cull, mentioned by Friedman and Percival in a brief footnote. Cull killed his wife in front of their seven-year-old daughter, but won acquittal when the trial judge deemed the girl incompetent to testify. The case turns out to be much more than another acquittal staked on a legal technicality. Unraveling its elaborate plot requires close attention to Lawrence Friedman's writings - not only Roots of Justice, but also his later studies of marriage and divorce in this era.","PeriodicalId":51386,"journal":{"name":"Stanford Law Review","volume":"59 1","pages":"1"},"PeriodicalIF":4.9,"publicationDate":"2005-11-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1017/CBO9780511921629.017","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"57099746","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Patenting nanotechnology. 纳米技术专利。
IF 4.9 1区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2005-11-01
Mark A Lemley

Universities and companies are rushing to the patent office in record numbers to patent nanotechnology inventions. This rush to the patent office is so significant that many law firms have established nanotechnology practice groups and the U.S. Patent and Trademark Office has now created a new technology class designed to track nanotechnology products. Three big differences between the emerging science of nanotechnology and other inventions make the role of patents more significant in this arena than elsewhere. First, this is almost the first new field in a century in which the basic ideas are being patented at the outset. In many of the most important fields of invention over the past century--computer hardware, software, the Internet, even biotechnology--the basic building blocks of the field were either unpatented or the patents were made available to all users by government regulation. In others, patents were delayed by interferences for so long that the industry developed free from their influence. In nanotechnology, by contrast, companies and universities alike are patenting early and often. A second factor distinguishing nanotechnology is its unique cross-industry structure. Unlike other new industries, in which the patentees are largely actual or at least potential participants in the market, a significant number of nanotechnology patentees will own rights not just in the industry in which they participate, but in other industries as well. This overlap may significantly affect their incentives to license the patents. Finally, a large number of the basic nanotechnology patents have been issued to universities, which have become far more active in patenting in the last twenty-five years. While universities have no direct incentive to restrict competition, their interests may or may not align with the optimal implementation of building-block nanotechnology inventions. The result is a nascent market in which a patent thicket is in theory a serious risk. Whether it will prove a problem in practice depends in large part on how efficient the licensing market turns out to be.

大学和公司正以创纪录的数量涌向专利局申请纳米技术发明的专利。这种涌向专利局的热潮是如此重要,以至于许多律师事务所已经建立了纳米技术实践小组,美国专利和商标局现在已经创建了一个新的技术课程,旨在跟踪纳米技术产品。新兴的纳米技术和其他发明之间的三大区别使得专利在这一领域的作用比在其他领域更为重要。首先,这几乎是一个世纪以来第一个从一开始就将基本思想申请专利的新领域。在上个世纪的许多最重要的发明领域——计算机硬件、软件、互联网,甚至生物技术——这些领域的基本组成部分要么没有获得专利,要么通过政府监管向所有用户开放专利。在另一些国家,专利由于受到干扰而拖延了很长时间,以至于该行业的发展不受这些干扰的影响。相比之下,在纳米技术领域,公司和大学都早早且频繁地申请专利。纳米技术与众不同的第二个因素是其独特的跨行业结构。在其他新兴产业中,专利权人大多是市场的实际参与者或至少是潜在的参与者,而与之不同的是,相当数量的纳米技术专利权人不仅在他们参与的产业中拥有权利,而且在其他产业中也拥有权利。这种重叠可能会显著影响他们授权专利的动机。最后,大量的基本纳米技术专利被授予了大学,在过去的25年里,大学在申请专利方面变得更加活跃。虽然大学没有限制竞争的直接动机,但它们的利益可能与纳米技术发明的最佳实现一致,也可能不一致。其结果是一个新兴市场,在这个市场中,专利丛林理论上是一个严重的风险。在实践中,这是否会成为一个问题,在很大程度上取决于许可市场的效率。
{"title":"Patenting nanotechnology.","authors":"Mark A Lemley","doi":"","DOIUrl":"","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Universities and companies are rushing to the patent office in record numbers to patent nanotechnology inventions. This rush to the patent office is so significant that many law firms have established nanotechnology practice groups and the U.S. Patent and Trademark Office has now created a new technology class designed to track nanotechnology products. Three big differences between the emerging science of nanotechnology and other inventions make the role of patents more significant in this arena than elsewhere. First, this is almost the first new field in a century in which the basic ideas are being patented at the outset. In many of the most important fields of invention over the past century--computer hardware, software, the Internet, even biotechnology--the basic building blocks of the field were either unpatented or the patents were made available to all users by government regulation. In others, patents were delayed by interferences for so long that the industry developed free from their influence. In nanotechnology, by contrast, companies and universities alike are patenting early and often. A second factor distinguishing nanotechnology is its unique cross-industry structure. Unlike other new industries, in which the patentees are largely actual or at least potential participants in the market, a significant number of nanotechnology patentees will own rights not just in the industry in which they participate, but in other industries as well. This overlap may significantly affect their incentives to license the patents. Finally, a large number of the basic nanotechnology patents have been issued to universities, which have become far more active in patenting in the last twenty-five years. While universities have no direct incentive to restrict competition, their interests may or may not align with the optimal implementation of building-block nanotechnology inventions. The result is a nascent market in which a patent thicket is in theory a serious risk. Whether it will prove a problem in practice depends in large part on how efficient the licensing market turns out to be.</p>","PeriodicalId":51386,"journal":{"name":"Stanford Law Review","volume":"58 2","pages":"601-30"},"PeriodicalIF":4.9,"publicationDate":"2005-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"25785931","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Patenting nanotechnology. 纳米技术专利。
IF 4.9 1区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2005-01-01 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.741326
Mark A. Lemley
Universities and companies are rushing to the patent office in record numbers to patent nanotechnology inventions. This rush to the patent office is so significant that many law firms have established nanotechnology practice groups and the U.S. Patent and Trademark Office has now created a new technology class designed to track nanotechnology products. Three big differences between the emerging science of nanotechnology and other inventions make the role of patents more significant in this arena than elsewhere. First, this is almost the first new field in a century in which the basic ideas are being patented at the outset. In many of the most important fields of invention over the past century--computer hardware, software, the Internet, even biotechnology--the basic building blocks of the field were either unpatented or the patents were made available to all users by government regulation. In others, patents were delayed by interferences for so long that the industry developed free from their influence. In nanotechnology, by contrast, companies and universities alike are patenting early and often. A second factor distinguishing nanotechnology is its unique cross-industry structure. Unlike other new industries, in which the patentees are largely actual or at least potential participants in the market, a significant number of nanotechnology patentees will own rights not just in the industry in which they participate, but in other industries as well. This overlap may significantly affect their incentives to license the patents. Finally, a large number of the basic nanotechnology patents have been issued to universities, which have become far more active in patenting in the last twenty-five years. While universities have no direct incentive to restrict competition, their interests may or may not align with the optimal implementation of building-block nanotechnology inventions. The result is a nascent market in which a patent thicket is in theory a serious risk. Whether it will prove a problem in practice depends in large part on how efficient the licensing market turns out to be.
大学和公司正以创纪录的数量涌向专利局申请纳米技术发明的专利。这种涌向专利局的热潮是如此重要,以至于许多律师事务所已经建立了纳米技术实践小组,美国专利和商标局现在已经创建了一个新的技术课程,旨在跟踪纳米技术产品。新兴的纳米技术和其他发明之间的三大区别使得专利在这一领域的作用比在其他领域更为重要。首先,这几乎是一个世纪以来第一个从一开始就将基本思想申请专利的新领域。在上个世纪的许多最重要的发明领域——计算机硬件、软件、互联网,甚至生物技术——这些领域的基本组成部分要么没有获得专利,要么通过政府监管向所有用户开放专利。在另一些国家,专利由于受到干扰而拖延了很长时间,以至于该行业的发展不受这些干扰的影响。相比之下,在纳米技术领域,公司和大学都早早且频繁地申请专利。纳米技术与众不同的第二个因素是其独特的跨行业结构。在其他新兴产业中,专利权人大多是市场的实际参与者或至少是潜在的参与者,而与之不同的是,相当数量的纳米技术专利权人不仅在他们参与的产业中拥有权利,而且在其他产业中也拥有权利。这种重叠可能会显著影响他们授权专利的动机。最后,大量的基本纳米技术专利被授予了大学,在过去的25年里,大学在申请专利方面变得更加活跃。虽然大学没有限制竞争的直接动机,但它们的利益可能与纳米技术发明的最佳实现一致,也可能不一致。其结果是一个新兴市场,在这个市场中,专利丛林理论上是一个严重的风险。在实践中,这是否会成为一个问题,在很大程度上取决于许可市场的效率。
{"title":"Patenting nanotechnology.","authors":"Mark A. Lemley","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.741326","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.741326","url":null,"abstract":"Universities and companies are rushing to the patent office in record numbers to patent nanotechnology inventions. This rush to the patent office is so significant that many law firms have established nanotechnology practice groups and the U.S. Patent and Trademark Office has now created a new technology class designed to track nanotechnology products. Three big differences between the emerging science of nanotechnology and other inventions make the role of patents more significant in this arena than elsewhere. First, this is almost the first new field in a century in which the basic ideas are being patented at the outset. In many of the most important fields of invention over the past century--computer hardware, software, the Internet, even biotechnology--the basic building blocks of the field were either unpatented or the patents were made available to all users by government regulation. In others, patents were delayed by interferences for so long that the industry developed free from their influence. In nanotechnology, by contrast, companies and universities alike are patenting early and often. A second factor distinguishing nanotechnology is its unique cross-industry structure. Unlike other new industries, in which the patentees are largely actual or at least potential participants in the market, a significant number of nanotechnology patentees will own rights not just in the industry in which they participate, but in other industries as well. This overlap may significantly affect their incentives to license the patents. Finally, a large number of the basic nanotechnology patents have been issued to universities, which have become far more active in patenting in the last twenty-five years. While universities have no direct incentive to restrict competition, their interests may or may not align with the optimal implementation of building-block nanotechnology inventions. The result is a nascent market in which a patent thicket is in theory a serious risk. Whether it will prove a problem in practice depends in large part on how efficient the licensing market turns out to be.","PeriodicalId":51386,"journal":{"name":"Stanford Law Review","volume":"58 2 1","pages":"601-30"},"PeriodicalIF":4.9,"publicationDate":"2005-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67816207","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 54
The Elysian Fields of the Law 法律的极乐世界
IF 4.9 1区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2004-12-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.630805
K. M. Sullivan, Pamela S. Karlan
In Democracy and Distrust and War and Responsibility, John Hart Ely advanced a participation-oriented, representation-reinforcing approach to judicial review that addressed problems of entrenchment, discrimination, and legislative delegation. This essay, which was written as the foreword to a symposium honoring Ely held at Stanford Law School in April 2004, discusses four recent Supreme Court decisions that map onto the central preoccupations in Ely's work: McConnell v. Federal Election Commission; Lawrence v. Texas; Vieth v. Jubelirer; and Hamdi v. Rumsfeld. McConnell raises important questions about how the Court ought to approach campaign finance legislation, given cross-cutting concerns with problems of entrenchment. While there are anti-entrenchment arguments on both sides of the debate over campaign finance reform, we suggest that, given the way in which Ely's anti-entrenchment theory focused on incumbent holders of government power, courts should be especially wary of restrictions that limit the speech of challengers. Lawrence offers an intriguing variation on judicial protection of discrete and insular minorities. Ely was a harsh critic of substantive due process. While the Court's opinion rests as a formal matter on substantive due process, rather than equal protection, a close reading suggests that Lawrence gives perhaps the first known Elysian reason for a substantive due process ruling: that it was necessary to invalidate a discriminatory law as if it applied to all persons in order to prevent the aftereffects of discrimination that would linger if it were not. Vieth shows how questions of political gerrymandering lie at the intersection of Ely's concerns with entrenchment and discrimination. While the Supreme Court has seen political gerrymandering as a species of discrimination, the larger problem is one of entrenchment, rather than the mistreatment of discrete and insular groups. The problem with the contemporary approach is not just that it is factually ill grounded: whatever else may be the case, it is hard to view the adherents of the two major political parties as discrete and insular minorities incapable of protecting themselves and victimized by prejudice. Rather, the problem is that the failure to recognize the issue as one of entrenchment can actually exacerbate political channel clogging and undercut effective and accountable representation. Finally, Hamdi confronts the question of how judicial review can reinforce congressional responsibility with respect to the use of military force and the protection of civil liberties given a world in which our most threatening enemies are no longer other nations. We show how War and Responsibility fleshes out one of the often-overlooked sections of Democracy and Distrust - its proposal to revive some version of the nondelegation doctrine - as a tool for ensuring accountability in decisions regarding the decision to go to war and identify echoes of Ely's theory in the three opinions in
在《民主与不信任》和《战争与责任》一书中,约翰·哈特·伊利提出了一种以参与为导向、强化代表权的司法审查方法,以解决堑壕、歧视和立法授权等问题。这篇文章是作为2004年4月在斯坦福大学法学院举行的纪念伊莱的研讨会的前言而写的,讨论了最近最高法院的四个判决,这些判决反映了伊莱工作中的核心问题:麦康奈尔诉联邦选举委员会;劳伦斯诉德克萨斯州案;维思诉朱贝利;以及哈姆迪诉拉姆斯菲尔德。麦康奈尔提出了一些重要的问题,即最高法院应该如何处理竞选财务立法,考虑到对壕沟问题的交叉关注。虽然在竞选资金改革的辩论中,双方都有反对壕沟的论点,但我们认为,鉴于伊利的反壕沟理论关注的是政府权力的现任掌权者,法院应该特别警惕限制挑战者言论的限制。劳伦斯在司法保护离散和孤立的少数群体方面提供了一个有趣的变化。伊利是实质性正当程序的严厉批评者。虽然法院的意见是关于实质性正当程序的正式问题,而不是平等保护,但仔细阅读就会发现,劳伦斯可能是已知的第一个关于实质性正当程序裁决的极乐世界理由:有必要使歧视性法律无效,就好像它适用于所有人一样,以防止歧视的后遗症,如果它不适用,就会持续存在。维思展示了政治上不公正地划分选区的问题是如何在伊利对壕沟和歧视的关注的交叉点上出现的。虽然最高法院认为政治上的不公正划分选区是一种歧视,但更大的问题是一种壕沟,而不是对离散和孤立群体的虐待。当代方法的问题不仅在于它缺乏事实依据:无论其他情况如何,都很难将两大政党的追随者视为孤立的、孤立的少数群体,他们无法保护自己,并受到偏见的伤害。相反,问题在于,未能认识到这个问题是一个堑壕问题,实际上可能加剧政治渠道堵塞,削弱有效和负责任的代表。最后,哈姆迪面对的问题是,在一个我们最具威胁的敌人不再是其他国家的世界里,司法审查如何加强国会在使用军事力量和保护公民自由方面的责任。我们展示了《战争与责任》如何充实了《民主与不信任》中经常被忽视的部分之一——它提议恢复某种版本的非授权原则——作为一种工具,以确保在决定是否参战的决策中负责任,并在哈姆迪的三个观点中发现了伊利理论的回声,这些观点反对政府对行政权力的全面主张。
{"title":"The Elysian Fields of the Law","authors":"K. M. Sullivan, Pamela S. Karlan","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.630805","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.630805","url":null,"abstract":"In Democracy and Distrust and War and Responsibility, John Hart Ely advanced a participation-oriented, representation-reinforcing approach to judicial review that addressed problems of entrenchment, discrimination, and legislative delegation. This essay, which was written as the foreword to a symposium honoring Ely held at Stanford Law School in April 2004, discusses four recent Supreme Court decisions that map onto the central preoccupations in Ely's work: McConnell v. Federal Election Commission; Lawrence v. Texas; Vieth v. Jubelirer; and Hamdi v. Rumsfeld. McConnell raises important questions about how the Court ought to approach campaign finance legislation, given cross-cutting concerns with problems of entrenchment. While there are anti-entrenchment arguments on both sides of the debate over campaign finance reform, we suggest that, given the way in which Ely's anti-entrenchment theory focused on incumbent holders of government power, courts should be especially wary of restrictions that limit the speech of challengers. Lawrence offers an intriguing variation on judicial protection of discrete and insular minorities. Ely was a harsh critic of substantive due process. While the Court's opinion rests as a formal matter on substantive due process, rather than equal protection, a close reading suggests that Lawrence gives perhaps the first known Elysian reason for a substantive due process ruling: that it was necessary to invalidate a discriminatory law as if it applied to all persons in order to prevent the aftereffects of discrimination that would linger if it were not. Vieth shows how questions of political gerrymandering lie at the intersection of Ely's concerns with entrenchment and discrimination. While the Supreme Court has seen political gerrymandering as a species of discrimination, the larger problem is one of entrenchment, rather than the mistreatment of discrete and insular groups. The problem with the contemporary approach is not just that it is factually ill grounded: whatever else may be the case, it is hard to view the adherents of the two major political parties as discrete and insular minorities incapable of protecting themselves and victimized by prejudice. Rather, the problem is that the failure to recognize the issue as one of entrenchment can actually exacerbate political channel clogging and undercut effective and accountable representation. Finally, Hamdi confronts the question of how judicial review can reinforce congressional responsibility with respect to the use of military force and the protection of civil liberties given a world in which our most threatening enemies are no longer other nations. We show how War and Responsibility fleshes out one of the often-overlooked sections of Democracy and Distrust - its proposal to revive some version of the nondelegation doctrine - as a tool for ensuring accountability in decisions regarding the decision to go to war and identify echoes of Ely's theory in the three opinions in","PeriodicalId":51386,"journal":{"name":"Stanford Law Review","volume":"57 1","pages":"695-722"},"PeriodicalIF":4.9,"publicationDate":"2004-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67780062","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Letting Billions Slip Through Your Fingers: Empirical Evidence and Legal Implications of the Failure of Financial Institutions to Participate in Securities Class Action Settlements 让数十亿美元从你的指间溜走:金融机构未能参与证券集体诉讼和解的经验证据和法律含义
IF 4.9 1区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2004-12-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.655181
James D. Cox, Randall S. Thomas
This article presents the results of an empirical investigation of the frequency with which financial institutions submit claims in settled securities class actions. We combine an empirical study of a large set of settlements with the results of a survey of institutional investors about their claims filing practices. Our sample for the first part of the analysis contains 118 settlements that were not included in our earlier study. We find that less than 30% of institutional investors with provable losses perfect their claims in these settlements. We then explore the possible explanations for this widespread failure. We suggest a wide range of potential problems from mechanical failures in the notification and recordkeeping processes to more subtle issues such as portfolio managers' beliefs that only investment activities produce significant returns for their clients. In order to determine which of these problems were the main culprits, we surveyed institutional investors about their claims filing practices, asking them who was responsible for this task, how they performed it, and what, if any, performance monitoring was done. We learned that most institutions relied on their custodian banks to file claims for them in securities fraud class action settlements, that many of these institutions did little monitoring of whether the custodian actually performed these services, and that custodians had financial disincentives to file claims on behalf of their clients. We argue that any such failures should be evaluated as potential breaches of the duty of care consistent with the monitoring obligations embraced in Delaware's Caremark decision. Applying this standard to our problem, we believe that the trustees of institutional investors must, in good faith, insure that their fund has an adequate system in place to identify and process the fund's claims. Furthermore, they should create a monitoring mechanism to insure that this system is adequate, and if they learn it is inadequate they should take measures to fix the problem. Custodians that file claims on behalf of their institutional clients should perform the various aspects of this job with due care, too, or face potential liability for negligence. We then identify several discrete problems with the claims filing system that can be addressed to help remedy the current situation. We conclude our article with two observations about the implications of our results for the goals of securities fraud litigation. Our survey results show a serious mismatch between the beneficiaries of the settlement and those that have been harmed by the securities violation that gave rise to the settlement. Simply stated, many defrauded beneficiaries are not compensated for their losses, while others are unjustly enriched. Given the enormous importance of institutional investors in the market, this mismatch raises serious doubts about whether securities fraud class actions can be justified as compensatory mechanisms. Moreov
本文提出了金融机构在解决证券集体诉讼中提交索赔的频率的实证调查结果。我们将对大量和解的实证研究与对机构投资者的索赔申请实践的调查结果结合起来。我们分析的第一部分样本包含118个定居点,这些定居点没有包括在我们早期的研究中。我们发现,只有不到30%的可证明损失的机构投资者在这些和解中完善了他们的索赔。然后,我们探讨了这种普遍失败的可能解释。我们提出了各种各样的潜在问题,从通知和记录保存过程中的机械故障,到更微妙的问题,如投资组合经理认为只有投资活动才能为客户带来可观的回报。为了确定哪些问题是主要的罪魁祸首,我们调查了机构投资者的索赔申请实践,询问他们谁负责这项任务,他们是如何执行的,如果有的话,他们做了什么绩效监控。我们了解到,大多数机构依靠其托管银行在证券欺诈集体诉讼和解中为它们提出索赔,其中许多机构几乎没有监督托管银行是否实际提供了这些服务,而且托管银行在代表客户提出索赔方面存在经济上的障碍。我们认为,任何此类失败都应被评估为潜在的违反注意义务的行为,这与特拉华州Caremark判决中所包含的监督义务相一致。将这一标准应用于我们的问题,我们认为机构投资者的受托人必须真诚地确保他们的基金有一个适当的系统来识别和处理基金的索赔。此外,他们应该建立一个监督机制,以确保这个系统是足够的,如果他们发现它是不够的,他们应该采取措施来解决问题。代表其机构客户提出索赔的托管人也应该以应有的谨慎来完成这项工作的各个方面,否则将面临潜在的疏忽责任。然后,我们确定了索赔归档系统中可以解决的几个离散问题,以帮助纠正当前的情况。最后,我们对我们的结果对证券欺诈诉讼目标的影响进行了两个观察。我们的调查结果显示,和解的受益人与那些因证券违规而受到损害的人之间存在严重的不匹配。简单地说,许多被骗的受益人没有得到赔偿,而其他人则不公正地发财。鉴于机构投资者在市场上的巨大重要性,这种不匹配引发了人们对证券欺诈集体诉讼作为补偿机制是否合理的严重质疑。此外,机构投资者糟糕的索赔备案记录加剧了这种不匹配,因为许多投资者被系统性地剥夺了从这些和解中获得的任何利益。这使人们对证券诈骗案的赔偿功能产生了更多的质疑。相反,我们认为这些案例更有说服力的理由是对欺诈的威慑。但是,为了实现这一目的,我们认为目前的进程需要进行一些改变。因此,我们建议将证券欺诈诉讼的目标锁定在个人违法者身上,只有当公司从欺诈中获益时才援引替代责任。
{"title":"Letting Billions Slip Through Your Fingers: Empirical Evidence and Legal Implications of the Failure of Financial Institutions to Participate in Securities Class Action Settlements","authors":"James D. Cox, Randall S. Thomas","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.655181","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.655181","url":null,"abstract":"This article presents the results of an empirical investigation of the frequency with which financial institutions submit claims in settled securities class actions. We combine an empirical study of a large set of settlements with the results of a survey of institutional investors about their claims filing practices. Our sample for the first part of the analysis contains 118 settlements that were not included in our earlier study. We find that less than 30% of institutional investors with provable losses perfect their claims in these settlements. We then explore the possible explanations for this widespread failure. We suggest a wide range of potential problems from mechanical failures in the notification and recordkeeping processes to more subtle issues such as portfolio managers' beliefs that only investment activities produce significant returns for their clients. In order to determine which of these problems were the main culprits, we surveyed institutional investors about their claims filing practices, asking them who was responsible for this task, how they performed it, and what, if any, performance monitoring was done. We learned that most institutions relied on their custodian banks to file claims for them in securities fraud class action settlements, that many of these institutions did little monitoring of whether the custodian actually performed these services, and that custodians had financial disincentives to file claims on behalf of their clients. We argue that any such failures should be evaluated as potential breaches of the duty of care consistent with the monitoring obligations embraced in Delaware's Caremark decision. Applying this standard to our problem, we believe that the trustees of institutional investors must, in good faith, insure that their fund has an adequate system in place to identify and process the fund's claims. Furthermore, they should create a monitoring mechanism to insure that this system is adequate, and if they learn it is inadequate they should take measures to fix the problem. Custodians that file claims on behalf of their institutional clients should perform the various aspects of this job with due care, too, or face potential liability for negligence. We then identify several discrete problems with the claims filing system that can be addressed to help remedy the current situation. We conclude our article with two observations about the implications of our results for the goals of securities fraud litigation. Our survey results show a serious mismatch between the beneficiaries of the settlement and those that have been harmed by the securities violation that gave rise to the settlement. Simply stated, many defrauded beneficiaries are not compensated for their losses, while others are unjustly enriched. Given the enormous importance of institutional investors in the market, this mismatch raises serious doubts about whether securities fraud class actions can be justified as compensatory mechanisms. Moreov","PeriodicalId":51386,"journal":{"name":"Stanford Law Review","volume":"58 1","pages":"411-454"},"PeriodicalIF":4.9,"publicationDate":"2004-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.655181","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67787572","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 29
Reform(aliz)ing Copyright 版权改革
IF 4.9 1区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2004-11-01 DOI: 10.4324/9781315092621-8
Christopher Sprigman
Reform(aliz)ing Copyright looks at the effect of the removal from the U.S. copyright laws of copyright formalities like registration, notice, and renewal. Beginning in 1976, the U.S. moved from a conditional copyright system that premised the existence and continuation of copyright on compliance with formalities, to an unconditional system, where copyright arises automatically when a work is fixed. Richard Epstein has aptly characterized these changes as copyright law . . . flipping over from a system that protected only rights that were claimed to one that vests all rights, whether claimed or not. That is a fundamental shift in any property rights regime, and one that, in the copyright context, represented a break with almost two centuries of practice.The advent of unconditional copyright has generated little comment in the academic literature - perhaps because the very term formalities signals that the former requirements were trifling, ministerial, or more bothersome than helpful. This paper argues that the disappearance of formalities was an important shift, and a harmful one. The paper recommends the re-introduction of formalities - albeit in a new form that accounts for changes in technology and complies with our international obligations under the Berne Convention, the principal international treaty governing copyright. This paper explores the important role that formalities played in our traditional copyright regime, particularly with respect to maintaining a balance between private incentives to produce creative works, and public access to those works. The paper then lays out a few possible approaches to re-introducing new-style formalities that comply with Berne.
《版权改革》着眼于美国版权法中版权手续(如注册、通知和续订)的取消所带来的影响。从1976年开始,美国从以遵守形式为前提的版权存在和延续的“有条件的版权制度”,转变为只要作品固定就自动产生版权的“无条件的版权制度”。理查德·爱泼斯坦恰当地将这些变化描述为版权法……从一个只保护被要求的权利的制度转变为一个赋予所有权利的制度,无论是否被要求。在任何产权制度中,这都是一个根本性的转变,在版权方面,这也代表着与近两个世纪以来的惯例的决破。无条件版权的出现在学术文献中几乎没有引起什么评论——也许是因为“形式”这个词本身就表明,以前的要求是琐碎的、部门式的,或者与其说有帮助,不如说更麻烦。本文认为,形式的消失是一个重要的转变,也是一个有害的转变。本文建议重新引入形式——尽管是以一种新的形式,考虑到技术的变化,并符合我们在《伯尔尼公约》(管理版权的主要国际条约)下的国际义务。本文探讨了形式在我们传统的版权制度中所起的重要作用,特别是在保持私人创作作品的动机与公众获取这些作品之间的平衡方面。然后,论文列出了几种可能的方法来重新引入符合伯尔尼的新型形式。
{"title":"Reform(aliz)ing Copyright","authors":"Christopher Sprigman","doi":"10.4324/9781315092621-8","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315092621-8","url":null,"abstract":"Reform(aliz)ing Copyright looks at the effect of the removal from the U.S. copyright laws of copyright formalities like registration, notice, and renewal. Beginning in 1976, the U.S. moved from a conditional copyright system that premised the existence and continuation of copyright on compliance with formalities, to an unconditional system, where copyright arises automatically when a work is fixed. Richard Epstein has aptly characterized these changes as copyright law . . . flipping over from a system that protected only rights that were claimed to one that vests all rights, whether claimed or not. That is a fundamental shift in any property rights regime, and one that, in the copyright context, represented a break with almost two centuries of practice.The advent of unconditional copyright has generated little comment in the academic literature - perhaps because the very term formalities signals that the former requirements were trifling, ministerial, or more bothersome than helpful. This paper argues that the disappearance of formalities was an important shift, and a harmful one. The paper recommends the re-introduction of formalities - albeit in a new form that accounts for changes in technology and complies with our international obligations under the Berne Convention, the principal international treaty governing copyright. This paper explores the important role that formalities played in our traditional copyright regime, particularly with respect to maintaining a balance between private incentives to produce creative works, and public access to those works. The paper then lays out a few possible approaches to re-introducing new-style formalities that comply with Berne.","PeriodicalId":51386,"journal":{"name":"Stanford Law Review","volume":"57 1","pages":"485-568"},"PeriodicalIF":4.9,"publicationDate":"2004-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"70629207","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 35
Evidence, Procedure, and the Upside of Cognitive Error 证据、程序与认知错误的好处
IF 4.9 1区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2004-06-22 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.497882
C. Sanchirico
Humans are imperfect information processors, a fact almost universally bemoaned in legal scholarship. But when it comes to how the legal system itself processes information, cognitive limitations are largely good news. Evidentiary procedure - inclusive of trial, discovery, and investigation - relies heavily on the fact that human mental capacity is limited. Such limits are crucial to separating sincere from insincere testimony. Moreover, notes and other cognitive artifacts that individuals make to compensate for their limited cognitive ability are an important source of evidence. This article's primary objective is to elucidate the extent to which cognitive imperfection is beneficial rather than detrimental to evidentiary process and thus to law as a whole. Secondarily, the article discusses how the law of evidentiary process tilts the playing field of litigation in a manner that exacerbates the cognitive limitations of the potentially insincere and offsets the limitations of competing participants.
人类是不完美的信息处理者,这是法律学界普遍哀叹的事实。但当涉及到法律系统本身如何处理信息时,认知限制在很大程度上是好消息。证据程序——包括审判、发现和调查——在很大程度上依赖于人类心智能力有限这一事实。这些限制对于区分真诚的证词和不真诚的证词至关重要。此外,个人为弥补其有限的认知能力而做的笔记和其他认知人工制品是重要的证据来源。本文的主要目的是阐明认知缺陷在多大程度上对证据程序有利而不是有害,从而对整个法律有利。其次,本文讨论了证据程序法如何使诉讼的竞争环境倾斜,从而加剧了潜在不真诚者的认知限制,并抵消了竞争参与者的限制。
{"title":"Evidence, Procedure, and the Upside of Cognitive Error","authors":"C. Sanchirico","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.497882","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.497882","url":null,"abstract":"Humans are imperfect information processors, a fact almost universally bemoaned in legal scholarship. But when it comes to how the legal system itself processes information, cognitive limitations are largely good news. Evidentiary procedure - inclusive of trial, discovery, and investigation - relies heavily on the fact that human mental capacity is limited. Such limits are crucial to separating sincere from insincere testimony. Moreover, notes and other cognitive artifacts that individuals make to compensate for their limited cognitive ability are an important source of evidence. This article's primary objective is to elucidate the extent to which cognitive imperfection is beneficial rather than detrimental to evidentiary process and thus to law as a whole. Secondarily, the article discusses how the law of evidentiary process tilts the playing field of litigation in a manner that exacerbates the cognitive limitations of the potentially insincere and offsets the limitations of competing participants.","PeriodicalId":51386,"journal":{"name":"Stanford Law Review","volume":"57 1","pages":"291-365"},"PeriodicalIF":4.9,"publicationDate":"2004-06-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67751571","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 10
Reducing Digital Copyright Infringement Without Restricting Innovation 在不限制创新的前提下减少数字版权侵权
IF 4.9 1区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2004-04-08 DOI: 10.31235/osf.io/n4863
Mark A. Lemley, R. A. Reese
Suing actual infringers is passe in copyright law. In the digital environment, the real stakes lie in suing those who facilitate infringement by others. There is of course a good reason copyright owners are filing such suits. They see themselves as under threat from a flood of cheap, easy copies and a dramatic increase in the number of people who can make those copies. The high volume of illegal uses, and the low return to suing any individual, make it more cost-effective to aim as far up the chain as possible. From the perspective of the movie industry, it's easier and more effective to shut down Napster than to sue the millions of people who traded files illegally on Napster. So far, the courts have been willing to go along, shutting down a number of innovative services in the digital music realm.In this article, we argue that unrestricted liability for anyone who is in any way involved with copyright infringement is a bad idea. Indirect liability is a continuum, in which acts most closely related to infringement and with the fewest affirmative benefits are the easiest to condemn. Going after makers of technology for the uses to which their technologies may be put threatens to stifle innovation. The fundamental difficulty is that while courts can make decisions about direct infringement on a case-by-case basis, lawsuits based on indirect liability necessarily sweep together both socially beneficial and socially harmful uses of a program or service, either permitting both uses or condemning both. Optimal digital copyright policy would do two things: stop deterring innovators, and permit cost-effective enforcement of copyright in the digital environment. In this paper, we suggest at least two possible alternatives that might provide ways out of the digital copyright morass. Both alternatives stem from the basic economics of copyright enforcement. It is not currently cost-effective for copyright owners to sue individual infringers, because there are tens of millions of them, because lawsuits are expensive, and because each infringer would be liable only for minimal damages. They are happy to sue facilitators instead, because there are fewer of them and both damages and the benefits of injunctive relief are substantial. Copyright owners have no incentive to permit optimal innovation by facilitators, because they do not benefit from that innovation except indirectly. Individual infringers in turn have no incentive to change their behavior or to subscribe to fee-based services, because they suffer none of the costs of infringement. One solution is to change the incentives of individuals. Because individual users of peer-to-peer (p2p) networks know that it is extremely unlikely they will be sued, economic theory suggests that the only way to effectively deter infringement is to increase the effective sanction substantially for those who are caught. Were the government to begin criminally prosecuting selected users of peer-to-peer services - or were th
起诉实际侵权人在版权法中是过时的。在数字环境中,真正的利害关系在于起诉那些为他人侵权提供便利的人。当然,版权所有者提起此类诉讼是有充分理由的。他们认为自己正面临着大量廉价、容易复制的产品以及能够复制这些产品的人数急剧增加的威胁。大量的非法使用,以及起诉任何个人的低回报,使得尽可能瞄准链条的上游更划算。从电影行业的角度来看,关闭Napster比起诉在Napster上非法交易文件的数百万人更容易、更有效。到目前为止,法院一直愿意配合,关闭了数字音乐领域的一些创新服务。在这篇文章中,我们认为任何人以任何方式参与版权侵权的无限制责任都是一个坏主意。间接责任是一个连续体,其中与侵权最密切相关且肯定利益最少的行为最容易受到谴责。因为技术的用途而追逐技术制造者,可能会扼杀创新。最根本的困难在于,虽然法院可以在个案基础上对直接侵权作出裁决,但基于间接责任的诉讼必然会将项目或服务对社会有益和有害的用途综合起来,要么允许两种用途,要么谴责两种用途。最优的数字版权政策将做两件事:停止阻止创新者,并允许在数字环境中具有成本效益的版权执行。在本文中,我们提出了至少两种可能的替代方案,它们可能提供摆脱数字版权困境的方法。这两种选择都源于版权执法的基本经济学。目前,版权所有者起诉侵权者个人并不符合成本效益,因为侵权者有数千万人,因为诉讼费用昂贵,而且每个侵权者只需承担最低限度的损害赔偿。他们很乐意起诉调解人,因为调解人的数量较少,而且损害赔偿和禁令救济的好处都是可观的。版权所有者没有动力允许促进者进行最优创新,因为他们只能间接地从创新中获益。反过来,个人侵权者也没有动力改变自己的行为或订阅收费服务,因为他们不承担侵权的成本。解决办法之一是改变个人的激励机制。因为点对点(p2p)网络的个人用户知道他们被起诉的可能性极低,经济学理论认为,有效阻止侵权的唯一方法是大幅增加对那些被抓到的人的有效制裁。如果政府开始对特定的点对点服务用户提起刑事诉讼,或者美国唱片工业协会认真起诉终端用户,这将对许多非法用户产生实质性的威慑作用。选择性起诉还有其他好处——政府可以针对p2p网站上相对较少的非法文件的主要提供者,而这些用户恰恰是最不可能参与合理使用的用户。虽然特定的起诉不会完全阻止非法文件交易,但版权所有者从未能够阻止所有盗版行为。他们所需要做的就是减少盗版,这样他们的投资就能得到回报。另一个解决方案是通过降低诉讼成本来改变版权所有者起诉个人侵权者的动机。其中一种方法就是征税制度。对设备或服务征税的优点是允许自动收取特许权使用费,大大降低了执行成本,但代价是对合法和非法使用征税。征税解决了前端的执法问题,但它在许多方面与目前起诉调解人的方法相似。两者的主要区别在于,在征税制度下,版权所有者受到强制许可而不是财产规则的保护。降低执行成本的另一种建议是建立某种快速、廉价的仲裁系统,使版权所有者能够从p2p系统的滥用者那里得到有限的救济。现有的域名商标仲裁制度在某些方面(速度快、成本低)是一个典范,但在其他方面(缺乏程序保护)则是一个警示。这样一个系统将允许对直接侵权者进行低成本的版权侵权执法,减少内容所有者起诉协助者的需要。相对于征税而言,仲裁制度将在一定程度上牺牲成本,以提高准确性,只针对那些非法使用电脑的人,而不是针对所有电脑或p2p网络的用户。 这将比选择性刑事起诉更公平,因为负担将更平均地落在每个违法者身上,而不是为了服务于社会利益而对少数人施加严厉的惩罚,以威慑其他人。相对于目前法院在间接侵权案件中面临的二元选择,该系统也可以被设计成提高准确性。我们可以设计这个系统,使其仅限于明确的情况。我们也可以为有争议的合理使用建立一个辩护,这样一个用户可以证明他们是他们已经拥有的空间移动cd就有了辩护。
{"title":"Reducing Digital Copyright Infringement Without Restricting Innovation","authors":"Mark A. Lemley, R. A. Reese","doi":"10.31235/osf.io/n4863","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.31235/osf.io/n4863","url":null,"abstract":"Suing actual infringers is passe in copyright law. In the digital environment, the real stakes lie in suing those who facilitate infringement by others. There is of course a good reason copyright owners are filing such suits. They see themselves as under threat from a flood of cheap, easy copies and a dramatic increase in the number of people who can make those copies. The high volume of illegal uses, and the low return to suing any individual, make it more cost-effective to aim as far up the chain as possible. From the perspective of the movie industry, it's easier and more effective to shut down Napster than to sue the millions of people who traded files illegally on Napster. So far, the courts have been willing to go along, shutting down a number of innovative services in the digital music realm.In this article, we argue that unrestricted liability for anyone who is in any way involved with copyright infringement is a bad idea. Indirect liability is a continuum, in which acts most closely related to infringement and with the fewest affirmative benefits are the easiest to condemn. Going after makers of technology for the uses to which their technologies may be put threatens to stifle innovation. The fundamental difficulty is that while courts can make decisions about direct infringement on a case-by-case basis, lawsuits based on indirect liability necessarily sweep together both socially beneficial and socially harmful uses of a program or service, either permitting both uses or condemning both. Optimal digital copyright policy would do two things: stop deterring innovators, and permit cost-effective enforcement of copyright in the digital environment. In this paper, we suggest at least two possible alternatives that might provide ways out of the digital copyright morass. Both alternatives stem from the basic economics of copyright enforcement. It is not currently cost-effective for copyright owners to sue individual infringers, because there are tens of millions of them, because lawsuits are expensive, and because each infringer would be liable only for minimal damages. They are happy to sue facilitators instead, because there are fewer of them and both damages and the benefits of injunctive relief are substantial. Copyright owners have no incentive to permit optimal innovation by facilitators, because they do not benefit from that innovation except indirectly. Individual infringers in turn have no incentive to change their behavior or to subscribe to fee-based services, because they suffer none of the costs of infringement. One solution is to change the incentives of individuals. Because individual users of peer-to-peer (p2p) networks know that it is extremely unlikely they will be sued, economic theory suggests that the only way to effectively deter infringement is to increase the effective sanction substantially for those who are caught. Were the government to begin criminally prosecuting selected users of peer-to-peer services - or were th","PeriodicalId":51386,"journal":{"name":"Stanford Law Review","volume":"56 1","pages":"1345"},"PeriodicalIF":4.9,"publicationDate":"2004-04-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"69652550","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 102
Convictions and Doubts: Retribution, Representation, and the Debate Over Felon Disenfranchisement 定罪与怀疑:惩罚、代表和重罪犯剥夺公民权的辩论
IF 4.9 1区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2004-01-08 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.484543
Pamela S. Karlan
The tenor of the debate over felon disenfranchisement has taken a remarkable turn. After a generation of essentially unsuccessful litigation, two federal courts of appeals have recently reinstated challenges to such laws. A number of states have recently made it easier for ex-offenders to regain their voting rights. Recent public opinion surveys find overwhelming support for restoring the franchise to offenders who have otherwise completed their sentences. On the international front, the supreme courts of Canada and South Africa issued decisions requiring their governments to permit even incarcerated citizens to vote. This essay discusses some of the causes and consequences for the way in which we now approach the question of criminal disenfranchisement. Parts I and II suggest that the terms of the contemporary debate reflect an underlying change both in how we conceive the right to vote and in how we understand the fundamental nature of criminal disenfranchisement. Once voting is understood as a fundamental right, rather than as a state-created privilege, the essentially punitive nature of criminal disenfranchisement statutes becomes undeniable. And once the right to vote is cast in group terms, rather than in purely individual ones, criminal disenfranchisement statutes are seen not only to deny the vote to particular individuals but also to dilute the voting strength of identifiable communities and to affect election outcomes and legislative policy choices. The 2000 presidential election and the popular and scholarly discussion that followed the debacle in Florida powerfully demonstrated the outcome-determinative effects of criminal disenfranchisement laws even as the 2000 census drove home other representational consequences of the mass incarceration that triggers much of the disenfranchisement. Felon disenfranchisement cases offer an attractive vehicle for courts concerned with the staggering burdens the war on drugs and significantly disparate incarceration rates have imposed on the minority community. The legitimacy of criminal punishment depends on the legitimacy of the process that produces and enforces the criminal law. The legitimacy of that process in turn depends on the ability of citizens to participate equally in choosing the officials who enact and administer criminal punishment. Lifetime disenfranchisement of ex-offenders short circuits this process in a pernicious and self-reinforcing way. Part III suggests that if we conclude that criminal disenfranchisement statutes are essentially punitive, rather than regulatory - as I think we must - this opens an additional legal avenue for attacking such laws beyond the equal protection- and Voting Rights Act-based challenges that courts are now entertaining. Blanket disenfranchisement statutes also raise serious questions under the Eighth Amendment, given the Supreme Court's recent decisions in Atkins v. Virginia and Ewing v. California.
关于剥夺重罪犯公民权的辩论的基调发生了显著的转变。在经历了一代基本上不成功的诉讼之后,两个联邦上诉法院最近恢复了对此类法律的挑战。最近,许多州都简化了刑满释放者重获投票权的程序。最近的民意调查显示,绝大多数人支持恢复已服完刑期的罪犯的选举权。在国际方面,加拿大和南非的最高法院发布了判决,要求他们的政府甚至允许被监禁的公民投票。本文讨论了我们现在处理刑事剥夺公民权问题的方式的一些原因和后果。第一部分和第二部分表明,当代辩论的术语反映了我们如何理解选举权和我们如何理解刑事剥夺公民权的基本性质的根本变化。一旦投票被理解为一项基本权利,而不是国家创造的特权,刑事剥夺选举权法规本质上的惩罚性就变得不可否认了。一旦投票权以群体而非纯粹以个人的名义行使,刑事剥夺公民权法规就会被视为不仅剥夺了特定个人的投票权,而且会稀释可识别社区的投票力量,并影响选举结果和立法政策选择。2000年的总统选举以及佛罗里达惨败之后的大众和学术讨论有力地证明了刑事剥夺公民权法对结果的决定性影响,尽管2000年的人口普查让人们明白了大规模监禁的其他代表性后果,这些后果引发了大部分的剥夺公民权。重罪犯被剥夺公民权的案件为法院提供了一个有吸引力的工具,法院关注的是毒品战争和明显不同的监禁率给少数族裔社区带来的惊人负担。刑罚的正当性取决于刑法产生和执行过程的正当性。这一过程的合法性反过来取决于公民平等参与选择制定和执行刑事处罚的官员的能力。终身剥夺前罪犯的公民权,以一种有害且自我强化的方式阻碍了这一过程。第三部分表明,如果我们得出结论,刑事剥夺公民权的法规本质上是惩罚性的,而不是监管性的——我认为我们必须这样做——这就为攻击这些法律开辟了一个额外的法律途径,超出了平等保护的范围——以及法院现在正在考虑的基于《选举权法案》的挑战。鉴于最高法院最近对阿特金斯诉弗吉尼亚案和尤因诉加利福尼亚案的判决,全面剥夺公民权的法规也引发了第八修正案下的严重问题。
{"title":"Convictions and Doubts: Retribution, Representation, and the Debate Over Felon Disenfranchisement","authors":"Pamela S. Karlan","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.484543","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.484543","url":null,"abstract":"The tenor of the debate over felon disenfranchisement has taken a remarkable turn. After a generation of essentially unsuccessful litigation, two federal courts of appeals have recently reinstated challenges to such laws. A number of states have recently made it easier for ex-offenders to regain their voting rights. Recent public opinion surveys find overwhelming support for restoring the franchise to offenders who have otherwise completed their sentences. On the international front, the supreme courts of Canada and South Africa issued decisions requiring their governments to permit even incarcerated citizens to vote. This essay discusses some of the causes and consequences for the way in which we now approach the question of criminal disenfranchisement. Parts I and II suggest that the terms of the contemporary debate reflect an underlying change both in how we conceive the right to vote and in how we understand the fundamental nature of criminal disenfranchisement. Once voting is understood as a fundamental right, rather than as a state-created privilege, the essentially punitive nature of criminal disenfranchisement statutes becomes undeniable. And once the right to vote is cast in group terms, rather than in purely individual ones, criminal disenfranchisement statutes are seen not only to deny the vote to particular individuals but also to dilute the voting strength of identifiable communities and to affect election outcomes and legislative policy choices. The 2000 presidential election and the popular and scholarly discussion that followed the debacle in Florida powerfully demonstrated the outcome-determinative effects of criminal disenfranchisement laws even as the 2000 census drove home other representational consequences of the mass incarceration that triggers much of the disenfranchisement. Felon disenfranchisement cases offer an attractive vehicle for courts concerned with the staggering burdens the war on drugs and significantly disparate incarceration rates have imposed on the minority community. The legitimacy of criminal punishment depends on the legitimacy of the process that produces and enforces the criminal law. The legitimacy of that process in turn depends on the ability of citizens to participate equally in choosing the officials who enact and administer criminal punishment. Lifetime disenfranchisement of ex-offenders short circuits this process in a pernicious and self-reinforcing way. Part III suggests that if we conclude that criminal disenfranchisement statutes are essentially punitive, rather than regulatory - as I think we must - this opens an additional legal avenue for attacking such laws beyond the equal protection- and Voting Rights Act-based challenges that courts are now entertaining. Blanket disenfranchisement statutes also raise serious questions under the Eighth Amendment, given the Supreme Court's recent decisions in Atkins v. Virginia and Ewing v. California.","PeriodicalId":51386,"journal":{"name":"Stanford Law Review","volume":"56 1","pages":"1147-1170"},"PeriodicalIF":4.9,"publicationDate":"2004-01-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67748115","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 40
Punishing Hatred and Prejudice 惩罚仇恨和偏见
IF 4.9 1区 社会学 Q1 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2003-11-25 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.472761
Heidi M. Hurd, M. Moore
This article undertakes a detailed examination of the justifications advanced for the national and international rush to enact and apply hate and bias crime legislation as an answer to the tragically brutal expressions of racial animosity, bigotry, homophobia, and misogyny that continue to remind the Western World of its inability to protect its citizens from those who do not share its egalitarian ideals. In undertaking this project, we seek to synthesize and critically evaluate over a decade's worth of scholarship on the wisdom of the enhanced penalties imposed by hate and bias crime legislation. We further seek to demonstrate that this literature, to date, has sadly failed to provide both an adequate moral justification and an acceptable doctrinal framework for this politically popular form of state action. The article is divided into four parts, corresponding to the four principal rationales for hate/bias crime legislation that have advanced over the past decade or more. Part I considers the "wrongdoing thesis" - the claim that the harms perpetrated by offenders who are motivated by group-hatred or prejudice represent wrongs more serious than those perpetrated by defendants who commit the same offenses with different motivations. We work through an extensive catalogue of harms that are commonly claimed to be uniquely associated with hate- and bias-motivated crimes: elevated physical and psychic injuries to principal victims; wide-spread fear within the principal victim's community; a diminished faith in the legal system and an associated instability within the larger social order; vigilante acts of retaliation by victims and their communities; the publication by such criminal acts of harmful messages corruptive of the moral order; and the associated, but independent harm of the state being complicit whenever it fails to express in law the moral outrage that such "statements" properly incite. As we demonstrate, even if social science ultimately vindicates the empirical claims made by those who propound the various wrongdoing theses, there are conceptual and moral problems that prevent these arguments from justifying the blanket sentence enhancements imposed by existing hate and bias crime legislation. Part II takes up different versions of what we call the "expressivist thesis" - the thesis that the disrespect for communities expressed by acts of group-hatred and prejudice properly invite denunciation by the state in the form of elevated criminal penalties. As we argue, either the expressivist thesis is redundant with the wrongdoing thesis, and so invites the problems articulated in Part I; or it depends upon a free-standing expressivist theory of punishment, and is, for that reason, unsustainable. Part III considers what we call the "culpability thesis" - the thesis that hate and prejudice constitute uniquely culpable mental states that justify penalties more severe than are meted out for other forms of viciousness. We demonstrate in this Part
这篇文章详细分析了国家和国际上急于制定和实施仇恨和偏见犯罪立法的理由,作为对种族仇恨、偏执、同性恋恐惧症和厌女症的悲剧性野蛮表达的回应,这些继续提醒西方世界,它无力保护其公民免受那些不分享其平等主义理想的人的伤害。在开展这个项目时,我们试图综合和批判性地评估十多年来关于仇恨和偏见犯罪立法所施加的加强惩罚的智慧的学术价值。我们进一步试图证明,可悲的是,迄今为止,这些文献未能为这种政治上流行的国家行动形式提供充分的道德理由和可接受的理论框架。文章分为四个部分,对应于过去十年或更长时间里进步的仇恨/偏见犯罪立法的四个主要理由。第一部分考虑了“不法行为理论”——声称由群体仇恨或偏见驱动的罪犯所造成的伤害比那些出于不同动机犯下同样罪行的被告所犯的罪行更严重。我们研究了一份广泛的伤害目录,这些伤害通常被认为与仇恨和偏见动机的犯罪有独特的联系:对主要受害者的身体和精神伤害加重;主要受害者社区内普遍存在恐惧;对法律体系的信心减弱,以及与之相关的更大社会秩序的不稳定;受害者及其社区的自卫报复行为;通过此类犯罪行为发布有害信息,败坏道德秩序;每当政府未能在法律上表达这种“言论”所适当煽动的道德愤怒时,相关的、但独立的损害就会成为同谋。正如我们所证明的那样,即使社会科学最终证明了那些提出各种不法行为论点的人所提出的经验主张是正确的,也存在一些概念和道德问题,使这些论点无法证明现有的仇恨和偏见犯罪立法所施加的全面判刑是合理的。第二部分讨论了我们所说的“表现主义论点”的不同版本——这个论点认为,通过群体仇恨和偏见的行为来表达对社区的不尊重,适当地招致国家以加重刑事处罚的形式的谴责。正如我们所论证的,要么表现主义的论点与错误的论点是多余的,因此引发了第一部分所阐述的问题;或者它依赖于一种独立的表现主义惩罚理论,因此,它是不可持续的。第三部分考虑了我们所说的“罪责论”——这个理论认为,仇恨和偏见构成了独特的罪责心理状态,因此比其他形式的邪恶更严厉的惩罚是合理的。在这一部分中,我们证明,如果仇恨和偏见被解释为罪责标准,那么仇恨/偏见犯罪是一种新的理论发明,它更适合以政治完美主义为理由的基于性格的刑法理论,而不是与经典政治自由主义更和谐的基于行为的理论。最后,第四部分讨论了“平等命题”——该命题认为,加强对仇恨/偏见犯罪的惩罚适当地发挥作用,以实现我们社会中犯罪风险的更平等的分配,因为它们阻止了已经承受了不成比例的社会暴力的公民群体(进一步)受害。正如我们所证明的,这一主张的每一种意义都使其在概念上不连贯或在道德上站不住脚,因此,它不能作为我们在第一、二、三部分中研究的仇恨/偏见犯罪立法理论的有希望的替代方案。
{"title":"Punishing Hatred and Prejudice","authors":"Heidi M. Hurd, M. Moore","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.472761","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.472761","url":null,"abstract":"This article undertakes a detailed examination of the justifications advanced for the national and international rush to enact and apply hate and bias crime legislation as an answer to the tragically brutal expressions of racial animosity, bigotry, homophobia, and misogyny that continue to remind the Western World of its inability to protect its citizens from those who do not share its egalitarian ideals. In undertaking this project, we seek to synthesize and critically evaluate over a decade's worth of scholarship on the wisdom of the enhanced penalties imposed by hate and bias crime legislation. We further seek to demonstrate that this literature, to date, has sadly failed to provide both an adequate moral justification and an acceptable doctrinal framework for this politically popular form of state action. The article is divided into four parts, corresponding to the four principal rationales for hate/bias crime legislation that have advanced over the past decade or more. Part I considers the \"wrongdoing thesis\" - the claim that the harms perpetrated by offenders who are motivated by group-hatred or prejudice represent wrongs more serious than those perpetrated by defendants who commit the same offenses with different motivations. We work through an extensive catalogue of harms that are commonly claimed to be uniquely associated with hate- and bias-motivated crimes: elevated physical and psychic injuries to principal victims; wide-spread fear within the principal victim's community; a diminished faith in the legal system and an associated instability within the larger social order; vigilante acts of retaliation by victims and their communities; the publication by such criminal acts of harmful messages corruptive of the moral order; and the associated, but independent harm of the state being complicit whenever it fails to express in law the moral outrage that such \"statements\" properly incite. As we demonstrate, even if social science ultimately vindicates the empirical claims made by those who propound the various wrongdoing theses, there are conceptual and moral problems that prevent these arguments from justifying the blanket sentence enhancements imposed by existing hate and bias crime legislation. Part II takes up different versions of what we call the \"expressivist thesis\" - the thesis that the disrespect for communities expressed by acts of group-hatred and prejudice properly invite denunciation by the state in the form of elevated criminal penalties. As we argue, either the expressivist thesis is redundant with the wrongdoing thesis, and so invites the problems articulated in Part I; or it depends upon a free-standing expressivist theory of punishment, and is, for that reason, unsustainable. Part III considers what we call the \"culpability thesis\" - the thesis that hate and prejudice constitute uniquely culpable mental states that justify penalties more severe than are meted out for other forms of viciousness. We demonstrate in this Part","PeriodicalId":51386,"journal":{"name":"Stanford Law Review","volume":"56 1","pages":"1081-1146"},"PeriodicalIF":4.9,"publicationDate":"2003-11-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67743997","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 35
期刊
Stanford Law Review
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1