首页 > 最新文献

Columbia Law Review最新文献

英文 中文
Resolving the Qualified Immunity Dilemma: Constitutional Tort Claims for Nominal Damages 解决合格豁免困境:名义损害赔偿的宪法侵权索赔
IF 2.9 2区 社会学 Pub Date : 2011-04-19 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.1795341
James E. Pfander
Scholars have criticized the Court’s qualified immunity decision in Pearson v. Callahan on the ground that it may lead to stagnation in the judicial elaboration of constitutional norms. Under current law, officers sued in their personal capacity for constitutional torts enjoy qualified immunity from liability unless the plaintiff can persuade the court that the conduct in question violated clearly established law. Pearson permits the lower courts to dismiss on the basis of legal uncertainty; it no longer requires the courts to address the merits of the constitutional question. This essay suggests that constitutional tort claimants should be permitted to avoid the qualified immunity defense by pursuing claims for nominal damages alone. Such nominal claims have a lengthy pedigree, both as a common law analog to the declaratory judgment, and as a remedy for constitutional violations. Because they do not threaten to impose personal liability on official defendants, nominal claims should not give rise to a qualified immunity defense. By seeking only nominal relief, litigants could secure the vindication of their constitutional rights in cases where legal uncertainty might otherwise lead to a dismissal. Such a regime would advance the acknowledged interest in maintaining a vibrant body of constitutional law without threatening to impose ruinous liability on the officials named in the complaint.
学者们批评了法院在皮尔逊诉卡拉汉案中对有条件豁免的裁决,理由是它可能导致宪法规范的司法阐述停滞不前。根据现行法律,以个人身份就宪法侵权提起诉讼的官员享有有条件的责任豁免,除非原告能使法院相信有关行为违反了明确确立的法律。皮尔逊允许下级法院基于法律的不确定性驳回诉讼;它不再要求法院处理宪法问题的是非曲直。本文建议,应允许宪法侵权请求人仅对名义损害赔偿提出索赔,以避免有条件的豁免抗辩。这种名义上的索赔有着悠久的历史,既是一种类似于宣告性判决的普通法,也是对违反宪法的一种补救。由于名义上的索赔不会威胁对正式被告施加个人责任,因此不应产生有条件的豁免辩护。通过寻求名义上的救济,诉讼当事人可以确保在法律不确定性可能导致驳回案件的情况下维护其宪法权利。这样一种制度将促进维护一个充满活力的宪法体系的公认利益,而不会威胁到对诉状中提到的官员施加毁灭性的责任。
{"title":"Resolving the Qualified Immunity Dilemma: Constitutional Tort Claims for Nominal Damages","authors":"James E. Pfander","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.1795341","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.1795341","url":null,"abstract":"Scholars have criticized the Court’s qualified immunity decision in Pearson v. Callahan on the ground that it may lead to stagnation in the judicial elaboration of constitutional norms. Under current law, officers sued in their personal capacity for constitutional torts enjoy qualified immunity from liability unless the plaintiff can persuade the court that the conduct in question violated clearly established law. Pearson permits the lower courts to dismiss on the basis of legal uncertainty; it no longer requires the courts to address the merits of the constitutional question. This essay suggests that constitutional tort claimants should be permitted to avoid the qualified immunity defense by pursuing claims for nominal damages alone. Such nominal claims have a lengthy pedigree, both as a common law analog to the declaratory judgment, and as a remedy for constitutional violations. Because they do not threaten to impose personal liability on official defendants, nominal claims should not give rise to a qualified immunity defense. By seeking only nominal relief, litigants could secure the vindication of their constitutional rights in cases where legal uncertainty might otherwise lead to a dismissal. Such a regime would advance the acknowledged interest in maintaining a vibrant body of constitutional law without threatening to impose ruinous liability on the officials named in the complaint.","PeriodicalId":51408,"journal":{"name":"Columbia Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.9,"publicationDate":"2011-04-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67747475","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 5
Clear Statement Rules and the Constitution 明确声明规则和宪法
IF 2.9 2区 社会学 Pub Date : 2010-03-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2849258
J. Manning
In recent years, the Supreme Court has increasingly supplemented traditional Marbury-style judicial review with constitutionally inspired clear statement rules. These canons of statutory construction have two characteristics. First, they impose a clarity tax on Congress by insisting that Congress legislate exceptionally clearly when it wishes to achieve a statutory outcome that threatens to intrude upon some judicially identified constitutional value-such as federalism, nonretroactivity, or the rule of law. Second, as the Court has acknowledged, clear statement rules apply even though the outcomes avoided by such rules would not themselves violate the Constitution. For example, although the Court has held that the Ex Post Facto Clause prohibits retroactivity only in the criminal context, the Court has also culled from that clause (among others) a more general value that it uses to justify a nonretroactivity clear statement rule for civil cases.This Essay argues that such clear statement rules rest on the mistaken premise that the Constitution contains freestanding values that can be meaningfully identified and enforced apart from the specific terms of the clauses from which the Court derives them. In fact, the Constitution represents a "bundle of compromises" that embody not merely abstract ends or values, but also particular means that limit and define the scope and the content of those values. If the Ex Post Facto Clause prohibits retroactivity in the criminal context, it violates the terms of the implementing bargain to extend its animating value to civil contexts. This concern-that clear statement rules impermissibly abstract from concrete constitutional means to general constitutional ends-applies, moreover, even if one believes that most constitutional law is now properly found in judge-made implementing doctrine. Such doctrine itself often defines relatively precise means of enforcing the Constitution, not merely the vague constitutional ends that so often animate clear statement rules.
近年来,最高法院越来越多地用宪法启发的明确陈述规则来补充传统的马布里式司法审查。这些法律解释规范有两个特点。首先,他们通过坚持国会在希望实现可能侵犯某些司法认定的宪法价值(如联邦制、不溯及力或法治)的法定结果时,特别明确地立法,向国会征收明确税。第二,正如法院所承认的,明确的陈述规则适用,即使这些规则所避免的结果本身并不违反宪法。例如,虽然本院认为,事后条款仅在刑事案件中禁止溯及既往,但本院也从该条款中(除其他外)剔除了一种更为普遍的价值,用以证明民事案件中不溯及既往的明确陈述规则是合理的。本文认为,这种明确的声明规则建立在一个错误的前提之上,即宪法包含独立的价值观,这些价值观可以被有意义地识别和执行,而不是法院从中得出的条款的具体条款。事实上,《宪法》代表了“一系列妥协”,这些妥协不仅体现了抽象的目的或价值观,而且还体现了限制和界定这些价值观的范围和内容的特定手段。如果溯后事由条款在刑事情形中禁止溯及力,则违反了将其溯及力扩展到民事情形的执行交易条款。此外,这种担忧——明确的声明规则不允许从具体的宪法手段抽象到一般的宪法目的——也适用,即使人们认为现在大多数宪法都是在法官制定的实施原则中找到的。这种原则本身往往定义了执行宪法的相对精确的方法,而不仅仅是模糊的宪法目的,而这些目的往往会激发明确的声明规则。
{"title":"Clear Statement Rules and the Constitution","authors":"J. Manning","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2849258","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2849258","url":null,"abstract":"In recent years, the Supreme Court has increasingly supplemented traditional Marbury-style judicial review with constitutionally inspired clear statement rules. These canons of statutory construction have two characteristics. First, they impose a clarity tax on Congress by insisting that Congress legislate exceptionally clearly when it wishes to achieve a statutory outcome that threatens to intrude upon some judicially identified constitutional value-such as federalism, nonretroactivity, or the rule of law. Second, as the Court has acknowledged, clear statement rules apply even though the outcomes avoided by such rules would not themselves violate the Constitution. For example, although the Court has held that the Ex Post Facto Clause prohibits retroactivity only in the criminal context, the Court has also culled from that clause (among others) a more general value that it uses to justify a nonretroactivity clear statement rule for civil cases.This Essay argues that such clear statement rules rest on the mistaken premise that the Constitution contains freestanding values that can be meaningfully identified and enforced apart from the specific terms of the clauses from which the Court derives them. In fact, the Constitution represents a \"bundle of compromises\" that embody not merely abstract ends or values, but also particular means that limit and define the scope and the content of those values. If the Ex Post Facto Clause prohibits retroactivity in the criminal context, it violates the terms of the implementing bargain to extend its animating value to civil contexts. This concern-that clear statement rules impermissibly abstract from concrete constitutional means to general constitutional ends-applies, moreover, even if one believes that most constitutional law is now properly found in judge-made implementing doctrine. Such doctrine itself often defines relatively precise means of enforcing the Constitution, not merely the vague constitutional ends that so often animate clear statement rules.","PeriodicalId":51408,"journal":{"name":"Columbia Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.9,"publicationDate":"2010-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.2849258","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68387007","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 9
The Disposing Power of the Legislature 立法机关的处置权
IF 2.9 2区 社会学 Pub Date : 2010-01-01 DOI: 10.7916/D89Z94H8
T. Merrill
The Constitution as we understand it includes principles that have emerged over time in a common law fashion. One such principle is the dis posing power of the legislature?the understanding that only the legislature has the power to arrange, order, and distribute the power to act with the force of law among the different institutions of society. This Essay illustrates the gradual emergence of the disposing power in criminal, civil, and administra tive law, and offers some reasons why it is appropriate that the legislature be given this exclusive authority. One implication of the disposing power is that another type of constitutional common law?the power of courts to pre scribe rules inspired by the Constitution but subject to legislative revision, as described in Professor Henry Monaghan fs pathbreaking 1975 Harvard Law Review Foreword?may in fact be unconstitutional in many of its applications.
我们所理解的宪法包括了随着时间的推移以普通法的形式出现的原则。其中一个原则就是立法机关的裁断权。认识到只有立法机关才有权在不同的社会机构之间安排、命令和分配具有法律效力的权力。本文阐述了处置权在刑法、民法和行政法中逐渐出现的过程,并提出了赋予立法机关这种排他性权力的合理性。处置权的一个含义是另一种宪法普通法?正如亨利·莫纳汉教授在1975年开创性的《哈佛法律评论前言》中所描述的那样,法院制定受宪法启发但受制于立法修订的规则的权力?可能在很多情况下都是违宪的。
{"title":"The Disposing Power of the Legislature","authors":"T. Merrill","doi":"10.7916/D89Z94H8","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.7916/D89Z94H8","url":null,"abstract":"The Constitution as we understand it includes principles that have emerged over time in a common law fashion. One such principle is the dis posing power of the legislature?the understanding that only the legislature has the power to arrange, order, and distribute the power to act with the force of law among the different institutions of society. This Essay illustrates the gradual emergence of the disposing power in criminal, civil, and administra tive law, and offers some reasons why it is appropriate that the legislature be given this exclusive authority. One implication of the disposing power is that another type of constitutional common law?the power of courts to pre scribe rules inspired by the Constitution but subject to legislative revision, as described in Professor Henry Monaghan fs pathbreaking 1975 Harvard Law Review Foreword?may in fact be unconstitutional in many of its applications.","PeriodicalId":51408,"journal":{"name":"Columbia Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.9,"publicationDate":"2010-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71365543","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 7
A treatise on the specific performance of contracts 契约论:关于契约具体履行的论文
IF 2.9 2区 社会学 Pub Date : 2009-10-21 DOI: 10.2307/1112913
J. Pomeroy, J. Mann
{"title":"A treatise on the specific performance of contracts","authors":"J. Pomeroy, J. Mann","doi":"10.2307/1112913","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2307/1112913","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":51408,"journal":{"name":"Columbia Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.9,"publicationDate":"2009-10-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2307/1112913","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68225009","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Civil Liability and Mandatory Disclosure 民事责任和强制披露
IF 2.9 2区 社会学 Pub Date : 2008-04-01 DOI: 10.7916/D8Z31Z4H
M. Fox
This paper explores the appropriate system of civil liability for mandatory securities disclosure violations by established, publicly traded issuers. The U.S. system's design has become outmoded as the underlying mandatory disclosure regime that has moved from an emphasis on disclosure at the time that an issuer makes a public offering, to an emphasis on the issuer's ongoing periodic disclosures. An efficiency analysis shows that, unlike U.S. law today, the relevant actors should have equally great civil liability incentives to comply with the disclosure rules whether or not the issuer is offering securities at the time. An issuer not making a public offering of securities should have no liability because the compensatory justification is weak. Deterrence will be achieved instead by imposing liability on other actors. An issuer's annual filings should be signed by an external certifier - an investment bank or other well capitalized entity with financial expertise. If the filing contains a material misstatement and the certifier fails to do due diligence, the certifier would face measured liability. Officers and directors would be subject to similar liability. Damages would be payable to the issuer. When an issuer is making a public offering, it would be liable to investors for its disclosure violations as an antidote to what otherwise would be an extra incentive not to comply. This design would address two major complaints concerning the existing U.S. civil liability system: underwriter Section 11 liability for a lack of due diligence concerning disclosures that in modern offerings underwriters have no realistic ability to police, and litigation-expensive issuer class action fraud-on-market liability. The system suggested here would eliminate both sorts of liability. But unlike elimination reforms proposed by underwriters and issuers, it would retain deterrence by substituting in place of these liabilities more effective and efficient civil liability incentives for disclosure compliance.
本文探讨了成熟的上市发行人违反强制性证券披露的民事责任制度。美国上市制度的设计已经过时,因为其基本的强制性披露制度已经从强调发行人在公开发行时进行披露,转变为强调发行人正在进行的定期披露。效率分析表明,与今天的美国法律不同,无论发行人当时是否发行证券,相关行为者都应该有同样大的民事责任激励来遵守披露规则。未公开发行证券的发行人不承担赔偿责任,赔偿理由不充分。相反,威慑将通过对其他行为者施加责任来实现。发行人的年度文件应由外部认证机构——投资银行或其他资本充足、具有金融专业知识的实体——签署。如果文件中包含重大错报,且认证机构未能尽职调查,则认证机构将面临计量责任。高级管理人员和董事也将承担类似的责任。损害赔偿应支付给开证人。当发行人进行公开发行时,它将因违反信息披露规定而对投资者承担责任,以消除不遵守规定的额外动机。这一设计将解决有关现有美国民事责任制度的两个主要投诉:承销商第11条对缺乏尽职调查的披露的责任,在现代发行中承销商没有实际的监督能力,以及诉讼费用高昂的发行人集体诉讼市场欺诈责任。这里建议的制度将消除这两种责任。但与承销商和发行人提出的取消改革不同,它将通过用更有效的民事责任激励措施来取代这些责任,从而保持威慑力。
{"title":"Civil Liability and Mandatory Disclosure","authors":"M. Fox","doi":"10.7916/D8Z31Z4H","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.7916/D8Z31Z4H","url":null,"abstract":"This paper explores the appropriate system of civil liability for mandatory securities disclosure violations by established, publicly traded issuers. The U.S. system's design has become outmoded as the underlying mandatory disclosure regime that has moved from an emphasis on disclosure at the time that an issuer makes a public offering, to an emphasis on the issuer's ongoing periodic disclosures. An efficiency analysis shows that, unlike U.S. law today, the relevant actors should have equally great civil liability incentives to comply with the disclosure rules whether or not the issuer is offering securities at the time. An issuer not making a public offering of securities should have no liability because the compensatory justification is weak. Deterrence will be achieved instead by imposing liability on other actors. An issuer's annual filings should be signed by an external certifier - an investment bank or other well capitalized entity with financial expertise. If the filing contains a material misstatement and the certifier fails to do due diligence, the certifier would face measured liability. Officers and directors would be subject to similar liability. Damages would be payable to the issuer. When an issuer is making a public offering, it would be liable to investors for its disclosure violations as an antidote to what otherwise would be an extra incentive not to comply. This design would address two major complaints concerning the existing U.S. civil liability system: underwriter Section 11 liability for a lack of due diligence concerning disclosures that in modern offerings underwriters have no realistic ability to police, and litigation-expensive issuer class action fraud-on-market liability. The system suggested here would eliminate both sorts of liability. But unlike elimination reforms proposed by underwriters and issuers, it would retain deterrence by substituting in place of these liabilities more effective and efficient civil liability incentives for disclosure compliance.","PeriodicalId":51408,"journal":{"name":"Columbia Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.9,"publicationDate":"2008-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71368505","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 23
Constitutional Tipping Points: Civil Rights, Social Change, and Fact-Based Adjudication 宪法转折点:公民权利、社会变革和基于事实的裁决
IF 2.9 2区 社会学 Pub Date : 2008-03-05 DOI: 10.7916/D8WD4033
Suzanne B. Goldberg
This Article offers an account of how courts respond to social change, with a specific focus on the process by which courts "tip" from one understanding of a social group and its constitutional claims to another. Adjudication of equal protection and due process claims, in particular, requires courts to make normative judgments regarding the effect of traits such as race, sex, sexual orientation, or mental retardation on group members' status and capacity. Yet, Professor Goldberg argues, courts commonly approach decisionmaking by focusing only on the "facts" about a social group, an approach that she terms "fact-based adjudication." Professor Goldberg critiques this approach for its flawed premise that restrictions on social groups can be evaluated based on facts alone and its role in obscuring judicial involvement in selecting among competing norms. The Article also observes that because fact-based adjudication enables courts to leave norms unacknowledged, it does serve the judiciary's institutional interests by maximizing flexibility for future decisionmaking regarding restrictions on group members' rights. At the same time, however, this approach facilitates inconsistency in theory and outcome by enabling courts to variously embrace and reject traditional rationales for restricting social groups without having to justify the inconsistent treatment of group-related norms. As a possible remedy for these flaws, the Article considers the costs and benefits of greater judicial candor regarding the normative underpinning of decisions. Although Professor Goldberg ultimately advocates only a limited modification to the current fact-based adjudication regime, she concludes that our theories of judicial review will improve, both with respect to descriptive accuracy and normative bite, to the extent they recognize the inevitable judicial involvement in making normative judgments about social groups.
本文介绍了法院如何应对社会变化,特别关注法院从对社会群体及其宪法要求的一种理解“提示”到另一种理解的过程。特别是对平等保护和正当程序要求的裁决,要求法院对种族、性别、性取向或智力迟钝等特征对群体成员地位和能力的影响作出规范性判断。然而,戈德堡教授认为,法院通常只关注一个社会群体的“事实”来进行决策,她称之为“基于事实的裁决”。戈德堡教授批评了这种方法,因为它有缺陷的前提,即对社会群体的限制可以仅根据事实进行评估,而且它在选择竞争性规范时模糊了司法参与的作用。该条还指出,由于基于事实的裁决使法院能够不承认规范,它确实通过最大限度地提高未来在限制群体成员权利方面的决策灵活性,服务于司法机构的制度利益。然而,与此同时,这种方法使法院能够以各种方式接受或拒绝限制社会群体的传统理由,而不必为不一致的对待群体相关规范进行辩护,从而促进了理论和结果的不一致性。作为对这些缺陷的可能补救,该条考虑了在决定的规范性基础方面更大的司法公正的成本和收益。尽管戈德堡教授最终只主张对当前基于事实的裁决制度进行有限的修改,但她得出的结论是,我们的司法审查理论将得到改进,无论是在描述的准确性还是在规范的咬合性方面,只要它们认识到对社会群体做出规范性判断时不可避免的司法介入。
{"title":"Constitutional Tipping Points: Civil Rights, Social Change, and Fact-Based Adjudication","authors":"Suzanne B. Goldberg","doi":"10.7916/D8WD4033","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.7916/D8WD4033","url":null,"abstract":"This Article offers an account of how courts respond to social change, with a specific focus on the process by which courts \"tip\" from one understanding of a social group and its constitutional claims to another. Adjudication of equal protection and due process claims, in particular, requires courts to make normative judgments regarding the effect of traits such as race, sex, sexual orientation, or mental retardation on group members' status and capacity. Yet, Professor Goldberg argues, courts commonly approach decisionmaking by focusing only on the \"facts\" about a social group, an approach that she terms \"fact-based adjudication.\" Professor Goldberg critiques this approach for its flawed premise that restrictions on social groups can be evaluated based on facts alone and its role in obscuring judicial involvement in selecting among competing norms. The Article also observes that because fact-based adjudication enables courts to leave norms unacknowledged, it does serve the judiciary's institutional interests by maximizing flexibility for future decisionmaking regarding restrictions on group members' rights. At the same time, however, this approach facilitates inconsistency in theory and outcome by enabling courts to variously embrace and reject traditional rationales for restricting social groups without having to justify the inconsistent treatment of group-related norms. As a possible remedy for these flaws, the Article considers the costs and benefits of greater judicial candor regarding the normative underpinning of decisions. Although Professor Goldberg ultimately advocates only a limited modification to the current fact-based adjudication regime, she concludes that our theories of judicial review will improve, both with respect to descriptive accuracy and normative bite, to the extent they recognize the inevitable judicial involvement in making normative judgments about social groups.","PeriodicalId":51408,"journal":{"name":"Columbia Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.9,"publicationDate":"2008-03-05","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"71368543","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 10
Human Welfare, Not Human Rights 人类福利,而不是人权
IF 2.9 2区 社会学 Pub Date : 2008-03-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.1105209
E. Posner
Human rights treaties play an important role in international relations but they lack a foundation in moral philosophy and doubts have been raised about their effectiveness for constraining states. Drawing on ideas from the literature on economic development, this paper argues that international concern should be focused on human welfare rather than on human rights. A focus on welfare has three advantages. First, the proposition that governments should advance the welfare of their populations enjoys broader international and philosophical support than do the various rights that are incorporated in the human rights treaties. Second, the human rights treaties are both too rigid and too vague - they do not allow governments to adopt reasonable policies that advance welfare at the expense of rights, and they do not set forth rules governing how states may trade off rights. A welfare treaty could provide guidance by supplying a maximand along with verifiable measures of compliance. Third, the human rights regime and international development policy work at cross-purposes. Development policy favors the poorest states, while the human rights regime condemns the states with the worst governments: unfortunately, the poorest states usually have the worst governments. Various possible welfare treaties are surveyed.
人权条约在国际关系中发挥着重要作用,但它们缺乏道德哲学基础,对其约束国家的有效性提出了质疑。根据经济发展文献的观点,本文认为国际关注应该集中在人类福利而不是人权上。关注福利有三个优势。首先,政府应该促进人民福利的主张比人权条约中所包含的各种权利得到了更广泛的国际和哲学上的支持。其次,人权条约既过于僵化又过于模糊——它们不允许政府采取以牺牲权利为代价促进福利的合理政策,也没有规定各国如何权衡权利的规则。福利条约可以提供指导,规定最高限额以及可核查的遵守措施。第三,人权机制与国际发展政策相互矛盾。发展政策有利于最贫穷的国家,而人权制度谴责政府最糟糕的国家:不幸的是,最贫穷的国家通常有最糟糕的政府。调查了各种可能的福利条约。
{"title":"Human Welfare, Not Human Rights","authors":"E. Posner","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.1105209","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.1105209","url":null,"abstract":"Human rights treaties play an important role in international relations but they lack a foundation in moral philosophy and doubts have been raised about their effectiveness for constraining states. Drawing on ideas from the literature on economic development, this paper argues that international concern should be focused on human welfare rather than on human rights. A focus on welfare has three advantages. First, the proposition that governments should advance the welfare of their populations enjoys broader international and philosophical support than do the various rights that are incorporated in the human rights treaties. Second, the human rights treaties are both too rigid and too vague - they do not allow governments to adopt reasonable policies that advance welfare at the expense of rights, and they do not set forth rules governing how states may trade off rights. A welfare treaty could provide guidance by supplying a maximand along with verifiable measures of compliance. Third, the human rights regime and international development policy work at cross-purposes. Development policy favors the poorest states, while the human rights regime condemns the states with the worst governments: unfortunately, the poorest states usually have the worst governments. Various possible welfare treaties are surveyed.","PeriodicalId":51408,"journal":{"name":"Columbia Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.9,"publicationDate":"2008-03-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68139717","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 91
Reforming Securities Litigation Reform: Restructuring the Relationship Between Public and Private Enforcement of Rule 10b-5 改革证券诉讼改革:重组规则10b-5的公共和私人执行关系
IF 2.9 2区 社会学 Pub Date : 2008-02-24 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.1096864
A. Rose
For years, commentators have debated how to reform the controversial Rule 10b-5 class action, without pausing to ask whether the game is worth the candle. Is private enforcement of Rule 10b-5 worth preserving, or might we be better off with exclusive public enforcement? This fundamental and neglected question demands attention today more than ever. An academic consensus has now emerged that private enforcement of Rule 10b-5 cannot be defended on compensatory grounds, at least in its most common form (a fraud-on-the-market class action brought against a non-trading issuer). That leaves the oft-cited, but under-theorized, rationale that private enforcement is a necessary supplement to the securities fraud deterrence efforts of the SEC. When this justification is critically examined, however, it proves to be highly debatable. A rich body of law and economics scholarship teaches that bounty hunter enforcement of an overbroad law, like Rule 10b-5, may lead to overdeterrence and stymie governmental efforts to set effective enforcement policy (even assuming away strike suits and the agency costs that attend class action litigation); if private enforcement is nevertheless desirable - a contestable proposition - it is because a world without it might result in even greater deviations from optimal deterrence, due to SEC budgetary constraints, inefficiency and/or capture. By carefully explicating the relative advantages and disadvantages of private Rule 10b-5 enforcement versus exclusive public enforcement, this Article reveals a new and better way to remedy the shortcomings of the Rule 10b-5 class action. It proposes that policymakers adopt an oversight approach to securities litigation reform by, for example, granting the SEC the ability to screen which Rule 10b-5 class actions may be filed, and against whom. By muting the overdeterrence threat of private litigation and placing the SEC back firmly at the helm of Rule 10b-5 enforcement policy, this approach would mitigate the primary disadvantages of private enforcement. Moreover, by preserving a private check on SEC inefficiency and capture and allowing the SEC to continue to supplement its budget with private enforcement resources, it would do so without eliminating the primary advantages of the current system. This approach stands in stark contrast to prior securities litigation reforms, which have responded to the overdeterrence threat posed by Rule 10b-5 class actions by rigidly narrowing the scope of private liability. This Article argues that an oversight approach to securities litigation reform carries distinct advantages over this narrowing approach, and ought to receive serious consideration in the ongoing policy debate.
多年来,评论员们一直在讨论如何改革备受争议的10b-5集体诉讼规则,却没有停下来问问这场比赛是否值得。10b-5规则的私人执行是否值得保留,或者我们是否可以更好地进行排他性的公共执行?这个基本而被忽视的问题今天比以往任何时候都更需要关注。学术界目前已形成共识,认为10b-5规则的私人执行不能以补偿性理由为辩护,至少在最常见的形式(针对非交易发行人的市场欺诈集体诉讼)中是如此。这就留下了一个经常被引用但理论不足的理由,即私人执法是证券交易委员会遏制证券欺诈努力的必要补充。然而,当这个理由被严格审查时,它被证明是非常有争议的。大量的法律和经济学研究表明,赏金猎人执行过于宽泛的法律,比如10b-5规则,可能会导致过度威慑,阻碍政府制定有效执法政策的努力(即使不考虑罢工诉讼和参与集体诉讼的代理成本);如果私人执法仍然是可取的(这是一个有争议的主张),那是因为一个没有私人执法的世界,可能会由于美国证券交易委员会(SEC)的预算限制、效率低下和/或俘获,导致更大程度上偏离最优威慑。本文通过对10b-5规则私法执行与排他性公法执行的相对优势和劣势的分析,揭示了一种新的、更好的弥补10b-5规则集体诉讼缺陷的途径。它建议政策制定者对证券诉讼改革采取一种监督方法,例如,授权SEC审查哪些集体诉讼可以提起,以及针对谁提起。通过消除私人诉讼的过度威慑威胁,并让SEC重新牢牢掌控10b-5规则的执行政策,这种方法将减轻私人执法的主要缺点。此外,通过保留对证券交易委员会效率低下和捕获的私人检查,并允许证券交易委员会继续用私人执法资源补充其预算,它将在不消除当前系统的主要优势的情况下这样做。这种做法与之前的证券诉讼改革形成鲜明对比,后者通过严格缩小私人责任的范围来应对规则10b-5集体诉讼带来的过度威慑威胁。本文认为,证券诉讼改革的监督方式比这种狭隘的方式具有明显的优势,应该在正在进行的政策辩论中得到认真的考虑。
{"title":"Reforming Securities Litigation Reform: Restructuring the Relationship Between Public and Private Enforcement of Rule 10b-5","authors":"A. Rose","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.1096864","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.1096864","url":null,"abstract":"For years, commentators have debated how to reform the controversial Rule 10b-5 class action, without pausing to ask whether the game is worth the candle. Is private enforcement of Rule 10b-5 worth preserving, or might we be better off with exclusive public enforcement? This fundamental and neglected question demands attention today more than ever. An academic consensus has now emerged that private enforcement of Rule 10b-5 cannot be defended on compensatory grounds, at least in its most common form (a fraud-on-the-market class action brought against a non-trading issuer). That leaves the oft-cited, but under-theorized, rationale that private enforcement is a necessary supplement to the securities fraud deterrence efforts of the SEC. When this justification is critically examined, however, it proves to be highly debatable. A rich body of law and economics scholarship teaches that bounty hunter enforcement of an overbroad law, like Rule 10b-5, may lead to overdeterrence and stymie governmental efforts to set effective enforcement policy (even assuming away strike suits and the agency costs that attend class action litigation); if private enforcement is nevertheless desirable - a contestable proposition - it is because a world without it might result in even greater deviations from optimal deterrence, due to SEC budgetary constraints, inefficiency and/or capture. By carefully explicating the relative advantages and disadvantages of private Rule 10b-5 enforcement versus exclusive public enforcement, this Article reveals a new and better way to remedy the shortcomings of the Rule 10b-5 class action. It proposes that policymakers adopt an oversight approach to securities litigation reform by, for example, granting the SEC the ability to screen which Rule 10b-5 class actions may be filed, and against whom. By muting the overdeterrence threat of private litigation and placing the SEC back firmly at the helm of Rule 10b-5 enforcement policy, this approach would mitigate the primary disadvantages of private enforcement. Moreover, by preserving a private check on SEC inefficiency and capture and allowing the SEC to continue to supplement its budget with private enforcement resources, it would do so without eliminating the primary advantages of the current system. This approach stands in stark contrast to prior securities litigation reforms, which have responded to the overdeterrence threat posed by Rule 10b-5 class actions by rigidly narrowing the scope of private liability. This Article argues that an oversight approach to securities litigation reform carries distinct advantages over this narrowing approach, and ought to receive serious consideration in the ongoing policy debate.","PeriodicalId":51408,"journal":{"name":"Columbia Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.9,"publicationDate":"2008-02-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.1096864","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68137975","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 55
Safe-Conduct Theory of the Alien Tort Statute, The 外国人侵权法的安全行为理论
IF 2.9 2区 社会学 Pub Date : 2007-02-22 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.687799
Thomas H. Lee
In this Article, Professor Lee introduces a novel explanation of the Alien Tort Statute (ATS) - a founding-era enactment that has achieved modern prominence as a vehicle for international human rights litigation. He demonstrates how the statute was intended to address violations of something called a "safe conduct" - a sovereign promise of safety to aliens from injury to their persons and property. The safe-conduct theory advances a new modern role for the ATS to redress torts committed by private actors - including aliens - with a U.S. sovereign nexus, and not for international law violations committed by anyone anywhere. In developing this contextual account, Professor Lee resolves uncertainty over the constitutional basis for the ATS and shows how, even with sparse conventional sources, the original meaning of an iconic founding-era statute might be recovered.
在这篇文章中,李教授介绍了对《外国人侵权法》(ATS)的一种新的解释。ATS是一项建国时期的立法,作为国际人权诉讼的工具,在现代取得了突出地位。他说明了该法规是如何处理违反所谓“安全行为”的行为的,“安全行为”是对外国人人身和财产不受伤害的主权承诺。安全行为理论为ATS提供了一个新的现代角色,以纠正私人行为者(包括外国人)与美国主权关系所犯的侵权行为,而不是针对任何人在任何地方所犯的违反国际法的行为。在发展这一背景叙述的过程中,李教授解决了ATS宪法基础的不确定性,并展示了如何在缺乏传统来源的情况下,恢复创始时代标志性法规的原始含义。
{"title":"Safe-Conduct Theory of the Alien Tort Statute, The","authors":"Thomas H. Lee","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.687799","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.687799","url":null,"abstract":"In this Article, Professor Lee introduces a novel explanation of the Alien Tort Statute (ATS) - a founding-era enactment that has achieved modern prominence as a vehicle for international human rights litigation. He demonstrates how the statute was intended to address violations of something called a \"safe conduct\" - a sovereign promise of safety to aliens from injury to their persons and property. The safe-conduct theory advances a new modern role for the ATS to redress torts committed by private actors - including aliens - with a U.S. sovereign nexus, and not for international law violations committed by anyone anywhere. In developing this contextual account, Professor Lee resolves uncertainty over the constitutional basis for the ATS and shows how, even with sparse conventional sources, the original meaning of an iconic founding-era statute might be recovered.","PeriodicalId":51408,"journal":{"name":"Columbia Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.9,"publicationDate":"2007-02-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.687799","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67800724","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 11
What Divides Textualists from Purposivists 是什么区分了文本主义者和目的主义者
IF 2.9 2区 社会学 Pub Date : 2006-01-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2849247
J. Manning
Recent scholarship has questioned whether there remains a meaningful distinction between modern textualism and purposivism. Purposivists traditionally argued that because Congress passes statutes to achieve some aim, federal judges should enforce the spirit rather than the letter of the law when the two conflict. Textualists, in contrast, have emphasized that federal judges have a constitutional duty to give effect to the duly enacted text (when clear), and not unenacted evidence of legislative purpose. They have further contended that asking how a reasonable person would understand the text is more objective than searching for a complex, multimember body's purpose.Writing from a textualist perspective, Professor Manning suggests that the conventional grounds for textualism need refinement. Modern textualists acknowledge that statutory language has meaning only in context, and that judges must consider a range of extratextual evidence to ascertain textual meaning. Sophisticated purposivists, moreover, have posited their own "reasonable person" framework to make purposive interpretation more objective. Properly understood, textualism nonetheless remains distinctive because it gives priority to semantic context (evidence about the way a reasonable person uses words) rather than policy context (evidence about the way a reasonable person solves problems). Professor Manning contends that the textualist approach to context is justified because semantic detail alone enables legislators to set meaningful limits on agreed-upon compromises. In contrast, he argues that by authorizing judges to make statutory rules more coherent with their apparent overall purposes, purposivism makes it surpassingly difficult for legislators to define reliable boundary lines for the (often awkward) compromises struck in the legislative process.
最近的学者对现代文本主义和目的主义之间是否存在有意义的区别提出了质疑。传统意义上,目的主义者认为,由于国会通过法规是为了达到某种目的,联邦法官应该在法律与法律冲突时执行法律的精神而不是文字。相反,文本论者则强调,联邦法官负有宪法义务,使正式颁布的文本(在明确的情况下)生效,而不是使具有立法目的的未颁布证据生效。他们进一步争辩说,询问一个理性的人如何理解文本,比寻找一个复杂的、由多个成员组成的机构的目的更客观。从文本主义的角度出发,曼宁教授认为文本主义的传统基础需要改进。现代文本学家承认,法定语言仅在上下文中具有意义,法官必须考虑一系列文本外证据来确定文本意义。此外,成熟的目的论者提出了他们自己的“理性人”框架,使有目的的解释更加客观。正确理解,文本主义仍然是独特的,因为它优先考虑语义上下文(关于一个理性的人使用词语的方式的证据)而不是政策上下文(关于一个理性的人解决问题的方式的证据)。曼宁教授认为,文本主义的上下文方法是合理的,因为语义细节本身就能使立法者对商定的妥协设定有意义的限制。相反,他认为,通过授权法官制定更符合其明显总体目的的法定规则,目的主义使得立法者极其难以为立法过程中达成的妥协(通常是尴尬的)定义可靠的界限。
{"title":"What Divides Textualists from Purposivists","authors":"J. Manning","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2849247","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2849247","url":null,"abstract":"Recent scholarship has questioned whether there remains a meaningful distinction between modern textualism and purposivism. Purposivists traditionally argued that because Congress passes statutes to achieve some aim, federal judges should enforce the spirit rather than the letter of the law when the two conflict. Textualists, in contrast, have emphasized that federal judges have a constitutional duty to give effect to the duly enacted text (when clear), and not unenacted evidence of legislative purpose. They have further contended that asking how a reasonable person would understand the text is more objective than searching for a complex, multimember body's purpose.Writing from a textualist perspective, Professor Manning suggests that the conventional grounds for textualism need refinement. Modern textualists acknowledge that statutory language has meaning only in context, and that judges must consider a range of extratextual evidence to ascertain textual meaning. Sophisticated purposivists, moreover, have posited their own \"reasonable person\" framework to make purposive interpretation more objective. Properly understood, textualism nonetheless remains distinctive because it gives priority to semantic context (evidence about the way a reasonable person uses words) rather than policy context (evidence about the way a reasonable person solves problems). Professor Manning contends that the textualist approach to context is justified because semantic detail alone enables legislators to set meaningful limits on agreed-upon compromises. In contrast, he argues that by authorizing judges to make statutory rules more coherent with their apparent overall purposes, purposivism makes it surpassingly difficult for legislators to define reliable boundary lines for the (often awkward) compromises struck in the legislative process.","PeriodicalId":51408,"journal":{"name":"Columbia Law Review","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":2.9,"publicationDate":"2006-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.2849247","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68386954","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"社会学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 30
期刊
Columbia Law Review
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1