首页 > 最新文献

Columbia Law Review最新文献

英文 中文
Watchdog or Demagogue? The Media in the Chinese Legal System 看门狗还是煽动者?中国法制中的媒体
IF 2.9 2区 社会学 Pub Date : 2005-01-01 DOI: 10.7916/D8J67GK4
B. Liebman
Over the past decade, the Chinese media have emerged as among the most influential actors in the Chinese legal system. As media commercialization and increased editorial discretion have combined with growing attention to social and legal problems, the media have gained incentives to expand their traditional mouthpiece roles in new directions. As a result, the media have emerged as one of the most effective and important avenues of citizen redress. Their role in the legal system, however, has also brought them increasingly into conflict with China’s courts. This Article examines the implications of the media’s roles in the Chinese legal system for China’s legal development. It shows how media commercialization has resulted in incentives for the media to expand the scope of
在过去的十年里,中国媒体已经成为中国法律体系中最具影响力的角色之一。随着媒体商业化和编辑裁量权的增加,加上对社会和法律问题的日益关注,媒体获得了在新的方向上扩大其传统喉舌角色的动力。因此,传播媒介已成为公民申诉的最有效和最重要的途径之一。然而,它们在法律体系中的角色也使它们与中国法院的冲突日益加剧。本文探讨了媒体在中国法律体系中的角色对中国法律发展的影响。它展示了媒体商业化如何导致媒体扩大范围的动机
{"title":"Watchdog or Demagogue? The Media in the Chinese Legal System","authors":"B. Liebman","doi":"10.7916/D8J67GK4","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.7916/D8J67GK4","url":null,"abstract":"Over the past decade, the Chinese media have emerged as among the most influential actors in the Chinese legal system. As media commercialization and increased editorial discretion have combined with growing attention to social and legal problems, the media have gained incentives to expand their traditional mouthpiece roles in new directions. As a result, the media have emerged as one of the most effective and important avenues of citizen redress. Their role in the legal system, however, has also brought them increasingly into conflict with China’s courts. This Article examines the implications of the media’s roles in the Chinese legal system for China’s legal development. It shows how media commercialization has resulted in incentives for the media to expand the scope of","PeriodicalId":51408,"journal":{"name":"Columbia Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.9,"publicationDate":"2005-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71366649","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 146
Rethinking Article I, Section 1: From Nondelegation to Exclusive Delegation 重新思考第一条第一节:从非授权到独家授权
IF 2.9 2区 社会学 Pub Date : 2004-12-01 DOI: 10.2307/4099357
T. Merrill
{"title":"Rethinking Article I, Section 1: From Nondelegation to Exclusive Delegation","authors":"T. Merrill","doi":"10.2307/4099357","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2307/4099357","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":51408,"journal":{"name":"Columbia Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.9,"publicationDate":"2004-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2307/4099357","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68755657","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 29
THE SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES AS QUASI-INTERNATIONAL TRIBUNAL: RECLAIMING THE COURT'S ORIGINAL AND EXCLUSIVE JURISDICTION OVER TREATY-BASED SUITS BY FOREIGN STATES AGAINST STATES 作为准国际法庭的美国最高法院:恢复法院对外国针对其他国家的基于条约的诉讼的原始和专属管辖权
IF 2.9 2区 社会学 Pub Date : 2004-11-01 DOI: 10.2307/4099335
Thomas H. Lee
In this Article, Professor Lee argues that the Constitution vests in the Supreme Court original and exclusive jurisdiction over suits brought by foreign states against States alleging violations of treaties of the United States. The basis for nonimmunity is a peacekeeping theory of ratification consent: Just as, by ratifying the Constitution, the States agreed to suits by other States and the national sovereign to ensure domestic peace, they agreed to suits by foreign states in the supreme national tribunal for the sake of international peace. The Founders of the new Republic viewed state breach of the 1783 Treaty of Peace as the leading potential cause for a shooting or trade war. The Article’s thesis is supported by the text of Article III as amended by the Eleventh Amendment and by evidence of original intent, including the inaugural implementation of the Original Jurisdiction Clause by the Judiciary Act of 1789. Nor is it inconsistent with the principle of sovereign dignity for the semisovereign States to be sued by fully sovereign foreign states in the Supreme Court. Justices of the Court throughout the nineteenth and the first quarter of the twentieth centuries acknowledged this aspect of the Court’s original jurisdiction, but awareness was lost by the time of the 1934 decision in Principality of Monaco v. Mississippi when the Republic had become a world power. Reclaiming the Court’s lost jurisdiction today requires a narrowing of that decision, but makes sense given the resurgence of American federalism and the pace of globalization.
在这一条款中,李教授主张,宪法赋予最高法院对外国指控违反美国条约的国家提起的诉讼的原始和专属管辖权。不豁免的基础是批准同意的维持和平理论:正如各国通过批准《宪法》同意其他国家和国家主权为确保国内和平而提起诉讼一样,它们也同意外国为了国际和平向国家最高法庭提起诉讼。新共和国的创始人认为国家违反1783年的和平条约是引发枪击或贸易战的主要潜在原因。本条款的论点得到经第十一修正案修正的第三条文本和原意证据的支持,包括1789年《司法法案》对“原始管辖权条款”的首次实施。由完全主权的外国在最高法院起诉半主权国家也不违反主权尊严原则。在整个19世纪和20世纪前25年,最高法院的大法官们都承认法院最初管辖权的这一方面,但在1934年摩纳哥公国诉密西西比州案(Principality of Monaco v. Mississippi)的判决中,当共和国已经成为世界强国时,人们对这方面的认识就消失了。今天,要收回最高法院失去的管辖权,需要缩小这一决定的范围,但考虑到美国联邦制的复苏和全球化的步伐,这是有道理的。
{"title":"THE SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES AS QUASI-INTERNATIONAL TRIBUNAL: RECLAIMING THE COURT'S ORIGINAL AND EXCLUSIVE JURISDICTION OVER TREATY-BASED SUITS BY FOREIGN STATES AGAINST STATES","authors":"Thomas H. Lee","doi":"10.2307/4099335","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2307/4099335","url":null,"abstract":"In this Article, Professor Lee argues that the Constitution vests in the Supreme Court original and exclusive jurisdiction over suits brought by foreign states against States alleging violations of treaties of the United States. The basis for nonimmunity is a peacekeeping theory of ratification consent: Just as, by ratifying the Constitution, the States agreed to suits by other States and the national sovereign to ensure domestic peace, they agreed to suits by foreign states in the supreme national tribunal for the sake of international peace. The Founders of the new Republic viewed state breach of the 1783 Treaty of Peace as the leading potential cause for a shooting or trade war. The Article’s thesis is supported by the text of Article III as amended by the Eleventh Amendment and by evidence of original intent, including the inaugural implementation of the Original Jurisdiction Clause by the Judiciary Act of 1789. Nor is it inconsistent with the principle of sovereign dignity for the semisovereign States to be sued by fully sovereign foreign states in the Supreme Court. Justices of the Court throughout the nineteenth and the first quarter of the twentieth centuries acknowledged this aspect of the Court’s original jurisdiction, but awareness was lost by the time of the 1934 decision in Principality of Monaco v. Mississippi when the Republic had become a world power. Reclaiming the Court’s lost jurisdiction today requires a narrowing of that decision, but makes sense given the resurgence of American federalism and the pace of globalization.","PeriodicalId":51408,"journal":{"name":"Columbia Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.9,"publicationDate":"2004-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2307/4099335","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68754907","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
THE NEW MORALIZERS: TRANSFORMING THE CONSERVATIVE LEGAL AGENDA 新的道德家:改变保守的法律议程
IF 2.9 2区 社会学 Pub Date : 2004-11-01 DOI: 10.2307/4099339
David A. Super
The essential elements of a wide range of social policies can be described in terms of responses to three basic questions. First, what burdens must the innocent carry? Second, what burdens must the blameworthy bear? And third, how does society assess blame? This Essay examines the increasingly successful efforts of a faction of social conservatives, called here the new moralizers, to reshape the resolution of each of these three issues and with them a wide range of social policies. Although the relative importance of these three questions has varied over time, the twentieth century saw a movement away from costly individualized adjudications of fault and toward efficiency as a guiding principle of lawmaking. Over the past decade, the new moralizers have sought to reverse this trend selectively, transforming law and social policy to increase reliance on individual assessments of virtue in place of rules of broad application. The new moralizers have imposed a range of per se rules that stigmatize and restrict unpopular groups without individualized findings of fault, while requiring individualized determinations of blameworthiness before restricting members of elites. Most remarkably, they have sought to create conditions in which providing less protection to the concededly innocent appears a moral imperative. The new moralizers' implicit assumptions about human nature are strikingly inconsistent with those of the law and economics movement, but they have received inadvertent aid from liberals. This Essay concludes that technical arguments cannot meet this agenda's considerable populist appeal. Its excesses, however, can be exposed and contained.
一系列广泛的社会政策的基本要素可以用对三个基本问题的回答来描述。首先,无辜的人必须承担什么责任?第二,应受责备的人必须承担什么负担?第三,社会是如何评估责任的?本文考察了社会保守派的一个派别,在这里被称为新道德家,为重塑这三个问题的解决方案以及与之相关的广泛的社会政策所做的日益成功的努力。尽管这三个问题的相对重要性随着时间的推移而变化,但20世纪见证了一场运动,即从代价高昂的个人过错裁决转向将效率作为立法的指导原则。在过去的十年里,新的道德家们试图有选择地扭转这一趋势,改变法律和社会政策,以增加对个人美德评估的依赖,而不是广泛适用的规则。新的道德家强加了一系列本身的规则,这些规则对不受欢迎的群体进行污名化和限制,而没有个性化的错误发现,同时要求在限制精英成员之前对应受谴责的人进行个性化的确定。最引人注目的是,他们试图创造一种条件,在这种条件下,减少对自认为无辜的人的保护似乎是一种道德上的要求。新道德家对人性的含蓄假设与法律和经济运动的假设明显不一致,但他们无意中得到了自由主义者的帮助。本文的结论是,技术论点无法满足这一议程相当大的民粹主义诉求。然而,它的过度行为是可以暴露和遏制的。
{"title":"THE NEW MORALIZERS: TRANSFORMING THE CONSERVATIVE LEGAL AGENDA","authors":"David A. Super","doi":"10.2307/4099339","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2307/4099339","url":null,"abstract":"The essential elements of a wide range of social policies can be described in terms of responses to three basic questions. First, what burdens must the innocent carry? Second, what burdens must the blameworthy bear? And third, how does society assess blame? This Essay examines the increasingly successful efforts of a faction of social conservatives, called here the new moralizers, to reshape the resolution of each of these three issues and with them a wide range of social policies. Although the relative importance of these three questions has varied over time, the twentieth century saw a movement away from costly individualized adjudications of fault and toward efficiency as a guiding principle of lawmaking. Over the past decade, the new moralizers have sought to reverse this trend selectively, transforming law and social policy to increase reliance on individual assessments of virtue in place of rules of broad application. The new moralizers have imposed a range of per se rules that stigmatize and restrict unpopular groups without individualized findings of fault, while requiring individualized determinations of blameworthiness before restricting members of elites. Most remarkably, they have sought to create conditions in which providing less protection to the concededly innocent appears a moral imperative. The new moralizers' implicit assumptions about human nature are strikingly inconsistent with those of the law and economics movement, but they have received inadvertent aid from liberals. This Essay concludes that technical arguments cannot meet this agenda's considerable populist appeal. Its excesses, however, can be exposed and contained.","PeriodicalId":51408,"journal":{"name":"Columbia Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.9,"publicationDate":"2004-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2307/4099339","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68755049","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 7
CARBON DIOXIDE: A POLLUTANT IN THE AIR, BUT IS THE EPA CORRECT THAT IT IS NOT AN "AIR POLLUTANT"? 二氧化碳:空气中的污染物,但是环保局说它不是“空气污染物”对吗?
IF 2.9 2区 社会学 Pub Date : 2004-11-01 DOI: 10.2307/4099338
N. Winters
{"title":"CARBON DIOXIDE: A POLLUTANT IN THE AIR, BUT IS THE EPA CORRECT THAT IT IS NOT AN \"AIR POLLUTANT\"?","authors":"N. Winters","doi":"10.2307/4099338","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2307/4099338","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":51408,"journal":{"name":"Columbia Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.9,"publicationDate":"2004-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2307/4099338","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68754990","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Embedded Options and the Case Against Compensation in Contract Law 嵌入期权与合同法中的赔偿案件
IF 2.9 2区 社会学 Pub Date : 2004-07-01 DOI: 10.7916/D8PR7VQ7
R. Scott, George G. Triantis
Despite the fact that compensation is the governing principle in contract law remedies, it has tenuous historical, economic and empirical support. A promisor's right to breach and pay damages (which is subject to the compensation principle) is only a subset of a larger family of termination rights that do not purport to compensate the promisee for losses suffered when the promisor walks away from the contemplated exchange. These termination rights can be characterized as embedded options that serve important risk management functions. We show that sellers often sell insurance to their buyers in the form of these embedded options. We explain why compensation is of little relevance to the option price agreed to by the parties, which is a function of the value of the option to the buyer, its cost to the seller and the market in which they transact. We thus propose a novel justification for why penalty liquidated damages may be higher than seller's costs: they are option prices that reflect the value of the options to the buyer. The regulation of liquidated damages is thus tantamount to price regulation, which is outside the realm of contract law. Moreover, in light of the heterogeneity among optimal option prices, we also make the case against having an expectation damages default rule to begin with. In thick markets, we argue for enforcing the parties ex ante risk allocation with market damages. In thin markets, we propose that parties be induced to agree explicitly with respect to all termination rights, including breach damages, by the threat of specific performance of their contemplated exchange or, in the case of consumers, by a default rule that provides them a termination option at no cost.
尽管赔偿是合同法救济的主导原则,但它的历史、经济和经验支持都很薄弱。承诺人违约和支付损害赔偿的权利(受赔偿原则的约束)只是一个更大的终止权家族的一个子集,当承诺人离开预期的交易时,承诺人所遭受的损失并没有得到补偿。这些终止权可以被描述为具有重要风险管理功能的嵌入式期权。我们表明,卖方经常以这些嵌入期权的形式向买方出售保险。我们解释了为什么补偿与双方同意的期权价格无关,期权价格是期权对买方的价值、卖方的成本和他们交易的市场的函数。因此,我们提出了一个新的理由来解释为什么违约金可能高于卖方的成本:它们是期权价格,反映了期权对买方的价值。因此,对违约金的监管等同于价格监管,而价格监管不在合同法的范畴之内。此外,鉴于最优期权价格之间的异质性,我们也提出了一个反对期望损害违约规则的案例。在厚市场中,我们主张用市场损害来强制各方事前风险分配。在稀薄的市场中,我们建议各方通过对其预期交易的特定履行的威胁,或在消费者的情况下,通过默认规则为他们提供免费的终止选择权,来诱导各方明确同意所有终止权,包括违约损害赔偿。
{"title":"Embedded Options and the Case Against Compensation in Contract Law","authors":"R. Scott, George G. Triantis","doi":"10.7916/D8PR7VQ7","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.7916/D8PR7VQ7","url":null,"abstract":"Despite the fact that compensation is the governing principle in contract law remedies, it has tenuous historical, economic and empirical support. A promisor's right to breach and pay damages (which is subject to the compensation principle) is only a subset of a larger family of termination rights that do not purport to compensate the promisee for losses suffered when the promisor walks away from the contemplated exchange. These termination rights can be characterized as embedded options that serve important risk management functions. We show that sellers often sell insurance to their buyers in the form of these embedded options. We explain why compensation is of little relevance to the option price agreed to by the parties, which is a function of the value of the option to the buyer, its cost to the seller and the market in which they transact. We thus propose a novel justification for why penalty liquidated damages may be higher than seller's costs: they are option prices that reflect the value of the options to the buyer. The regulation of liquidated damages is thus tantamount to price regulation, which is outside the realm of contract law. Moreover, in light of the heterogeneity among optimal option prices, we also make the case against having an expectation damages default rule to begin with. In thick markets, we argue for enforcing the parties ex ante risk allocation with market damages. In thin markets, we propose that parties be induced to agree explicitly with respect to all termination rights, including breach damages, by the threat of specific performance of their contemplated exchange or, in the case of consumers, by a default rule that provides them a termination option at no cost.","PeriodicalId":51408,"journal":{"name":"Columbia Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.9,"publicationDate":"2004-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71367442","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 37
The Domesticated Liberty of Lawrence v. Texas 劳伦斯诉德克萨斯州案中被驯化的自由
IF 2.9 2区 社会学 Pub Date : 2004-05-02 DOI: 10.7916/D84X57SP
Katherine M. Franke
In this Commentary, Professor Franke offers an account of the Supreme Court's decision in Lawrence v. Texas. She concludes that in overruling the earlier Bowers v. Hardwick decision, Justice Kennedy does not rely upon a robust form of freedom made available by the Court's earlier reproductive rights cases, but instead announces a kind of privatized liberty right that allows gay and lesbian couples the right to intimacy in the bedroom. In this sense, the rights-holders in Lawrence are people in relationships and the liberty right those couples enjoy does not extend beyond the domain of the private. Franke expresses concern that Lawrence risks domesticating the gay and lesbian civil rights movement. She argues that the limited scope of the Lawrence opinion, as well as the gay community's reaction to it, can be traced, in large part, to the palimpsestic presence of Bowers in the opinion and in the political organizing that has followed it.
在这篇评注中,弗兰克教授提供了最高法院对劳伦斯诉德克萨斯州案判决的解释。她的结论是,在推翻早期鲍尔斯诉哈德威克案的判决时,肯尼迪大法官并没有依赖于法院早期生殖权利案件中提供的一种强有力的自由形式,而是宣布了一种私有化的自由权利,即允许男女同性恋伴侣在卧室里亲密的权利。从这个意义上说,劳伦斯的权利持有者是处于关系中的人这些夫妻享有的自由权利并不超出私人领域。弗兰克担心劳伦斯可能会把同性恋民权运动驯化。她认为,劳伦斯意见的有限范围,以及同性恋群体对它的反应,在很大程度上可以追溯到鲍尔斯在该意见和随后的政治组织中的改写式存在。
{"title":"The Domesticated Liberty of Lawrence v. Texas","authors":"Katherine M. Franke","doi":"10.7916/D84X57SP","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.7916/D84X57SP","url":null,"abstract":"In this Commentary, Professor Franke offers an account of the Supreme Court's decision in Lawrence v. Texas. She concludes that in overruling the earlier Bowers v. Hardwick decision, Justice Kennedy does not rely upon a robust form of freedom made available by the Court's earlier reproductive rights cases, but instead announces a kind of privatized liberty right that allows gay and lesbian couples the right to intimacy in the bedroom. In this sense, the rights-holders in Lawrence are people in relationships and the liberty right those couples enjoy does not extend beyond the domain of the private. Franke expresses concern that Lawrence risks domesticating the gay and lesbian civil rights movement. She argues that the limited scope of the Lawrence opinion, as well as the gay community's reaction to it, can be traced, in large part, to the palimpsestic presence of Bowers in the opinion and in the political organizing that has followed it.","PeriodicalId":51408,"journal":{"name":"Columbia Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.9,"publicationDate":"2004-05-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71364297","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 80
Rationing Criminal Defense Entitlements: An Argument from Institutional Design 刑事辩护权利配给:一个制度设计的论证
IF 2.9 2区 社会学 Pub Date : 2004-04-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.444000
Darryl K. Brown
This essay takes as its premise that the widespread and long-term underfunding of indigent criminal defense is, for practical purposes, a permanent fixture of the political and constitutional landscape. From this assumption, it makes two points, one theoretical, the other practical. The theoretical point is that consistent underfunding of constitutional entitlements can be a legitimate legislative response to judicial specification of constitutional rights. Courts define constitutional rights, but many of those entitlements are unfunded mandates to legislatures. Entitlements such as the right to defense counsel, require money to become reality. Legislatures have responded by underfunding those rights, yet have not specified how limited funds should be allocated - that is, how rights should be rationed. The Supreme Court, in fact, has to a large degree barred legislatures from doing so through constitutional criminal procedure rules. This legislative-judicial dynamic implicitly delegates, largely to defense attorneys but also to trial judges, the task of rationing rights that cannot be implemented as fully as formal judicial pronouncement implies. This ongoing interaction between courts, legislatures and the defense bar (aided by trial judges) looks like a species of Dorf and Sabel's "democratic experimentalism," a model that describes a broad array of government actions that define constitutional and sub-constitutional law. Here the twist is that private actors - defense attorneys - have a large hand in constructing the real, working content of constitutional entitlements. Given this weighty task, the essay sketches a set of practical guidelines by which defense counsel and other trial-level actors can most sensibly implement the job of rationing rights that has been delegated to them. This essay proposes a set of default rules grounded on two core principles: priority to factual innocence over other instrumental goals of criminal procedure, and a harm-reduction principle that gives preference to suspects facing greater potential punishments. A set of default rules, drawn largely from the study of wrongful convictions, provides practical guidance for implementing these principles. This practice substantively revises the real meaning of constitutional entitlements and leaves some defendants indisputably with less than judicial pronouncements of constitutional law imply. But when rights are underfunded, that outcome is inevitable, as longstanding practice demonstrates. Explicitly confronting funding limits and allocating rights in light of them yields a more coherent, defensible allocation of entitlements.
本文的前提是,贫困刑事辩护的广泛和长期资金不足,实际上是政治和宪法景观的永久固定。从这个假设出发,它提出了两点,一个是理论的,另一个是实际的。理论上的观点是,宪法权利的持续资金不足可以成为对宪法权利司法规范的合法立法回应。法院定义了宪法权利,但其中许多权利是立法机构没有资金支持的授权。诸如获得辩护律师的权利等权利需要金钱才能成为现实。立法机关的反应是对这些权利的资金不足,但没有具体说明如何分配有限的资金- -即如何分配权利。事实上,最高法院在很大程度上禁止立法机关通过宪法刑事诉讼规则这样做。这种立法-司法动态隐含地将分配权利的任务主要委托给了辩护律师,也委托给了审判法官,这些权利不能像正式的司法声明所暗示的那样得到充分实施。法院、立法机构和辩护律师之间的这种持续互动(在审判法官的帮助下)看起来像是多夫和萨贝尔的“民主实验主义”的一种,这种模式描述了一系列界定宪法和次宪法法律的政府行为。这里的转折是,私人行为者——辩护律师——在构建宪法权利的真实、有效内容方面发挥了很大的作用。鉴于这项艰巨的任务,本文概述了一套实用的指导方针,根据这些指导方针,辩护律师和其他审判级别的行为者可以最明智地执行分配给他们的权利的工作。本文提出了一套基于两个核心原则的默认规则:优先考虑事实无罪,而不是刑事诉讼的其他工具目标,以及优先考虑面临更大潜在惩罚的嫌疑人的减少伤害原则。一套主要从对错误定罪的研究中得出的默认规则为实施这些原则提供了实际指导。这种做法实质上修改了宪法权利的真正含义,并使一些被告无可争议地获得比宪法司法声明所暗示的要少的权利。但长期以来的实践表明,当权利资金不足时,这种结果是不可避免的。明确地面对资金限制,并据此分配权利,会使权利分配更连贯、更合理。
{"title":"Rationing Criminal Defense Entitlements: An Argument from Institutional Design","authors":"Darryl K. Brown","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.444000","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.444000","url":null,"abstract":"This essay takes as its premise that the widespread and long-term underfunding of indigent criminal defense is, for practical purposes, a permanent fixture of the political and constitutional landscape. From this assumption, it makes two points, one theoretical, the other practical. The theoretical point is that consistent underfunding of constitutional entitlements can be a legitimate legislative response to judicial specification of constitutional rights. Courts define constitutional rights, but many of those entitlements are unfunded mandates to legislatures. Entitlements such as the right to defense counsel, require money to become reality. Legislatures have responded by underfunding those rights, yet have not specified how limited funds should be allocated - that is, how rights should be rationed. The Supreme Court, in fact, has to a large degree barred legislatures from doing so through constitutional criminal procedure rules. This legislative-judicial dynamic implicitly delegates, largely to defense attorneys but also to trial judges, the task of rationing rights that cannot be implemented as fully as formal judicial pronouncement implies. This ongoing interaction between courts, legislatures and the defense bar (aided by trial judges) looks like a species of Dorf and Sabel's \"democratic experimentalism,\" a model that describes a broad array of government actions that define constitutional and sub-constitutional law. Here the twist is that private actors - defense attorneys - have a large hand in constructing the real, working content of constitutional entitlements. Given this weighty task, the essay sketches a set of practical guidelines by which defense counsel and other trial-level actors can most sensibly implement the job of rationing rights that has been delegated to them. This essay proposes a set of default rules grounded on two core principles: priority to factual innocence over other instrumental goals of criminal procedure, and a harm-reduction principle that gives preference to suspects facing greater potential punishments. A set of default rules, drawn largely from the study of wrongful convictions, provides practical guidance for implementing these principles. This practice substantively revises the real meaning of constitutional entitlements and leaves some defendants indisputably with less than judicial pronouncements of constitutional law imply. But when rights are underfunded, that outcome is inevitable, as longstanding practice demonstrates. Explicitly confronting funding limits and allocating rights in light of them yields a more coherent, defensible allocation of entitlements.","PeriodicalId":51408,"journal":{"name":"Columbia Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.9,"publicationDate":"2004-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68789438","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 13
Truth and Justice in Sierra Leone: Coordination between Commission and Court 塞拉利昂的真相与正义:委员会与法院之间的协调
IF 2.9 2区 社会学 Pub Date : 2004-04-01 DOI: 10.2307/4099329
Elizabeth M. Evenson
{"title":"Truth and Justice in Sierra Leone: Coordination between Commission and Court","authors":"Elizabeth M. Evenson","doi":"10.2307/4099329","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2307/4099329","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":51408,"journal":{"name":"Columbia Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.9,"publicationDate":"2004-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2307/4099329","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68754382","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 46
Diffusion of Local Regulatory Innovations: The San Francisco Cedaw Ordinance and the New York City Human Rights Initiative 地方监管创新的传播:旧金山《消除对妇女歧视条例》和纽约市人权倡议
IF 2.9 2区 社会学 Pub Date : 2004-04-01 DOI: 10.2307/4099330
Stacy Laira Lozner
{"title":"Diffusion of Local Regulatory Innovations: The San Francisco Cedaw Ordinance and the New York City Human Rights Initiative","authors":"Stacy Laira Lozner","doi":"10.2307/4099330","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2307/4099330","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":51408,"journal":{"name":"Columbia Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.9,"publicationDate":"2004-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2307/4099330","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68754575","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 30
期刊
Columbia Law Review
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1