首页 > 最新文献

Social Epistemology最新文献

英文 中文
Expertise in Non-Well-Defined Task Domains: The Case of Reading 非明确任务领域的专业知识:阅读案例
IF 1.7 2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2023-11-14 DOI: 10.1080/02691728.2023.2266690
S. B. Trasmundi, Edward Baggs, Juan Toro, S. Steffensen
{"title":"Expertise in Non-Well-Defined Task Domains: The Case of Reading","authors":"S. B. Trasmundi, Edward Baggs, Juan Toro, S. Steffensen","doi":"10.1080/02691728.2023.2266690","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/02691728.2023.2266690","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":51614,"journal":{"name":"Social Epistemology","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":1.7,"publicationDate":"2023-11-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139277726","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Becoming a Knower: Fabricating Knowing Through Coaction 成为一个知者:通过合作制造知识
2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2023-11-09 DOI: 10.1080/02691728.2023.2266716
Marie-Theres Fester-Seeger
ABSTRACTThis paper takes a step back from considering expertise as a social phenomenon. One should investigate how people become knowers before assigning expertise to a person’s actions. Using a temporal-sensitive systemic ethnography, a case study shows how undergraduate students form a social system out of necessity as they fabricate knowledge around an empty wording like ‘conscious living’. Tracing the engagement with students and tutor to recursive moments of coaction, I argue that, through the subtleties of bodily movements, people incorporate the actions of others as they become knowers. Knowing for a person solidifies as they imbue concepts, terms, facts, etc. with their own understanding. While coaction refers to the interlocking of actions in a specific moment, the fabrication of knowledge resides in temporally distributed moments of coaction where students deliberately incorporate and build on past occurrences in a present moment. In so doing, people cannot be separated from their systemic embedding. Linking coaction with systemic cognition, people fabricate knowledge within wider systemic structures. Within these boundaries, knowers come to fabricate knowledge for themselves and a wider system. Thus, knowing must be seen as an active, embodied, dialogical and multiscalar activity.KEYWORDS: Languagingcoactionsystemic cognitionembodiment AcknowledgmentsThis paper benefited greatly from the comments of two anonymous reviewers. I would also like to thank Stephen Cowley for his very valuable comments and for the insightful conversations about this paper. I also would like to thank the two editors of this special issue, Sarah Bro Trasmundi and Charlie Lassiter, for their patience and kindness and for making this special issue happen. My special thanks go to Charlie Lassiter for his invaluable feedback and help on this paper. A heartfelt thanks go to the research participants who consented to this study. Without them, this paper could not have been written.Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. The written language bias emerges from Linell’s (Citation1982) observation that ‘[o]ur conception of linguistic behavior is biased by a tendency to treat processes, activities, and conditions on them in terms of object-like, static, autonomous and permanent structures, i.e. as if they shared such properties with written characters, words, texts, pictures and images’ (1). Pointing towards the bias of treating ‘natural’ language in terms of its written forms – that is, as ‘thing’-like entities – greatly excludes how human beings bring about language. Consequently, rather than acknowledging the heterogeneous character of language, linguists (and beyond) assign fixed and stable meanings to lexical items, view language as homogeneous systems, and think about language use in terms of acting with stable structures (Linell Citation2019). Hence, traditional linguistics dismiss how people, through gaze, gestur
一个人过去参与特定语言社区的经验使他们能够对特定的发音运动模式作出反应并采取行动。我敢肯定,我们中的许多人都偶然发现过他们过去学生时代的旧课本或文件夹,就像我前几天一样。看着我的旧笔记,我立刻想起了在课堂上与老师和同学交谈和讨论的情景。它带来了过去与他人交往的时刻,现在在我自己的写作中具体化。系统认知(Cowley and vall<s:1> - tourangeau Citation2013)强调了人作为人类认知代理(Giere Citation2004)在更广泛的系统中的作用。考虑到一个人是如何嵌入到系统结构中并产生系统结构的,这种观点呼吁人们注意一个人在系统中的行为(例如,在工作环境或运动队中)。5 .稍后我将详细介绍这一观点。“捏造”一词是在与斯蒂芬·考利就手稿初稿进行的生动讨论中出现的,他正确地看到,被调查的学生并没有展示出专业知识,而是在为自己和他人构建知识。从生物学的角度来看,Maturana使用“双方同意”来描述生物体如何相互作用,因为“它们在相同的物理环境中暴露于相似的感官刺激”(Kravchenko Citation2007, 652)。在这样做的过程中,Maturana强调了直接环境对生物体行为的作用。微尺度包括持续时间从毫秒到十分之一秒的身体动态,微尺度的身体动态追踪可以从十分之一秒到几秒测量的“说话和行为”,最后,宏观尺度使人们能够追踪可以以秒、分等测量的情境社会事件(Thibault Citation2011, 2015-216)。Järviletho (Citation1998)引入了生物-环境系统理论,以抵消将生物与环境明显分开的“两个系统”观点。当喝一杯咖啡时,杯子是属于生物还是环境,Järviletho可视化了生物和环境是如何不可分割的。因此,行为属于生物-环境系统,不能被视为两个系统之间的中介。生物-环境系统是行为的结果。在强调有机体和环境的不可分割性时,他强调“系统的所有部分都是与结果相关的活跃的”(330)——可观察的行为。在这个观点中,按下电梯按钮,例如,不依赖于对感知刺激的反应,因此不能仅仅归因于个人的思维,而是归因于一个人与他的直接环境的接触,并在更广泛的上层建筑文化约束下行动。知道什么时候按下按钮,它做什么和它的功能不仅来自于过去与他人的接触,也来自于一个人的文化嵌入。因此,心理活动不能定位于一个有机体,而必须归因于整个系统。该理论告知系统认知,因为它允许承认非本地约束(例如文化,自传事件等)如何影响人类的认知行为。这种形式的教学建立在建构主义思想的基础上,其前提是“通过解决问题来构建知识”(Blumenfeld等人)。Citation2000, 150)。重点是“现实世界的问题”,学生们会围绕一个特定的主题提出一个驱动问题。学生在小组中学习和发展新想法,并“代表围绕驱动问题的知识”(Blumenfeld等人)。Citation2000)。。这个小组由四个人组成,而宝拉、加比和文森特组成了核心小组。作为第四名成员,安娜只是不定期地参加小组会议。课程一周上两次,第二天是小组作业。这个小组只在课堂上见过面(尽管他们也尝试过在课外见面),在拍摄的7周时间里,整个小组只见过两次面。因此,“缺席”和“不规律”的主题在很大程度上决定了该小组的工作。因为每个人都想单独工作,并且有不同的兴趣,所以这四个人很难组成一个小组。Paula对烹饪感兴趣,Gaby对韩国流行音乐感兴趣,Vincent喜欢制作YouTube视频,Anna喜欢烤面包。他们面临着把这四个主题结合起来的挑战。详情见附录13。这些录像是用教室里的几台摄像机拍摄的。所有的学生都在课堂上一起讨论他们的项目。因此,所有小组讨论的声音重叠,每个小组的谈话,因此,部分难以理解。无法抄写的实例,我标记为((听不懂))。 对于考利和哈维(Citation2016)来说,措辞是“与一个人的社会文化经验相关的感知和解释”的短期事件(58)。他们强调,扬声器不能发出相同的声音,而是发出一种被视为“相同”的声音模式。在这个逻辑中,我们在声音上产生的一切都是一个临时事件。只有当我们对所听到的东西采取现象学的行动时,这些行动才能产生规范效果。请在附录中找到更详细的文字记录。Kendon (Citation2004)区分了两种摊开手的手势:摊开手仰卧(手掌朝上)和摊开手俯卧(手掌朝下)。这些手势在对话中具有语用功能。对于Kendon来说,前者(手掌向上)与否定或打断的语境有关,而后者与服务或提供的语境有关。从目前的情况可以看出,这两个方面都没有在这个协调时刻发生。相反,手势取代了一种认知功能:当学生建立一个项目并为自己创造知识时,它们允许学生将过去的事件在时空上联系在一起。这与传统的语言方法相反,传统的语言方法将手势和其他身体动态降级为副语言线索,因此对语言学来说不是必要的。在采用语言视角的过程中,这种民族志将这些副语言线索视为必不可少的,并且与分析所显示的具有相同的重要性。参与本研究的学生在这门课上获得3%的额外学分,此外,他们的参与还获得了额外的20美元。国家自然科学基金项目(批准号:31571141、31628010)与华南师范大学合作资助。该研究已被美国主办大学的研究合规人类研究计划批准为豁免,该大学进行了数据收集。我的博士研究是由丹麦欧登塞的南丹麦大学语言与传播系资助的。这篇文章的写作是在我作为博士后在勃兰登堡博士后网络工作期间进行的,该网络为我的研究提供了个人资助。作者简介marie - theres Fester-Seeger,欧洲大学(德国法兰克福)博士后研究员。她于2021年获得南丹麦大学语言与传播系博士学位。她的研究兴趣包括分布式语言/语言,多标量时间认知,认知系统观点和语言对话方法。她特别感兴趣的是人类与直接他者的接触如何决定人类的感知、行动和思考。她对人类的生活经验和时间性感兴趣,研究人们如何能够感知和行动不直接存在的东西,以及这如何有助于人类的发展。基于此,她在博士学位期间提出了人类存在的想法。她获得了勃兰登堡博士后网络(Postdoc Network Brandenburg)的个人资助,目前正在研究人类在家庭环境中与数字语音助手的互动。
{"title":"Becoming a Knower: Fabricating Knowing Through Coaction","authors":"Marie-Theres Fester-Seeger","doi":"10.1080/02691728.2023.2266716","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/02691728.2023.2266716","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTThis paper takes a step back from considering expertise as a social phenomenon. One should investigate how people become knowers before assigning expertise to a person’s actions. Using a temporal-sensitive systemic ethnography, a case study shows how undergraduate students form a social system out of necessity as they fabricate knowledge around an empty wording like ‘conscious living’. Tracing the engagement with students and tutor to recursive moments of coaction, I argue that, through the subtleties of bodily movements, people incorporate the actions of others as they become knowers. Knowing for a person solidifies as they imbue concepts, terms, facts, etc. with their own understanding. While coaction refers to the interlocking of actions in a specific moment, the fabrication of knowledge resides in temporally distributed moments of coaction where students deliberately incorporate and build on past occurrences in a present moment. In so doing, people cannot be separated from their systemic embedding. Linking coaction with systemic cognition, people fabricate knowledge within wider systemic structures. Within these boundaries, knowers come to fabricate knowledge for themselves and a wider system. Thus, knowing must be seen as an active, embodied, dialogical and multiscalar activity.KEYWORDS: Languagingcoactionsystemic cognitionembodiment AcknowledgmentsThis paper benefited greatly from the comments of two anonymous reviewers. I would also like to thank Stephen Cowley for his very valuable comments and for the insightful conversations about this paper. I also would like to thank the two editors of this special issue, Sarah Bro Trasmundi and Charlie Lassiter, for their patience and kindness and for making this special issue happen. My special thanks go to Charlie Lassiter for his invaluable feedback and help on this paper. A heartfelt thanks go to the research participants who consented to this study. Without them, this paper could not have been written.Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. The written language bias emerges from Linell’s (Citation1982) observation that ‘[o]ur conception of linguistic behavior is biased by a tendency to treat processes, activities, and conditions on them in terms of object-like, static, autonomous and permanent structures, i.e. as if they shared such properties with written characters, words, texts, pictures and images’ (1). Pointing towards the bias of treating ‘natural’ language in terms of its written forms – that is, as ‘thing’-like entities – greatly excludes how human beings bring about language. Consequently, rather than acknowledging the heterogeneous character of language, linguists (and beyond) assign fixed and stable meanings to lexical items, view language as homogeneous systems, and think about language use in terms of acting with stable structures (Linell Citation2019). Hence, traditional linguistics dismiss how people, through gaze, gestur","PeriodicalId":51614,"journal":{"name":"Social Epistemology","volume":" 5","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135291497","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Designing an Expert-Setting for Interdisciplinary Dialogue: Literary Texts as Boundary Objects 设计跨学科对话的专家设置:文学文本作为边界对象
2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2023-11-07 DOI: 10.1080/02691728.2023.2270552
Karin Kukkonen
While literature is often used as a source of examples and illustrations across disciplines, literary studies tends to be underrepresented in interdisciplinary exchanges. Perhaps the reason lies in a lack of understanding what actually is the expertise of literary studies and how this can be useful in interdisciplinary settings. In this article, I propose to outline the expertise of literary scholars through concepts of 4E cognition and to devise a proposal for how such expertise could successfully shape the epistemic common ground of social cognition of experts in interdisciplinary dialogue. Literature involves metacognition centrally through its language style, the design of the narrative and its links to other texts, and literary scholars have the expertise in formulating exactly how this works – in a non-mimetic way – through the analysis and interpretation of literary texts. This very particular expertise and practice of literary scholars enables literary texts to be proposed as a boundary object in interdisciplinary dialogues through a shared epistemic common ground. For this argument, I build on earlier theoretical work in 4E cognition and predictive processing and my experience running interdisciplinary workshops on that model.
虽然文学经常被用作跨学科例子和插图的来源,但文学研究在跨学科交流中往往代表性不足。也许原因在于缺乏对文学研究专业知识的真正理解,以及它如何在跨学科环境中发挥作用。在本文中,我建议通过4E认知的概念来概述文学学者的专业知识,并就这些专业知识如何在跨学科对话中成功塑造专家社会认知的认识共同点提出建议。文学主要通过语言风格、叙事设计及其与其他文本的联系来涉及元认知,文学学者有专业知识,通过对文学文本的分析和解释,以一种非模仿的方式,准确地阐述元认知是如何起作用的。文学学者的这种特殊的专业知识和实践使得文学文本在跨学科对话中通过共享的认知共同点被提出作为边界对象。对于这个论点,我建立在早期关于4E认知和预测处理的理论工作以及我在该模型上举办跨学科研讨会的经验之上。
{"title":"Designing an Expert-Setting for Interdisciplinary Dialogue: Literary Texts as Boundary Objects","authors":"Karin Kukkonen","doi":"10.1080/02691728.2023.2270552","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/02691728.2023.2270552","url":null,"abstract":"While literature is often used as a source of examples and illustrations across disciplines, literary studies tends to be underrepresented in interdisciplinary exchanges. Perhaps the reason lies in a lack of understanding what actually is the expertise of literary studies and how this can be useful in interdisciplinary settings. In this article, I propose to outline the expertise of literary scholars through concepts of 4E cognition and to devise a proposal for how such expertise could successfully shape the epistemic common ground of social cognition of experts in interdisciplinary dialogue. Literature involves metacognition centrally through its language style, the design of the narrative and its links to other texts, and literary scholars have the expertise in formulating exactly how this works – in a non-mimetic way – through the analysis and interpretation of literary texts. This very particular expertise and practice of literary scholars enables literary texts to be proposed as a boundary object in interdisciplinary dialogues through a shared epistemic common ground. For this argument, I build on earlier theoretical work in 4E cognition and predictive processing and my experience running interdisciplinary workshops on that model.","PeriodicalId":51614,"journal":{"name":"Social Epistemology","volume":"55 10","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135539566","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Censorship Bubbles Vs Hate Bubbles 审查泡沫Vs仇恨泡沫
2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2023-11-06 DOI: 10.1080/02691728.2023.2274324
Wendy Xin
ABSTRACTIn this paper, I argue that considerations of epistemic bubbles can give us reason to defend censorship of hate speech. Although censoring hate speech leads to epistemic bubbles (‘censorship bubbles’), they tend to be less epistemically problematic than epistemic bubbles generated by the circulation of hate speech (‘hate bubbles’). Because hate speech silences its target groups and creates the illusion that the dominant group identities are threatened, hate bubbles are likely more restrictive in structure than censorship bubbles and have a stronger tendency to turn into echo chambers where opposing views are actively discredited. Therefore, I argue that censorship bubbles might be a minor price we ought to pay to avoid hate bubbles. Additionally, my analysis shows that we cannot focus exclusively on the content or the structure of epistemic bubbles, since their content can partly determine their structure, as is in the case of hate bubbles.KEYWORDS: Hate speechcensorshipepistemic bubbles AcknowledgmentsI thank Emanuel Viebahn, Caroline West and James Evans for reading and commenting on this paper.Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. Here Alcoff draws from Lorraine Code Citation1993.2. Here Alcoff draws from Sandra Harding Citation1991.3. Here Alcoff draws from Charles Mills Citation1997.Additional informationNotes on contributorsWendy XinWendy Xin is a PhD candidate in Philosophy at the University of Sydney. Her research interests include environmental ethics, emotions, feminist philosophy and social epistemology.
在本文中,我认为对认知泡沫的考虑可以给我们辩护仇恨言论审查的理由。虽然审查仇恨言论会导致认知泡沫(“审查泡沫”),但它们往往比仇恨言论流通产生的认知泡沫(“仇恨泡沫”)在认知上的问题更少。因为仇恨言论让目标群体噤声,并制造了一种主导群体身份受到威胁的错觉,所以仇恨泡沫在结构上可能比审查泡沫更具限制性,而且更容易变成回音室,在那里,反对意见被积极地抹黑。因此,我认为审查泡沫可能是我们应该付出的一个小代价,以避免仇恨泡沫。此外,我的分析表明,我们不能只关注认知泡沫的内容或结构,因为它们的内容可以部分地决定它们的结构,就像仇恨泡沫的情况一样。感谢Emanuel Viebahn, Caroline West和James Evans对本文的阅读和评论。披露声明作者未报告潜在的利益冲突。这里Alcoff引用了Lorraine Code Citation1993.2。这里Alcoff引用了Sandra Harding的引文。这里Alcoff摘自1997年的Charles Mills引文。本文作者wendy Xin是悉尼大学哲学博士研究生。她的研究兴趣包括环境伦理、情感、女性主义哲学和社会认识论。
{"title":"Censorship Bubbles Vs Hate Bubbles","authors":"Wendy Xin","doi":"10.1080/02691728.2023.2274324","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/02691728.2023.2274324","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTIn this paper, I argue that considerations of epistemic bubbles can give us reason to defend censorship of hate speech. Although censoring hate speech leads to epistemic bubbles (‘censorship bubbles’), they tend to be less epistemically problematic than epistemic bubbles generated by the circulation of hate speech (‘hate bubbles’). Because hate speech silences its target groups and creates the illusion that the dominant group identities are threatened, hate bubbles are likely more restrictive in structure than censorship bubbles and have a stronger tendency to turn into echo chambers where opposing views are actively discredited. Therefore, I argue that censorship bubbles might be a minor price we ought to pay to avoid hate bubbles. Additionally, my analysis shows that we cannot focus exclusively on the content or the structure of epistemic bubbles, since their content can partly determine their structure, as is in the case of hate bubbles.KEYWORDS: Hate speechcensorshipepistemic bubbles AcknowledgmentsI thank Emanuel Viebahn, Caroline West and James Evans for reading and commenting on this paper.Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. Here Alcoff draws from Lorraine Code Citation1993.2. Here Alcoff draws from Sandra Harding Citation1991.3. Here Alcoff draws from Charles Mills Citation1997.Additional informationNotes on contributorsWendy XinWendy Xin is a PhD candidate in Philosophy at the University of Sydney. Her research interests include environmental ethics, emotions, feminist philosophy and social epistemology.","PeriodicalId":51614,"journal":{"name":"Social Epistemology","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135636704","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Cringe 畏缩
2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2023-10-30 DOI: 10.1080/02691728.2023.2268588
Thomas J. Spiegel
ABSTRACTWhile shame and embarrassment have received significant attention in philosophy and psychology, cringe (also sometimes called ‘vicarious embarrassment’ and ‘vicarious shame’) has received little thought. This is surprising as the relatively new genre of cringe comedy has seen a meteoric rise since the early 2000s. In this paper, I aim to offer a novel characterization of cringe as a hostile social emotion which turns out to be closer to disgust and horror than to shame or embarrassment, thus disclosing ‘vicarious shame’ and ‘vicarious embarrassment’ to be misnomers. The closing part offers an explanation as to why cringe and cringe comedy in particular have become recently more relevant: cringe allows one to express hostility and disgust (often at other forms of life) in a nonviolent manner which fits perfectly well within the permissible boundaries of tolerance set up in liberal Western democracies since the second half of the 20th century.KEYWORDS: Cringevicarious embarrassmentvicarious shameemotions Disclosure StatementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. While shame and embarrassment are sometimes treated as different phenomena, the current focus on cringe (Fremdscham) allows us to gloss over these differences.2. For the changing semantics of ‘cringe’ in the age of social media, cf. Gomez-Mejia (Citation2020, 317ff.).3. Hacker (Citation2017) further speaks of ‘other-directed shame’ which seemingly picks out a different kind of shame, i.e. not what is described here as cringe, but a kind where one feels due to the actions of others, not instead of others.4. Paulus et al. (Citation2013) – likely due to their background in psychology – use the term ‘empathetic’ (rather than ‘sympathetic’) here, but this terminology is contentious insofar as empathy is often regarded in philosophy as a capacity of discernment of emotions in others (e.g. Edith Stein’s original sense of Einfühlung). Empathy then does not necessarily sharing an emotion with someone (psychologists Nadler, Dvash, and Shamay-Tsoory Citation2015 commit the same terminological mix-up). Hence, what these authors have in mind is better described as ‘sympathetic’.5. In this way cringe (vicarious embarrassment) is different from vicarious anger. In vicarious anger, I am really just angry on behalf of someone else.6. Cf. also Montes Sánchez and Salice (Citation2017) who offer an exhaustive argument as to why Fremdscham is to be delineated from shame simpliciter.7. In an excellent paper, Mayer et al. (Citation2021) are the only ones to consider the role of laughter in cringing. They suggest that laughter likely only occurs in cringing at someone if the cringer is not strongly committed to the social norms being broken. While this may sometimes be the case, I would contend that the point of cringing and cringe comedy often is that one is supposed to laugh at something even if someone finds the norm violation in question offensive; and whether or not th
摘要羞耻和尴尬在哲学和心理学上受到了极大的关注,而畏缩(有时也被称为“替代性尴尬”和“替代性羞耻”)却很少受到关注。这是令人惊讶的,因为自21世纪初以来,相对较新的尴尬喜剧类型迅速崛起。在本文中,我的目标是提供一种新的特征,将畏缩作为一种敌对的社会情绪,结果证明它更接近于厌恶和恐惧,而不是羞耻或尴尬,从而揭示“替代羞耻”和“替代尴尬”是用词不当。结尾处解释了为什么畏缩,尤其是畏缩喜剧最近变得更有意义:畏缩允许一个人以非暴力的方式表达敌意和厌恶(通常是对其他形式的生活),这完全符合自20世纪下半叶以来自由西方民主国家所允许的宽容界限。关键词:尴尬尴尬羞愧情绪披露声明作者未发现潜在的利益冲突。虽然羞耻和尴尬有时被视为不同的现象,但目前对畏缩(fredscham)的关注使我们能够掩盖这些差异。关于社交媒体时代“cringe”语义的变化,参见Gomez-Mejia (Citation2020, 317ff.)。Hacker (Citation2017)进一步谈到了“他人导向的羞耻”,它似乎选择了一种不同的羞耻,即不是这里所描述的畏缩,而是一种由于他人的行为而感到的羞耻,而不是代替他人。Paulus等人(Citation2013)——可能是由于他们的心理学背景——在这里使用了“共情”一词(而不是“同情”),但这个术语是有争议的,因为在哲学中,共情通常被认为是一种识别他人情绪的能力(例如Edith Stein最初的einfhlung)。同理心并不一定与他人分享情感(心理学家Nadler、Dvash和Shamay-Tsoory Citation2015也犯了同样的术语混淆)。因此,这些作者的想法被更好地描述为“同情”。这样看来,畏缩(替代的尴尬)和替代的愤怒是不同的。在代怒中,我实际上只是代表别人生气。参见Montes Sánchez和Salice (Citation2017),他们提供了一个详尽的论点,说明为什么fredscham要从羞耻感中区分出来。在一篇优秀的论文中,Mayer等人(Citation2021)是唯一考虑笑声在畏缩中的作用的人。他们认为,笑可能只会发生在对某人卑躬屈膝时,如果卑躬屈膝者没有强烈地致力于打破社会规范。虽然有时可能是这种情况,但我认为,畏缩和畏缩喜剧的重点往往是,人们应该嘲笑某些东西,即使有人觉得违反规范的行为令人反感;畏缩者能否克服他们最初的下意识反应是性格和幽默感的标志。有些人可能认为,社会敌意不足以作为区分畏缩与羞耻或尴尬的标准。感谢一位匿名推荐人提醒我注意这一点。另外唯一一份更接近恐怖的出版物是《海-克努森》(citation, 2018, 14页)。我要感谢兰伯特·维辛为我指明了这个方向。下面的评论并不意味着在20世纪之前不存在或从来没有相关的畏缩。我只是想说,畏缩作为一种情感的相关性正在增长,因为这些相对较新的社会结构越来越不允许在任何社会场合使用身体暴力。此外,对一些人来说,认为自20世纪下半叶以来,生命形式已经激增的说法可能会引起争议。这是由于城市化、好莱坞的全球胜利、不同语言的消亡,甚至是福山所谓的“历史的终结”等因素造成的。这些过程表明全球均质化而不是分层。考虑到这样的发展,从全球范围来看,生命形式是在增加还是在减少,特别是考虑到过去一百年来人口的爆炸式增长,确实很难得出结论。因此,自20世纪下半叶以来,这里关于生活形式分层的建议仅限于自由西方民主国家。在这种有限的背景下,我们可以考虑产生和源于生活形式分层的巨大社会变化。
{"title":"Cringe","authors":"Thomas J. Spiegel","doi":"10.1080/02691728.2023.2268588","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/02691728.2023.2268588","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTWhile shame and embarrassment have received significant attention in philosophy and psychology, cringe (also sometimes called ‘vicarious embarrassment’ and ‘vicarious shame’) has received little thought. This is surprising as the relatively new genre of cringe comedy has seen a meteoric rise since the early 2000s. In this paper, I aim to offer a novel characterization of cringe as a hostile social emotion which turns out to be closer to disgust and horror than to shame or embarrassment, thus disclosing ‘vicarious shame’ and ‘vicarious embarrassment’ to be misnomers. The closing part offers an explanation as to why cringe and cringe comedy in particular have become recently more relevant: cringe allows one to express hostility and disgust (often at other forms of life) in a nonviolent manner which fits perfectly well within the permissible boundaries of tolerance set up in liberal Western democracies since the second half of the 20th century.KEYWORDS: Cringevicarious embarrassmentvicarious shameemotions Disclosure StatementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. While shame and embarrassment are sometimes treated as different phenomena, the current focus on cringe (Fremdscham) allows us to gloss over these differences.2. For the changing semantics of ‘cringe’ in the age of social media, cf. Gomez-Mejia (Citation2020, 317ff.).3. Hacker (Citation2017) further speaks of ‘other-directed shame’ which seemingly picks out a different kind of shame, i.e. not what is described here as cringe, but a kind where one feels due to the actions of others, not instead of others.4. Paulus et al. (Citation2013) – likely due to their background in psychology – use the term ‘empathetic’ (rather than ‘sympathetic’) here, but this terminology is contentious insofar as empathy is often regarded in philosophy as a capacity of discernment of emotions in others (e.g. Edith Stein’s original sense of Einfühlung). Empathy then does not necessarily sharing an emotion with someone (psychologists Nadler, Dvash, and Shamay-Tsoory Citation2015 commit the same terminological mix-up). Hence, what these authors have in mind is better described as ‘sympathetic’.5. In this way cringe (vicarious embarrassment) is different from vicarious anger. In vicarious anger, I am really just angry on behalf of someone else.6. Cf. also Montes Sánchez and Salice (Citation2017) who offer an exhaustive argument as to why Fremdscham is to be delineated from shame simpliciter.7. In an excellent paper, Mayer et al. (Citation2021) are the only ones to consider the role of laughter in cringing. They suggest that laughter likely only occurs in cringing at someone if the cringer is not strongly committed to the social norms being broken. While this may sometimes be the case, I would contend that the point of cringing and cringe comedy often is that one is supposed to laugh at something even if someone finds the norm violation in question offensive; and whether or not th","PeriodicalId":51614,"journal":{"name":"Social Epistemology","volume":"360 12","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"136069729","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Wrong of Bullshit 废话的错误
2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2023-10-27 DOI: 10.1080/02691728.2023.2267501
Thorian R. Harris
{"title":"The Wrong of Bullshit","authors":"Thorian R. Harris","doi":"10.1080/02691728.2023.2267501","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/02691728.2023.2267501","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":51614,"journal":{"name":"Social Epistemology","volume":"136 3-4","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"136317578","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Introduction to the Special Issue: “Expertise, Semiotics and Interactivity” 特刊简介:“专业知识、符号学与互动”
2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2023-10-13 DOI: 10.1080/02691728.2023.2263411
Charles Lassiter, Sarah Bro Trasmundi
ABSTRACTIn this article, we offer an overview of the philosophical and psychological literatures on expertise. Work so far has failed to engage with recent work in embodied and encultured cognition--in particular the notions of interactivity and semiosis. We suggest how bringing these concepts on board reveals new areas of research concerning the philosophy and psychology of expertise. We conclude with a brief synopsis of each paper.KEYWORDS: Expertiseinteractivitysemiotics Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. These are keywords from abstracts that occur together in the dataset at least 25 times and clustered together based on their frequency of co-occurrence as well as the documents in which they co-occur.2. Apologies to Hilary Putnam.Additional informationNotes on contributorsCharles LassiterCharles Lassiter is Associate Professor of Philosophy at Gonzaga University. His research focuses on the epistemology and metaphysics of mind of encultured cognition.Sarah Bro TrasmundiSarah Bro Trasmundi is Associate Professor of Cognitive Ethnography at the University of Southern Denmark and Researcher at Oslo University in the research group ‘Literature, Cognition and Emotions’. She focuses on the intersection between cognition, imagination, and language in domains such as literature, interaction, reading and education.
在本文中,我们提供了一个概述的哲学和心理学文献的专业知识。到目前为止,这项工作未能与最近在具体化和文化认知方面的研究相结合——特别是互动性和符号学的概念。我们建议如何将这些概念引入董事会,揭示有关专业知识的哲学和心理学的新研究领域。最后,我们对每篇论文都作了简要介绍。关键词:专家;互动性;符号学披露声明作者未报告潜在的利益冲突。这些关键词来自于在数据集中至少出现25次的摘要,并根据它们共同出现的频率以及它们共同出现的文档聚集在一起。向希拉里·普特南道歉。作者简介:charles Lassiter是冈萨加大学哲学副教授。他的研究重点是文化认知的认识论和心灵形而上学。Sarah Bro Trasmundi是南丹麦大学认知人种学副教授,也是奥斯陆大学“文学、认知和情感”研究小组的研究员。她专注于认知、想象和语言在文学、互动、阅读和教育等领域的交叉。
{"title":"Introduction to the Special Issue: “Expertise, Semiotics and Interactivity”","authors":"Charles Lassiter, Sarah Bro Trasmundi","doi":"10.1080/02691728.2023.2263411","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/02691728.2023.2263411","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTIn this article, we offer an overview of the philosophical and psychological literatures on expertise. Work so far has failed to engage with recent work in embodied and encultured cognition--in particular the notions of interactivity and semiosis. We suggest how bringing these concepts on board reveals new areas of research concerning the philosophy and psychology of expertise. We conclude with a brief synopsis of each paper.KEYWORDS: Expertiseinteractivitysemiotics Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. These are keywords from abstracts that occur together in the dataset at least 25 times and clustered together based on their frequency of co-occurrence as well as the documents in which they co-occur.2. Apologies to Hilary Putnam.Additional informationNotes on contributorsCharles LassiterCharles Lassiter is Associate Professor of Philosophy at Gonzaga University. His research focuses on the epistemology and metaphysics of mind of encultured cognition.Sarah Bro TrasmundiSarah Bro Trasmundi is Associate Professor of Cognitive Ethnography at the University of Southern Denmark and Researcher at Oslo University in the research group ‘Literature, Cognition and Emotions’. She focuses on the intersection between cognition, imagination, and language in domains such as literature, interaction, reading and education.","PeriodicalId":51614,"journal":{"name":"Social Epistemology","volume":"32 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135853501","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Reading the Signs: From Dyadic to Triadic Views for Identifying Experts 解读迹象:识别专家从二元观点到三元观点
2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2023-10-09 DOI: 10.1080/02691728.2023.2263423
Charles Lassiter
ABSTRACTA naturalistic approach to expert-identification begins by asking, ‘how do novices pick out putative experts?’ Alvin Goldman and Elizabeth Anderson, representing a fairly common approach, consider agents’ psychological biases as well as social situatedness. As good as this is, culture’s role in shaping cognitive mechanisms is neglected. An explanatory framework that works well to accommodate culturally-sensitive mechanisms is Peircean semiotics. His triadic approach holds that signs signify objects to interpreters. Applying the triadic model to expert-identification: novices interpret signs of expertise as pointing to particular experts. The main advantage of the framework is that it is significantly more nuanced than the Goldman-Anderson model in describing how agents identify experts. It explicitly accommodates cultural and agential differences in expert-identification. It also explicitly admits the possibility of rational disagreement in assessment of evidence for expertise. But these advantages come at a cost. Namely, it’s difficult in theory – as well as practice – to make one’s way into the semiotic system of someone from another culture to help guide them away from fraudulent experts. Even so, it’s a trade-off worth making since it organizes relevant details for expert-identification, which is a first step in sketching a better normative theory.KEYWORDS: Expert identificationcultural psychologyC.S. Peircesemioticsrecognition problem Disclosure StatementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. Examples of untrustworthy experts include sham epistemic authorities (Lassiter Citation2019) and epistemic trespassers (Ballantyne Citation2019).2. What makes an expert an expert isn’t necessarily the same as how novices identify experts. For instance, an excellent track-record could make A an expert in topic T, but there’s nothing about track-records in Anderson’s to-do list.3. These aren’t entailed by inside-out social epistemology, but they do fit naturally with the approach. Here is a brief sketch of how. Objectivism about Justification prohibits facts about justification from being grounded in community needs and interests, which (defeasibly) suggests that the justificatory facts are grounded in individuals. Non-natural Meaning is typically coupled with a story about discerning that meaning, which is usually conceptualized as an individual process. Finally, the sciences appealed to trend towards the individualist end of the spectrum, e.g. cognitive and social psychology. Again, none of these is entailed by an inside-out epistemology, but one can find these claims manifested in the work of Goldman and Anderson, as well as Martini (Citation2014).4. There are many ways to refine this position. I’m sticking with Boghossian’s formulation since it seems to capture what is common to other iterations of the idea. See Carter and McKenna (Citation2021) for an overview5. Another option is to seriously overhaul Methodol
作者简介:charles Lassiter,冈萨加大学哲学副教授。他的研究主要集中在形而上学和认识论的问题在思想和文化的交集。
{"title":"Reading the Signs: From Dyadic to Triadic Views for Identifying Experts","authors":"Charles Lassiter","doi":"10.1080/02691728.2023.2263423","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/02691728.2023.2263423","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTA naturalistic approach to expert-identification begins by asking, ‘how do novices pick out putative experts?’ Alvin Goldman and Elizabeth Anderson, representing a fairly common approach, consider agents’ psychological biases as well as social situatedness. As good as this is, culture’s role in shaping cognitive mechanisms is neglected. An explanatory framework that works well to accommodate culturally-sensitive mechanisms is Peircean semiotics. His triadic approach holds that signs signify objects to interpreters. Applying the triadic model to expert-identification: novices interpret signs of expertise as pointing to particular experts. The main advantage of the framework is that it is significantly more nuanced than the Goldman-Anderson model in describing how agents identify experts. It explicitly accommodates cultural and agential differences in expert-identification. It also explicitly admits the possibility of rational disagreement in assessment of evidence for expertise. But these advantages come at a cost. Namely, it’s difficult in theory – as well as practice – to make one’s way into the semiotic system of someone from another culture to help guide them away from fraudulent experts. Even so, it’s a trade-off worth making since it organizes relevant details for expert-identification, which is a first step in sketching a better normative theory.KEYWORDS: Expert identificationcultural psychologyC.S. Peircesemioticsrecognition problem Disclosure StatementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. Examples of untrustworthy experts include sham epistemic authorities (Lassiter Citation2019) and epistemic trespassers (Ballantyne Citation2019).2. What makes an expert an expert isn’t necessarily the same as how novices identify experts. For instance, an excellent track-record could make A an expert in topic T, but there’s nothing about track-records in Anderson’s to-do list.3. These aren’t entailed by inside-out social epistemology, but they do fit naturally with the approach. Here is a brief sketch of how. Objectivism about Justification prohibits facts about justification from being grounded in community needs and interests, which (defeasibly) suggests that the justificatory facts are grounded in individuals. Non-natural Meaning is typically coupled with a story about discerning that meaning, which is usually conceptualized as an individual process. Finally, the sciences appealed to trend towards the individualist end of the spectrum, e.g. cognitive and social psychology. Again, none of these is entailed by an inside-out epistemology, but one can find these claims manifested in the work of Goldman and Anderson, as well as Martini (Citation2014).4. There are many ways to refine this position. I’m sticking with Boghossian’s formulation since it seems to capture what is common to other iterations of the idea. See Carter and McKenna (Citation2021) for an overview5. Another option is to seriously overhaul Methodol","PeriodicalId":51614,"journal":{"name":"Social Epistemology","volume":"2016 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135094769","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Apology for an Average Believer: Wagered Belief and Information Environments 为普通信徒道歉:下注信仰与信息环境
2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2023-10-09 DOI: 10.1080/02691728.2023.2263408
Richard Kenneth Atkins
ABSTRACTSome persons who believe provably false claims – such as that there were significant voter irregularities in the 2020 election – may nevertheless be evidentially rational for holding their false beliefs. I consider a person I call our average believer. In her daily life, she incidentally gathers evidence favoring the hypothesis that there were significant voter irregularities, but she does not investigate the matter. Her information environment, moreover, is such that it accidentally (through no fault of her own) excludes counterevidence to the thesis that there were such irregularities and intensifies the flow of information that there were irregularities. As a consequence, she becomes convinced that there were significant voting irregularities in the 2020 U.S. election. I argue that while she is not zetetically rational, for she does not investigate the matter, she is evidentially rational in that she apportions her belief to the evidence. While she has no right to the Cliffordian, or assertoric, belief that there were such irregularities, she is not epistemically blameworthy for having the wagered belief it is true.KEYWORDS: Beliefconvictionrationalityevidence AcknowledgmentsAn earlier version of this essay was delivered at the 2022 Society for the Advancement of American Philosophy conference. I am indebted to the attendees for their questions and comments. Junhee Han assisted with research for this article and proofread an earlier version, for which I am grateful. I thank two anonymous reviewers for their comments, which have helped improve this essay.Disclosure StatementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. After writing this essay, I discovered that Endre Begby (Citation2021) also discusses information environments; I haven’t the space here to examine how well our accounts align.Additional informationNotes on contributorsRichard Kenneth AtkinsRichard Kenneth Atkins is Associate Professor of Philosophy at Boston College. He is author of Peirce on Inference (Oxford 2023), Charles S. Peirce’s Phenomenology (Oxford 2018), Peirce and the Conduct of Life (Cambridge 2016), and Puzzled?! (Hackett 2015). His articles have appeared in Synthese, Journal of the American Philosophical Association, European Journal of Philosophy, and British Journal for the History of Philosophy, among other venues.
【摘要】有些人相信可以证明是错误的主张——比如2020年大选中存在重大的选民违规行为——然而,持有他们的错误信念可能是明显合理的。我考虑一个我称之为普通信徒的人。在日常生活中,她偶尔会收集一些证据,证明存在重大的选举舞弊假设,但她不会调查此事。此外,她的信息环境是这样的,它偶然地(不是她自己的过错)排除了对存在这种违规行为的论点的反证,并加剧了存在违规行为的信息流动。因此,她确信在2020年美国大选中存在严重的投票违规行为。我认为,虽然她不是探究理性的,因为她没有调查这件事,但她显然是理性的,因为她把自己的信念分配给了证据。虽然她没有权利以克利福德式或武断的方式相信存在这样的违规行为,但她在认识论上也不应该因为坚信这是真的而受到指责。本文的早期版本已在2022年美国哲学进步学会会议上发表。我非常感谢与会者提出的问题和意见。韩俊熙(Junhee Han)协助本文的研究工作,并对早期版本进行了校对,对此我表示感谢。我感谢两位匿名评论者的评论,他们的评论帮助我改进了这篇文章。披露声明作者未报告潜在的利益冲突。在写完这篇文章后,我发现Endre Begby (Citation2021)也讨论了信息环境;我在这里没有篇幅来检查我们的账目是否相符。作者简介:理查德·肯尼斯·阿特金斯理查德·肯尼斯·阿特金斯是波士顿学院哲学副教授。他著有《皮尔斯论推理》(牛津大学2023年版)、《查尔斯·s·皮尔斯现象学》(牛津大学2018年版)、《皮尔斯与生活行为》(剑桥大学2016年版)和《困惑?!》(哈科特2015)。他的文章曾发表在《综合》、《美国哲学协会杂志》、《欧洲哲学杂志》和《英国哲学史杂志》等刊物上。
{"title":"Apology for an Average Believer: Wagered Belief and Information Environments","authors":"Richard Kenneth Atkins","doi":"10.1080/02691728.2023.2263408","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/02691728.2023.2263408","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTSome persons who believe provably false claims – such as that there were significant voter irregularities in the 2020 election – may nevertheless be evidentially rational for holding their false beliefs. I consider a person I call our average believer. In her daily life, she incidentally gathers evidence favoring the hypothesis that there were significant voter irregularities, but she does not investigate the matter. Her information environment, moreover, is such that it accidentally (through no fault of her own) excludes counterevidence to the thesis that there were such irregularities and intensifies the flow of information that there were irregularities. As a consequence, she becomes convinced that there were significant voting irregularities in the 2020 U.S. election. I argue that while she is not zetetically rational, for she does not investigate the matter, she is evidentially rational in that she apportions her belief to the evidence. While she has no right to the Cliffordian, or assertoric, belief that there were such irregularities, she is not epistemically blameworthy for having the wagered belief it is true.KEYWORDS: Beliefconvictionrationalityevidence AcknowledgmentsAn earlier version of this essay was delivered at the 2022 Society for the Advancement of American Philosophy conference. I am indebted to the attendees for their questions and comments. Junhee Han assisted with research for this article and proofread an earlier version, for which I am grateful. I thank two anonymous reviewers for their comments, which have helped improve this essay.Disclosure StatementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. After writing this essay, I discovered that Endre Begby (Citation2021) also discusses information environments; I haven’t the space here to examine how well our accounts align.Additional informationNotes on contributorsRichard Kenneth AtkinsRichard Kenneth Atkins is Associate Professor of Philosophy at Boston College. He is author of Peirce on Inference (Oxford 2023), Charles S. Peirce’s Phenomenology (Oxford 2018), Peirce and the Conduct of Life (Cambridge 2016), and Puzzled?! (Hackett 2015). His articles have appeared in Synthese, Journal of the American Philosophical Association, European Journal of Philosophy, and British Journal for the History of Philosophy, among other venues.","PeriodicalId":51614,"journal":{"name":"Social Epistemology","volume":"23 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135094120","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Enacting Practices: Perception, Expertise and Enlanguaged Affordances 制定实践:感知、专业知识和语言支持
2区 哲学 Q1 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2023-09-26 DOI: 10.1080/02691728.2023.2261397
Rasmus Gahrn-Andersen
ABSTRACTThe paper thematizes basic content-free cognition in human social practices. It explores the enlanguaged dimension of skilled practical doings and expertise by taking the minimal case of concept-based perception as its starting point. Having made a case for considering such activity as free of mental content, I argue in favor of the abolishment of the distinction between truth-telling and social consensus, thus questioning the assumption held by proponents of Radical Enactivism, namely that truth and accuracy conditions are restricted to content-involving activity. Instead, I claim, even content-free practical activity can be evaluated on the basis of accuracy conditions which ultimately tie with agents’ practical understandings and the normative aspects of the practice. With this as my backdrop, I explore how expertise arises in the interplay of enlanguaged affordances, concept-involving perception and the normative accuracy conditions that constrain a particular practice.KEYWORDS: Expertisecontent-free cognitionEnactivismpractices Disclosure StatementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. Concrete concepts such as ‘cat’, ‘house’ and ‘cucumber’ differ fundamentally from abstract concepts such as ‘freedom’, ‘language’, ‘human rights’, ‘beauty’, ‘politics’, etc. which are all devoid of concrete sensory referents (cf. Paivio Citation1986).2. The fact that Heidegger’s work resonates with anti-representationalist positions is well-known (see, Clark and Toribio Citation1994, 406).3. Indeed, there are also non-basic as-structures and this relates to the distinction between the pre-predicative and predicative. For as Engelland (Citation2020) argues, ‘The statement, “There’s a bird in the store!” makes explicit the part-whole relation resident in the experience of bird and of store. Predication (the apophantic is of S is p) remains founded on pre-predicative explication (the hermeneutic as of taking S as p)’ (10) Relatedly, Heidegger points out that ‘the “as” does not first show up in the statement, but is only first stated, which is possible only because it is there as something to be stated’ (Heidegger Citation2010, 145). So, a statement such as ‘I see this thing as a hammer’ contains to the very least as-structures on two levels: first, there is the pre-predicative, hermeneutic experience of the thing as a hammer which motivates the statement in the first place and, then, the thematization of this ‘as’ in the statement. In fact, we could go even further and argue that in the context of the statement, ‘this thing’ is taken as or understood as a Subject while ‘a hammer’ is taken as a predicate. This suggests that there are different as-structures in play whenever we are articulating statements based on our experiencing of things as somethings.4. A simulator is defined as: ‘the imitative representation of the functioning of one system or process by means of the functioning of another’ (https://www.merriam-webster.
摘要本文对人类社会实践中基本的无内容认知进行了主题化研究。它以基于概念的最小感知为出发点,探索熟练实践行为和专业知识的语言维度。在论证了这类活动不包含心理内容之后,我主张废除讲真话和社会共识之间的区别,从而质疑激进激进主义支持者所持的假设,即真理和准确性条件仅限于涉及内容的活动。相反,我主张,即使是无内容的实践活动也可以根据准确性条件进行评估,这些条件最终与行动者的实践理解和实践的规范方面联系在一起。以此为背景,我将探讨专业知识是如何在语言支持、概念感知和限制特定实践的规范准确性条件的相互作用中产生的。关键词:专家无内容认知行为实践披露声明作者未报告潜在的利益冲突。诸如“猫”、“房子”和“黄瓜”等具体概念与诸如“自由”、“语言”、“人权”、“美”、“政治”等抽象概念有着根本的区别,这些概念都缺乏具体的感官所指物(参见Paivio Citation1986)。海德格尔的作品与反表征主义立场产生共鸣的事实是众所周知的(见Clark and Toribio citation1994,406)。事实上,也有非基本as结构,这与前置谓语和谓语之间的区别有关。正如Engelland (Citation2020)所说,“这种说法,‘商店里有一只鸟!明确了驻留在鸟类和储存经验中的部分-整体关系。谓词(S is p的象形结构)仍然建立在前谓词解释(将S作为p的解释学结构)的基础上(10)。与此相关,海德格尔指出,“‘as’并不首先出现在陈述中,而只是首先被陈述,这是可能的,只是因为它作为某种东西存在于那里。”(海德格尔引文2010,145)。所以,像"我认为这个东西是一把锤子"这样的陈述至少包含了两个层面上的作为结构:首先,作为锤子的东西的先行谓词,解释学经验首先激发了这个陈述,然后,这个"作为"在陈述中的主题化。事实上,我们还可以进一步说,在这句陈述中,"这东西"可认作或理解为主词,而"锤子"可认作谓词。这表明,当我们基于对事物作为事物的经验来表达陈述时,就会有不同的作为结构在起作用。模拟器被定义为:“通过另一个系统或过程的功能来模拟一个系统或过程的功能”(https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/simulation)。虽然在当前的背景下,对“表现”的呼吁可能会产生误导,但我更喜欢“表现”这个词。代替和加强实际工作实践的专业训练实践(如飞行模拟、医疗模拟、战争模拟等)都是实践模拟器的例子。不用说,这并不意味着销售人员实际上是在撒谎。事实上,顾客的怀疑可能完全没有根据,仅仅是由于他们对汽车缺乏了解,过去购买二手车的不良经历或二手车销售人员的普遍负面声誉所致。参见Gahrn-Andersen (Citation2021b)的一个例子,说明专业知识可能需要对与非专家不同的as结构进行解释。例如,公用事业公司的泄漏检测人员将街道上的雪融化与供暖管道泄漏联系起来,从而使他在概念上将雪融化视为“可能的泄漏”。所以,虽然大多数人只会看到一片融化的雪,但专业人士由于他的专业知识而看到了泄漏。本研究得到了Velux基金会[Grant 38917]的支持。作者简介rasmus Gahrn-Andersen,南丹麦大学文化与语言系副教授。他目前正在从跨学科的角度研究人类社会实践活动。更具体地说,他探讨了涉及感知的概念和非概念、基本和分布式认知、社会组织、人类技术纠缠以及语言能力和技能如何使人类的实际行为成为可能等现象。
{"title":"Enacting Practices: Perception, Expertise and Enlanguaged Affordances","authors":"Rasmus Gahrn-Andersen","doi":"10.1080/02691728.2023.2261397","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/02691728.2023.2261397","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTThe paper thematizes basic content-free cognition in human social practices. It explores the enlanguaged dimension of skilled practical doings and expertise by taking the minimal case of concept-based perception as its starting point. Having made a case for considering such activity as free of mental content, I argue in favor of the abolishment of the distinction between truth-telling and social consensus, thus questioning the assumption held by proponents of Radical Enactivism, namely that truth and accuracy conditions are restricted to content-involving activity. Instead, I claim, even content-free practical activity can be evaluated on the basis of accuracy conditions which ultimately tie with agents’ practical understandings and the normative aspects of the practice. With this as my backdrop, I explore how expertise arises in the interplay of enlanguaged affordances, concept-involving perception and the normative accuracy conditions that constrain a particular practice.KEYWORDS: Expertisecontent-free cognitionEnactivismpractices Disclosure StatementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. Concrete concepts such as ‘cat’, ‘house’ and ‘cucumber’ differ fundamentally from abstract concepts such as ‘freedom’, ‘language’, ‘human rights’, ‘beauty’, ‘politics’, etc. which are all devoid of concrete sensory referents (cf. Paivio Citation1986).2. The fact that Heidegger’s work resonates with anti-representationalist positions is well-known (see, Clark and Toribio Citation1994, 406).3. Indeed, there are also non-basic as-structures and this relates to the distinction between the pre-predicative and predicative. For as Engelland (Citation2020) argues, ‘The statement, “There’s a bird in the store!” makes explicit the part-whole relation resident in the experience of bird and of store. Predication (the apophantic is of S is p) remains founded on pre-predicative explication (the hermeneutic as of taking S as p)’ (10) Relatedly, Heidegger points out that ‘the “as” does not first show up in the statement, but is only first stated, which is possible only because it is there as something to be stated’ (Heidegger Citation2010, 145). So, a statement such as ‘I see this thing as a hammer’ contains to the very least as-structures on two levels: first, there is the pre-predicative, hermeneutic experience of the thing as a hammer which motivates the statement in the first place and, then, the thematization of this ‘as’ in the statement. In fact, we could go even further and argue that in the context of the statement, ‘this thing’ is taken as or understood as a Subject while ‘a hammer’ is taken as a predicate. This suggests that there are different as-structures in play whenever we are articulating statements based on our experiencing of things as somethings.4. A simulator is defined as: ‘the imitative representation of the functioning of one system or process by means of the functioning of another’ (https://www.merriam-webster.","PeriodicalId":51614,"journal":{"name":"Social Epistemology","volume":"94 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-09-26","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135718787","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Social Epistemology
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1