首页 > 最新文献

William and Mary law review最新文献

英文 中文
Natural Resources and Natural Law Part I: Prior Appropriation 自然资源与自然法第一部分:优先拨款
Pub Date : 2018-02-15 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.3124428
R. Adler
In recent years there has been a resurgence of civil disobedience over public land policy in the West, sometimes characterized by armed confrontations between ranchers and federal officials. This trend reflects renewed assertions that applicable positive law violates the natural rights (sometimes of purportedly divine origin) of ranchers and other land users, particularly under the prior appropriation doctrine and grounded in Lockean theories of property. At the same time, Native Americans and environmental activists on the opposite side of the political-environmental spectrum have also relied on civil disobedience to assert natural rights to a healthy environment, based on public trust and other principles. This article explores the legitimacy of natural law assertions that prior appropriation justifies private property rights in federal grazing resources. A companion article will evaluate the legitimacy of public trust and related assertions of natural law to support environmental protection.
近年来,西方对公共土地政策的公民抗命现象死灰复燃,有时表现为牧场主和联邦官员之间的武装对抗。这一趋势反映了新的断言,即适用的实在法侵犯了牧场主和其他土地使用者的自然权利(有时据称是神圣起源),特别是根据先前的侵占原则,并以洛克财产理论为基础。与此同时,美国原住民和政治环境光谱另一边的环境活动家也依靠公民抗命,基于公众信任和其他原则,维护健康环境的自然权利。本文探讨了自然法主张的合法性,即事先拨款证明了联邦放牧资源的私有产权是正当的。一篇配套文章将评估公众信任的合法性以及支持环境保护的自然法的相关主张。
{"title":"Natural Resources and Natural Law Part I: Prior Appropriation","authors":"R. Adler","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.3124428","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.3124428","url":null,"abstract":"In recent years there has been a resurgence of civil disobedience over public land policy in the West, sometimes characterized by armed confrontations between ranchers and federal officials. This trend reflects renewed assertions that applicable positive law violates the natural rights (sometimes of purportedly divine origin) of ranchers and other land users, particularly under the prior appropriation doctrine and grounded in Lockean theories of property. At the same time, Native Americans and environmental activists on the opposite side of the political-environmental spectrum have also relied on civil disobedience to assert natural rights to a healthy environment, based on public trust and other principles. This article explores the legitimacy of natural law assertions that prior appropriation justifies private property rights in federal grazing resources. A companion article will evaluate the legitimacy of public trust and related assertions of natural law to support environmental protection.","PeriodicalId":75324,"journal":{"name":"William and Mary law review","volume":"60 1","pages":"739"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-02-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48087019","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Can Judges Be Uncivilly Obedient 法官可以不文明地服从吗
Pub Date : 2018-02-13 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.3123167
Brannon P. Denning
In a recent article, Jessica Bulman-Pozen and David Pozen identified “uncivil obedience” as a tactic for protesting laws or regulations, not by violating the law, as with civil disobedience, but rather by scrupulous attendance to it. They noted that it is a tactic available to private and public actors alike, but were doubtful that a judicial variety existed because even hyper-formalist legal opinions, they argued, would be unlikely to be perceived as provocative as scrupulous adherence to the letter of the law might be when observed in non-judicial actors. In this article, I argue that judicial uncivil obedience is possible, discuss examples of lower court uncivil obedience to U.S. Supreme Court decisions, speculate why uncivil obedience might be a particularly attractive form of dissent by inferior courts in a hierarchical judicial system, and argue that my examples satisfy Bulman-Pozen and Pozen’s criteria. In addition, I argue that the constraints on uncivil obedience they identify, which can limit the opportunity for its exercise, have analogues that likewise limit the ability of judges to engage in uncivil obedience.
在最近的一篇文章中,Jessica Bulman-Pozen和David Pozen认为“不文明的服从”是一种抗议法律或法规的策略,不是像公民不服从那样违反法律,而是严格遵守法律。他们指出,这是一种对私人和公共行为者都适用的策略,但他们怀疑是否存在司法上的多样性,因为他们认为,即使是超形式主义的法律意见,也不太可能像在非司法行为者身上观察到的严格遵守法律条文那样被视为具有挑衅性。在这篇文章中,我认为司法上的不文明服从是可能的,讨论了下级法院对美国最高法院判决的不文明服从的例子,推测为什么在等级司法系统中,不文明服从可能是下级法院特别有吸引力的异议形式,并认为我的例子满足Bulman-Pozen和Pozen的标准。此外,我认为,他们确定的限制不文明服从的约束,可以限制其行使的机会,也有类似的限制法官参与不文明服从的能力。
{"title":"Can Judges Be Uncivilly Obedient","authors":"Brannon P. Denning","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.3123167","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.3123167","url":null,"abstract":"In a recent article, Jessica Bulman-Pozen and David Pozen identified “uncivil obedience” as a tactic for protesting laws or regulations, not by violating the law, as with civil disobedience, but rather by scrupulous attendance to it. They noted that it is a tactic available to private and public actors alike, but were doubtful that a judicial variety existed because even hyper-formalist legal opinions, they argued, would be unlikely to be perceived as provocative as scrupulous adherence to the letter of the law might be when observed in non-judicial actors. In this article, I argue that judicial uncivil obedience is possible, discuss examples of lower court uncivil obedience to U.S. Supreme Court decisions, speculate why uncivil obedience might be a particularly attractive form of dissent by inferior courts in a hierarchical judicial system, and argue that my examples satisfy Bulman-Pozen and Pozen’s criteria. In addition, I argue that the constraints on uncivil obedience they identify, which can limit the opportunity for its exercise, have analogues that likewise limit the ability of judges to engage in uncivil obedience.","PeriodicalId":75324,"journal":{"name":"William and Mary law review","volume":"60 1","pages":"1"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-02-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45753433","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Why a President Cannot Authorize the Military to Violate (Most of) the Law of War 为什么总统不能授权军队违反(大部分)战争法
Pub Date : 2018-02-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2941159
John C. Dehn
Waterboarding and “much worse,” torture, and “tak[ing] out” the family members of terrorists: President Trump endorsed these measures while campaigning for office. After his inauguration, Trump confirmed his view of the effectiveness of torture and has not rejected other measures forbidden by international law. This article therefore examines whether a president has the power to order or authorize the military to violate international humanitarian law, known as the “law of war.” Rather than assess whether international or federal law generally constrains a president as commander-in-chief, however, its focus is the extent to which Congress requires the U.S. military to comply with the law of war in its disciplinary code, the Uniform Code of Military Justice (UCMJ). It clarifies the extent to which Article 18 of the UCMJ, which vests general courts-martial with jurisdiction over offenders and offenses triable by military tribunal and to impose punishments “permitted” by the law of war, requires law of war compliance. It explains how Article 18 empowers courts-martial to try and punish not only war crimes defined by international law but also other law of war violations that entail a criminal offense under the UCMJ. Put differently, the article clarifies why reasonable compliance with the law of war is necessary to justify common war measures that are otherwise crimes punishable under the UCMJ, such as murder, maiming, assault, and arson. The article then explains why this domestic execution of the law of war limits a president’s authority as Commander-in-Chief: a president does not possess constitutional power to override congressional regulation of the military. So long as Article 18 remains unchanged, no president may order or authorize war crimes or other law of war violations that entail a crime under the UCMJ.
水刑和“更糟糕的是”酷刑,以及“驱逐”恐怖分子的家人:特朗普总统在竞选公职时支持了这些措施。就职后,特朗普证实了他对酷刑有效性的看法,并没有拒绝国际法禁止的其他措施。因此,本文探讨了总统是否有权命令或授权军队违反国际人道主义法,即“战争法”。然而,与其评估国际法或联邦法是否普遍限制总统担任总司令,其重点是国会在其纪律准则《统一军事司法准则》(UCMJ)中要求美国军队遵守战争法的程度。它澄清了UCMJ第18条要求遵守战争法的程度,该条赋予普通军事法院对罪犯和军事法庭可审理的罪行的管辖权,并规定战争法“允许”的惩罚。它解释了第18条如何授权军事法庭不仅审判和惩罚国际法定义的战争罪,而且审判和惩罚根据UCMJ构成刑事犯罪的其他违反战争法的行为。换言之,这篇文章阐明了为什么合理遵守战争法是必要的,以证明普通战争措施是根据UCMJ应惩罚的罪行,如谋杀、致残、袭击和纵火。文章随后解释了为什么国内对战争法的执行限制了总统作为总司令的权力:总统不拥有推翻国会对军队监管的宪法权力。只要第18条保持不变,任何总统都不得下令或授权战争罪或其他违反战争法的行为,这些行为将构成UCMJ规定的罪行。
{"title":"Why a President Cannot Authorize the Military to Violate (Most of) the Law of War","authors":"John C. Dehn","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2941159","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2941159","url":null,"abstract":"Waterboarding and “much worse,” torture, and “tak[ing] out” the family members of terrorists: President Trump endorsed these measures while campaigning for office. After his inauguration, Trump confirmed his view of the effectiveness of torture and has not rejected other measures forbidden by international law. This article therefore examines whether a president has the power to order or authorize the military to violate international humanitarian law, known as the “law of war.” Rather than assess whether international or federal law generally constrains a president as commander-in-chief, however, its focus is the extent to which Congress requires the U.S. military to comply with the law of war in its disciplinary code, the Uniform Code of Military Justice (UCMJ). It clarifies the extent to which Article 18 of the UCMJ, which vests general courts-martial with jurisdiction over offenders and offenses triable by military tribunal and to impose punishments “permitted” by the law of war, requires law of war compliance. It explains how Article 18 empowers courts-martial to try and punish not only war crimes defined by international law but also other law of war violations that entail a criminal offense under the UCMJ. Put differently, the article clarifies why reasonable compliance with the law of war is necessary to justify common war measures that are otherwise crimes punishable under the UCMJ, such as murder, maiming, assault, and arson. The article then explains why this domestic execution of the law of war limits a president’s authority as Commander-in-Chief: a president does not possess constitutional power to override congressional regulation of the military. So long as Article 18 remains unchanged, no president may order or authorize war crimes or other law of war violations that entail a crime under the UCMJ.","PeriodicalId":75324,"journal":{"name":"William and Mary law review","volume":"59 1","pages":"813"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-02-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45987065","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Taking Virtual Representation Seriously 认真对待虚拟表示
Pub Date : 2018-01-31 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.3118775
Joseph Fishkin
Virtual representation-the representation of people who cannot vote-has come to occupy a distinctly disfavored position in modern conceptions of democracy. For most of our history, this was not the case. Before women's suffrage, most U.S. citizens were represented only virtually. Today, virtual representation remains a substantial part of our democratic order, but it is a part that we tend to ignore. For instance, about a quarter of all U.S. citizens cannot vote because they are children. They, and others who cannot vote, are virtually represented. This Article argues, first, that virtual representation is an inevitable part of any democratic system; second, that it has value, even if it is generally second-best to actual representation; and third, that as long as we are going to do this, we ought to try to do it as well as we can. The Article traces the origins of the American aversion to virtual representation, then begins to build an account of how some forms of virtual representation are better or worse than others. Surprisingly, under conditions of sufficient geographic segregation along various politically salient dimensions, it turns out that our system of electing nearly all representatives from single-member districts may actually ensure non-voters tolerably good virtual representation. That is, as long as we count all the people, not just the voters, for purposes of apportionment-and similarly, as long as we count prisoners at their last address rather than at the location of their prison (this is the problem of so-called "prison gerrymandering"). Finally, the Article argues that the United States Constitution itself constructs a mixed system of actual and virtual representation. The question of the reach of this federal constitutional model-and in what contexts, if any, it mandates the current practice of drawing districts with equal numbers of people, rather than equal numbers of voters-is likely to come before the Supreme Court sometime after the 2020 Census.
虚拟代表——不能投票的人的代表——在现代民主概念中已经占据了明显不受欢迎的地位。在我们的大部分历史中,情况并非如此。在妇女获得选举权之前,大多数美国公民只能在网上获得代表。今天,虚拟代表仍然是我们民主秩序的重要组成部分,但这是一个我们往往忽视的部分。例如,大约四分之一的美国公民不能投票,因为他们是儿童。他们和其他不能投票的人实际上是有代表的。本文认为,首先,虚拟代表制是任何民主制度不可避免的一部分;第二,它是有价值的,即使它通常是仅次于实际代表的;第三,只要我们要做这件事,我们就应该尽力把它做好。本文追溯了美国人厌恶虚拟代表的起源,然后开始阐述某些形式的虚拟代表是如何比其他形式更好或更差的。令人惊讶的是,在各种政治显著因素的充分地理隔离的条件下,我们从单一选区选举几乎所有代表的制度实际上可能确保非选民有相当好的虚拟代表性。也就是说,只要我们计算所有的人,而不仅仅是选民,为了分配的目的,同样,只要我们计算囚犯的最后住址,而不是他们监狱的所在地(这就是所谓的“监狱不公正划分”的问题)。最后,本文认为,美国宪法本身构建了一个现实代表与虚拟代表的混合体系。这种联邦宪法模式的适用范围问题——以及在什么情况下(如果有的话),它会强制执行目前划分人口数量相等而不是选民数量相等的选区的做法——可能会在2020年人口普查后的某个时候出现在最高法院面前。
{"title":"Taking Virtual Representation Seriously","authors":"Joseph Fishkin","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.3118775","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.3118775","url":null,"abstract":"Virtual representation-the representation of people who cannot vote-has come to occupy a distinctly disfavored position in modern conceptions of democracy. For most of our history, this was not the case. Before women's suffrage, most U.S. citizens were represented only virtually. Today, virtual representation remains a substantial part of our democratic order, but it is a part that we tend to ignore. For instance, about a quarter of all U.S. citizens cannot vote because they are children. They, and others who cannot vote, are virtually represented. \u0000This Article argues, first, that virtual representation is an inevitable part of any democratic system; second, that it has value, even if it is generally second-best to actual representation; and third, that as long as we are going to do this, we ought to try to do it as well as we can. The Article traces the origins of the American aversion to virtual representation, then begins to build an account of how some forms of virtual representation are better or worse than others. Surprisingly, under conditions of sufficient geographic segregation along various politically salient dimensions, it turns out that our system of electing nearly all representatives from single-member districts may actually ensure non-voters tolerably good virtual representation. That is, as long as we count all the people, not just the voters, for purposes of apportionment-and similarly, as long as we count prisoners at their last address rather than at the location of their prison (this is the problem of so-called \"prison gerrymandering\"). \u0000Finally, the Article argues that the United States Constitution itself constructs a mixed system of actual and virtual representation. The question of the reach of this federal constitutional model-and in what contexts, if any, it mandates the current practice of drawing districts with equal numbers of people, rather than equal numbers of voters-is likely to come before the Supreme Court sometime after the 2020 Census.","PeriodicalId":75324,"journal":{"name":"William and Mary law review","volume":"59 1","pages":"1681"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-01-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44108205","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Why Rape Should Be a Federal Crime 为什么强奸应该是联邦犯罪
Pub Date : 2018-01-02 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.3095741
Donald A. Dripps
Sexual assault remains at high levels despite decades of legal reforms. The recent wave of accusations against public figures signals both the persistence of the problem and a new political climate for addressing it. The Article argues that Congress should make forcible rape a federal crime, to the limits of the Commerce Clause. This would bring federal assets to the fight against rape by redirecting them from enforcement of possessory crimes. The simple statutory proposal might be accompanied by a more ambitious reorganization of the Justice Department to include a Bureau of Violent Crimes. Replies are offered to objections based on federalism, civil liberties, feminism, and systemic feedback loops.
尽管进行了几十年的法律改革,但性侵仍然居高不下。最近对公众人物的指控浪潮既表明了这个问题的持续存在,也表明了解决这个问题的新政治气候。该条款认为,国会应该在商业条款的限制下,将强迫强奸定为联邦犯罪。这将通过将联邦资产从占有性犯罪的执行中转移出来,将其带到打击强奸的斗争中。在提出简单的法定提案的同时,可能会对司法部进行更雄心勃勃的重组,将暴力犯罪局纳入其中。针对基于联邦制、公民自由、女权主义和系统反馈循环的反对意见,提供了答复。
{"title":"Why Rape Should Be a Federal Crime","authors":"Donald A. Dripps","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.3095741","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.3095741","url":null,"abstract":"Sexual assault remains at high levels despite decades of legal reforms. The recent wave of accusations against public figures signals both the persistence of the problem and a new political climate for addressing it. The Article argues that Congress should make forcible rape a federal crime, to the limits of the Commerce Clause. This would bring federal assets to the fight against rape by redirecting them from enforcement of possessory crimes. The simple statutory proposal might be accompanied by a more ambitious reorganization of the Justice Department to include a Bureau of Violent Crimes. Replies are offered to objections based on federalism, civil liberties, feminism, and systemic feedback loops.","PeriodicalId":75324,"journal":{"name":"William and Mary law review","volume":"60 1","pages":"1685"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2018-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.3095741","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48471675","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Gerrymander and the Constitution: Two Avenues of Analysis and the Quest for a Durable Precedent Gerrymander与宪法:分析与寻求持久先例的两条道路
Pub Date : 2017-07-10 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2999738
E. Foley
It has been notoriously difficult for the U.S. Supreme Court to develop a judicially manageable — and publicly comprehensible — standard for adjudicating partisan gerrymandering claims, a standard comparable in this respect to the extraordinarily successful “one-person, one-vote” principle articulated in the Reapportionment Revolution of the 1960s. This difficulty persists because the quest has been for a gerrymandering standard that is universalistic in the same way that “one-person, one-vote” is: derived from abstract ideas of political theory, like the equal right of citizens to participate in electoral politics. But other domains of constitutional law employ particularistic modes of reasoning in sharp contrast to the universalism of the “one-person, one-vote” principle; and particularism can provide a judicially manageable standard for partisan gerrymandering claims, doing so by making the original Gerrymander — the one provided the name for this category of pernicious partisanship — a fixed historical benchmark by which to judge the distortion of legislative districts. This particularistic reasoning should be persuasive to Justice Anthony Kennedy, especially if rooted in the First Amendment (home to other well-known examples of particularistic analysis), and if also combined with a cogent explanation why the First Amendment right must remain “judicially under-enforced” relative to its potential scope on universalistic grounds, because of the barrier imposed by the political question doctrine’s need for a judicially manageable standard. (Particularism, in other words, defines not necessarily the full First Amendment right from a theoretical perspective, but only the judicially enforceable portion of it.) Even more important than persuading Justice Kennedy, however, is convincing a Supreme Court controlled by conservatives — after Kennedy has been replaced by another like Justices Thomas, Alito, or Gorsuch — not to overrule an opinion in which Justice Kennedy has identified a judicially manageable standard for invalidating partisan gerrymanders as unconstitutional. On this crucial point, particularism has distinct advantages to universalism, including facilitating the possibility that the Kennedy-authored precedent quickly becomes imbedded in the nation’s political culture, because the public easily understands (and embraces) a precedent that renders unconstitutional a district as disfigured as the original Gerrymander. A precedent that becomes as integral element of America’s public self-understanding in this way is one that conservatives on the Court would have difficulty overruling and, indeed, little interest in repudiating insofar as it is historically grounded and limited by the kind of particularistic reasoning that conservatives consider acceptable.
众所周知,美国最高法院很难制定一个司法上可管理的、公众可理解的标准来裁决党派不公正的选区划分主张,在这方面,这个标准可以与20世纪60年代重新分配革命中提出的非常成功的“一人一票”原则相媲美。这种困难之所以持续存在,是因为人们一直在寻求一种不公正的选区划分标准,这种标准与“一人一票”一样具有普遍性:源于抽象的政治理论思想,比如公民平等参与选举政治的权利。但宪法的其他领域采用了特殊的推理模式,与“一人一票”原则的普世主义形成鲜明对比;特殊主义可以为党派划分选区的主张提供一个司法上可管理的标准,通过使最初的选区划分者——为这类恶性党派划分提供名称的人——成为判断立法区扭曲的固定历史基准来做到这一点。这种特殊推理对安东尼·肯尼迪大法官来说应该是有说服力的,特别是如果它植根于第一修正案(其他著名的特殊分析例子的发源地),如果它还结合了一个令人信服的解释,即为什么第一修正案的权利相对于其基于普遍性的潜在范围必须保持“司法强制执行不足”,由于政治问题学说对司法可管理标准的需求所造成的障碍。(换句话说,特殊性不一定从理论角度定义了第一修正案的全部权利,而只定义了其中可司法执行的部分。)然而,比说服肯尼迪大法官更重要的是说服一个由保守派控制的最高法院——在肯尼迪被托马斯、阿利托、,或者戈萨奇——不要推翻一项意见,即肯尼迪大法官已经确定了一个司法上可管理的标准,以使党派划分不公的人无效,这是违宪的。在这一关键点上,特殊主义比普遍主义有着明显的优势,包括促进了肯尼迪开创的先例很快融入国家政治文化的可能性,因为公众很容易理解(并接受)一个先例,这个先例会使一个像最初的格里曼德一样丑陋的地区违宪。一个先例以这种方式成为美国公众自我理解的组成部分,法院中的保守派很难推翻这个先例,事实上,只要它是基于历史的,并且受到保守派认为可以接受的那种特殊推理的限制,就没有兴趣否定它。
{"title":"The Gerrymander and the Constitution: Two Avenues of Analysis and the Quest for a Durable Precedent","authors":"E. Foley","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2999738","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2999738","url":null,"abstract":"It has been notoriously difficult for the U.S. Supreme Court to develop a judicially manageable — and publicly comprehensible — standard for adjudicating partisan gerrymandering claims, a standard comparable in this respect to the extraordinarily successful “one-person, one-vote” principle articulated in the Reapportionment Revolution of the 1960s. This difficulty persists because the quest has been for a gerrymandering standard that is universalistic in the same way that “one-person, one-vote” is: derived from abstract ideas of political theory, like the equal right of citizens to participate in electoral politics. But other domains of constitutional law employ particularistic modes of reasoning in sharp contrast to the universalism of the “one-person, one-vote” principle; and particularism can provide a judicially manageable standard for partisan gerrymandering claims, doing so by making the original Gerrymander — the one provided the name for this category of pernicious partisanship — a fixed historical benchmark by which to judge the distortion of legislative districts. \u0000This particularistic reasoning should be persuasive to Justice Anthony Kennedy, especially if rooted in the First Amendment (home to other well-known examples of particularistic analysis), and if also combined with a cogent explanation why the First Amendment right must remain “judicially under-enforced” relative to its potential scope on universalistic grounds, because of the barrier imposed by the political question doctrine’s need for a judicially manageable standard. (Particularism, in other words, defines not necessarily the full First Amendment right from a theoretical perspective, but only the judicially enforceable portion of it.) Even more important than persuading Justice Kennedy, however, is convincing a Supreme Court controlled by conservatives — after Kennedy has been replaced by another like Justices Thomas, Alito, or Gorsuch — not to overrule an opinion in which Justice Kennedy has identified a judicially manageable standard for invalidating partisan gerrymanders as unconstitutional. On this crucial point, particularism has distinct advantages to universalism, including facilitating the possibility that the Kennedy-authored precedent quickly becomes imbedded in the nation’s political culture, because the public easily understands (and embraces) a precedent that renders unconstitutional a district as disfigured as the original Gerrymander. A precedent that becomes as integral element of America’s public self-understanding in this way is one that conservatives on the Court would have difficulty overruling and, indeed, little interest in repudiating insofar as it is historically grounded and limited by the kind of particularistic reasoning that conservatives consider acceptable.","PeriodicalId":75324,"journal":{"name":"William and Mary law review","volume":"59 1","pages":"1729"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-07-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48251763","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
The Conjunction Problem and the Logic of Jury Findings 衔接问题与陪审团裁决的逻辑
Pub Date : 2017-03-03 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2927252
David S. Schwartz, E. Sober
For several decades, evidence theorists have puzzled over the following paradox, known as the "conjunction problem." Probability theory appears to tell us that the probability of a conjunctive claim is the product resulting from multiplying the probabilities of its separate conjuncts. In a three element negligence case (breach of duty, causation, damages), a plaintiff who proves each element to a 0.6 probability, will have proven her overall claim to a very low probability of 0.216. Either the plaintiff wins the verdict based on this low probability (if the jury focuses on elements) or the plaintiff loses despite having met the condition of proving each element to the stated threshold. To solve this "conjunction problem," evidence theorists have advanced such proposals as changing the rules of probability, barring probability theory entirely from analysis of adjudicative factfinding, abandoning the procedural principle that the defendant need not present a narrative of innocence or non-liability, or dispensing with the requirement that the overall claim must meet an established burden of proof. This article argues that the conjunction paradox in fact presents a theoretical problem of little if any consequence. Dropping the condition that proving each element is a sufficient, as opposed to merely a necessary condition for proof of a claim, makes the conjunction problem disappear. Nothing in logic or probability theory requires this "each element/sufficiency" condition, and the legal decision rules reflected in most jury instructions do not mandate it. Once this "each element/sufficiency" condition is removed, all that is left of the conjunction problem is a "probability gap," an intuitive but ill-founded impression that the mathematical underpinnings of the conjunction problem are "unfair" to claimants. This probability gap is considerably narrowed by recognizing the probabilistic dependence of most facts internal to a given claim, and by applying the correct multiplication rule for probabilistically dependent events. Finally, the article argues that solving the conjunction problem is an insufficient ground either to abandon probability theory as a useful analytical tool in the context of adjudicative factfinding, or reform decision rules for trial factfinders.
几十年来,证据理论家一直对以下悖论感到困惑,即“连词问题”。概率论似乎告诉我们,连词声明的概率是其单独连词的概率乘积。在三要素过失案件(违反义务、因果关系、损害赔偿)中,原告以0.6的概率证明每一要素,将以0.216的极低概率证明其总体索赔。要么原告基于这种低概率赢得判决(如果陪审团关注要素),要么原告尽管满足了证明每个要素达到规定阈值的条件,但还是输了。为了解决这一“连带问题”,证据理论家们提出了一些建议,如改变概率规则,将概率论完全排除在对裁决事实认定的分析之外,放弃被告不必提出无罪或无责任陈述的程序原则,或者免除整个索赔必须满足既定举证责任的要求。本文认为,连词悖论实际上是一个后果很小的理论问题。放弃证明每个元素都是充分的条件,而不仅仅是证明一个权利要求的必要条件,会使连接问题消失。逻辑或概率论中没有任何东西需要这个“每个元素/充分性”条件,大多数陪审团指令中反映的法律裁决规则也没有强制要求,连词问题只剩下“概率差距”,这是一种直观但毫无根据的印象,认为连词问题的数学基础对索赔人“不公平”。通过认识到给定索赔内部大多数事实的概率相关性,并对概率相关性事件应用正确的乘法规则,大大缩小了这种概率差距。最后,文章认为,解决衔接问题不足以放弃概率论作为裁决事实调查中有用的分析工具,也不足以改革审判事实调查者的决策规则。
{"title":"The Conjunction Problem and the Logic of Jury Findings","authors":"David S. Schwartz, E. Sober","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2927252","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2927252","url":null,"abstract":"For several decades, evidence theorists have puzzled over the following paradox, known as the \"conjunction problem.\" Probability theory appears to tell us that the probability of a conjunctive claim is the product resulting from multiplying the probabilities of its separate conjuncts. In a three element negligence case (breach of duty, causation, damages), a plaintiff who proves each element to a 0.6 probability, will have proven her overall claim to a very low probability of 0.216. Either the plaintiff wins the verdict based on this low probability (if the jury focuses on elements) or the plaintiff loses despite having met the condition of proving each element to the stated threshold. To solve this \"conjunction problem,\" evidence theorists have advanced such proposals as changing the rules of probability, barring probability theory entirely from analysis of adjudicative factfinding, abandoning the procedural principle that the defendant need not present a narrative of innocence or non-liability, or dispensing with the requirement that the overall claim must meet an established burden of proof. This article argues that the conjunction paradox in fact presents a theoretical problem of little if any consequence. Dropping the condition that proving each element is a sufficient, as opposed to merely a necessary condition for proof of a claim, makes the conjunction problem disappear. Nothing in logic or probability theory requires this \"each element/sufficiency\" condition, and the legal decision rules reflected in most jury instructions do not mandate it. Once this \"each element/sufficiency\" condition is removed, all that is left of the conjunction problem is a \"probability gap,\" an intuitive but ill-founded impression that the mathematical underpinnings of the conjunction problem are \"unfair\" to claimants. This probability gap is considerably narrowed by recognizing the probabilistic dependence of most facts internal to a given claim, and by applying the correct multiplication rule for probabilistically dependent events. Finally, the article argues that solving the conjunction problem is an insufficient ground either to abandon probability theory as a useful analytical tool in the context of adjudicative factfinding, or reform decision rules for trial factfinders.","PeriodicalId":75324,"journal":{"name":"William and Mary law review","volume":"59 1","pages":"619"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-03-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44759015","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 8
The Constitution and the Language of the Law 宪法与法律语言
Pub Date : 2017-01-01 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2928936
John O. McGinnis, Michael B. Rappaport
There has been a long-standing debate over whether the Constitution is written in ordinary or legal language. Yet no article has offered a framework for determining the nature of the Constitution’s language, let alone systematically canvassed the evidence. This article fills the gap. First, it shows that a distinctive legal language exists. This language in the Constitution includes terms, like Letters of Marque and Reprisal, that are patently technical, and terms, like good behavior, that are latently so in that they have both an ordinary and legal meaning but are better interpreted according to the latter. It also includes legal interpretive rules such as those that tell readers when to understand a term in its legal sense or its ordinary meaning sense. The article shows how to determine whether a document is written in the language of the law. The most important factor is the language of the document itself. The pervasive presence of technical legal terms provides strong evidence that a document is written in the language of the law, because ordinary language cannot easily account for even a small number of legal terms. The purpose of the document also counts. Insofar as it is written to inform officials of their duties, it is more likely to written in legal language, because that language allows more precision. The language of similar documents provides additional evidence. Since other constitutions at the time were written in the language of the law, that militates in favor of reading the Constitution in that same language. The article supplies strong evidence that the Constitution is written in the language of the law. The article is the first to count the legal terms in the Constitution and approximates them at a hundred. Moreover, the Constitution’s text both blocks the operation of certain legal interpretive rules and calls for the application of other such rules. Finally, the judges and legislators charged with implementing the Constitution in the early Republic frequently deployed legal interpretive rules to resolve contested issues. The Constitution’s legal language has important theoretical and practical significance. Theoretically, it shows that that original methods originalism is the correct form of originalism, because the Constitution’s legal interpretive rules are crucial to cashing out its meaning. Practically, the richness of its idiom provides resources to address otherwise unresolvable interpretive questions.
关于宪法是用普通语言还是法律语言一直存在争论。然而,没有一篇文章提供了一个框架来确定宪法语言的性质,更不用说系统地调查证据了。本文填补了这一空白。首先,它表明存在一种独特的法律语言。《宪法》中的这种语言包括一些术语,比如《马尔克书信》和《报复》,它们显然是技术性的,还有一些术语,比如良好行为,它们潜在地具有普通和法律意义,但根据后者更好地解释。它还包括法律解释规则,比如告诉读者什么时候从法律意义上理解一个术语,什么时候从普通意义上理解一个术语。这篇文章说明了如何确定一份文书是否是用法律语言写成的。最重要的因素是文件本身的语言。法律术语的普遍存在提供了强有力的证据,证明一份文件是用法律语言写成的,因为普通语言甚至不能轻易地解释一小部分法律术语。文件的目的也很重要。如果是为了告知官员他们的职责而写的,那么更有可能是用法律语言写的,因为法律语言更精确。类似文件的语言提供了额外的证据。由于当时的其他宪法都是用法律语言写成的,这不利于用同样的语言来解读宪法。这条条款提供了强有力的证据,证明宪法是用法律语言写成的。这篇文章第一次统计了宪法中的法律术语,大约有100个。此外,宪法文本既阻碍了某些法律解释规则的运作,又要求适用其他法律解释规则。最后,共和国早期负责执行宪法的法官和立法者经常使用法律解释性规则来解决有争议的问题。宪法法律语言具有重要的理论和实践意义。从理论上讲,这表明原意主义是原意主义的正确形式,因为宪法的法律解释规则对原意的实现至关重要。实际上,其丰富的成语为解决其他无法解决的解释问题提供了资源。
{"title":"The Constitution and the Language of the Law","authors":"John O. McGinnis, Michael B. Rappaport","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2928936","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2928936","url":null,"abstract":"There has been a long-standing debate over whether the Constitution is written in ordinary or legal language. Yet no article has offered a framework for determining the nature of the Constitution’s language, let alone systematically canvassed the evidence. This article fills the gap. First, it shows that a distinctive legal language exists. This language in the Constitution includes terms, like Letters of Marque and Reprisal, that are patently technical, and terms, like good behavior, that are latently so in that they have both an ordinary and legal meaning but are better interpreted according to the latter. It also includes legal interpretive rules such as those that tell readers when to understand a term in its legal sense or its ordinary meaning sense. The article shows how to determine whether a document is written in the language of the law. The most important factor is the language of the document itself. The pervasive presence of technical legal terms provides strong evidence that a document is written in the language of the law, because ordinary language cannot easily account for even a small number of legal terms. The purpose of the document also counts. Insofar as it is written to inform officials of their duties, it is more likely to written in legal language, because that language allows more precision. The language of similar documents provides additional evidence. Since other constitutions at the time were written in the language of the law, that militates in favor of reading the Constitution in that same language. The article supplies strong evidence that the Constitution is written in the language of the law. The article is the first to count the legal terms in the Constitution and approximates them at a hundred. Moreover, the Constitution’s text both blocks the operation of certain legal interpretive rules and calls for the application of other such rules. Finally, the judges and legislators charged with implementing the Constitution in the early Republic frequently deployed legal interpretive rules to resolve contested issues. The Constitution’s legal language has important theoretical and practical significance. Theoretically, it shows that that original methods originalism is the correct form of originalism, because the Constitution’s legal interpretive rules are crucial to cashing out its meaning. Practically, the richness of its idiom provides resources to address otherwise unresolvable interpretive questions.","PeriodicalId":75324,"journal":{"name":"William and Mary law review","volume":"59 1","pages":"1321"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2017-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68435073","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 7
Protean Statutory Interpretation in the Courts of Appeals 上诉法院中千变万化的法定解释
Pub Date : 2016-12-20 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2745987
J. Brudney, L. Baum
This article is the first in-depth empirical and doctrinal analysis of differences in statutory interpretation between the courts of appeals and the Supreme Court. It is also among the first to anticipate how the Supreme Court’s interpretive approach may shift with the passing of Justice Scalia. We begin by identifying several factors that may contribute to interpretive divergence between the two judicial levels, based on their different institutional structures and operational realities. In doing so, we discuss certain normative implications that may follow from the prospect of such interpretive divergence. We then examine how three circuit courts have used dictionaries and legislative history in three subject matter areas over the past decade, and compare these findings in detail to the interpretive approach taken by the Roberts Court in the same three fields. We determine that the appeals courts have followed a protean approach, adapting their usage patterns in ways that differ substantially from patterns in the Supreme Court. Appeals court judges use dictionaries far less relative to legislative history than do the justices; we found no semblance of the distinctive dictionary culture that is prevalent on the Roberts Court. In addition, the relative frequency of dictionary usage between the two court levels varies considerably depending on the subject area and the type of dictionary (general or legal). With respect to relative frequency for legislative history, the Supreme Court far more than the circuits courts invokes the record of changes in statutory text—either modified over multiple Congresses (statutory history) or developed in successive pre-enactment versions of a bill (drafting history). This “vertical history” is apparently more attractive, or less unattractive, to textualist justices than is traditional legislative history commentary such as committee reports. More broadly, circuit courts use legislative history regularly to resolve ambiguities, confirm apparent meaning, or simply explicate legislative intent, all without characterizing its legitimacy or systemic value. For both dictionaries and legislative history, the courts of appeals’ eclectic approach differs markedly from the Supreme Court’s more self-consciously articulated methodological path. We suggest how certain sources of interpretive divergence contribute to these differences, notably the justices’ interaction with all their colleagues in every case and their experience as objects of continuing media and congressional attention, some of which reflects attention that carries over from the judicial confirmation process. We conclude that the eclecticism of the appeals courts is likely to limit judicial discretion more effectively than the Supreme Court’s current approach which favors clear interpretive rules or priorities that are applied on a presumptively consistent basis.
本文是对上诉法院和最高法院之间的法律解释差异进行的第一次深入的实证和理论分析。它也是最早预测最高法院的解释方式可能随着斯卡利亚大法官的去世而发生变化的机构之一。我们首先确定可能导致两个司法级别根据其不同的体制结构和业务现实在解释上出现分歧的几个因素。在此过程中,我们讨论了从这种解释分歧的前景中可能产生的某些规范性含义。然后,我们研究了三个巡回法院在过去十年中如何在三个主题领域使用词典和立法历史,并将这些发现与罗伯茨法院在相同三个领域采取的解释方法进行了详细比较。我们认为,上诉法院遵循了一种千变万化的方法,以与最高法院的模式有很大不同的方式调整了它们的使用模式。与大法官相比,上诉法院的法官使用的与立法史相关的词典要少得多;我们没有发现罗伯茨法院盛行的那种独特的词典文化。此外,两级法院之间使用字典的相对频率根据主题领域和字典的类型(一般或法律)而有很大差异。就立法史的相对频率而言,最高法院远比巡回法院更频繁地援引法律文本的变化记录——要么经过多次国会的修改(法定史),要么在法案颁布前的连续版本中发展(起草史)。这种“纵向历史”显然比传统的立法历史评论(如委员会报告)更有吸引力,或者更有吸引力。更广泛地说,巡回法院经常利用立法历史来解决歧义,确认明显的含义,或简单地解释立法意图,而不确定其合法性或系统价值。就词典和立法史而言,上诉法院的折衷方法与最高法院更自觉地明确表达的方法路径明显不同。我们提出了解释分歧的某些来源是如何导致这些差异的,特别是大法官在每个案件中与所有同事的互动,以及他们作为媒体和国会持续关注对象的经历,其中一些反映了从司法确认过程延续下来的关注。我们的结论是,上诉法院的折衷主义可能比最高法院目前的做法更有效地限制司法自由裁量权,最高法院目前的做法倾向于在假定一致的基础上适用明确的解释性规则或优先事项。
{"title":"Protean Statutory Interpretation in the Courts of Appeals","authors":"J. Brudney, L. Baum","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2745987","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2745987","url":null,"abstract":"This article is the first in-depth empirical and doctrinal analysis of differences in statutory interpretation between the courts of appeals and the Supreme Court. It is also among the first to anticipate how the Supreme Court’s interpretive approach may shift with the passing of Justice Scalia. We begin by identifying several factors that may contribute to interpretive divergence between the two judicial levels, based on their different institutional structures and operational realities. In doing so, we discuss certain normative implications that may follow from the prospect of such interpretive divergence. We then examine how three circuit courts have used dictionaries and legislative history in three subject matter areas over the past decade, and compare these findings in detail to the interpretive approach taken by the Roberts Court in the same three fields. We determine that the appeals courts have followed a protean approach, adapting their usage patterns in ways that differ substantially from patterns in the Supreme Court. Appeals court judges use dictionaries far less relative to legislative history than do the justices; we found no semblance of the distinctive dictionary culture that is prevalent on the Roberts Court. In addition, the relative frequency of dictionary usage between the two court levels varies considerably depending on the subject area and the type of dictionary (general or legal). With respect to relative frequency for legislative history, the Supreme Court far more than the circuits courts invokes the record of changes in statutory text—either modified over multiple Congresses (statutory history) or developed in successive pre-enactment versions of a bill (drafting history). This “vertical history” is apparently more attractive, or less unattractive, to textualist justices than is traditional legislative history commentary such as committee reports. More broadly, circuit courts use legislative history regularly to resolve ambiguities, confirm apparent meaning, or simply explicate legislative intent, all without characterizing its legitimacy or systemic value. For both dictionaries and legislative history, the courts of appeals’ eclectic approach differs markedly from the Supreme Court’s more self-consciously articulated methodological path. We suggest how certain sources of interpretive divergence contribute to these differences, notably the justices’ interaction with all their colleagues in every case and their experience as objects of continuing media and congressional attention, some of which reflects attention that carries over from the judicial confirmation process. We conclude that the eclecticism of the appeals courts is likely to limit judicial discretion more effectively than the Supreme Court’s current approach which favors clear interpretive rules or priorities that are applied on a presumptively consistent basis.","PeriodicalId":75324,"journal":{"name":"William and Mary law review","volume":"58 1","pages":"681"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2016-12-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68284344","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Our Prescriptive Judicial Power: Constitutive and Entrenchment Effects of Historical Practice in Federal Courts Law 我们的规定性司法权:联邦法院法历史实践的构成与巩固效应
Pub Date : 2016-02-28 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2739305
E. A. Young
Scholars examining the use of historical practice in constitutional adjudication have focused on a few high-profile separation-of-powers disputes, such as the recent decisions in NLRB v. Noel Canning and Zivotofsky v. Kerry. This essay argues that “big cases make bad theory” — that the focus on high-profile cases of this type distorts our understanding of how historical practice figures in constitutional adjudication more generally. I shift focus here to the more prosaic terrain of federal courts law, in which practice plays a pervasive role. That shift reveals two important insights: First, while historical practice plays an important constitutive role, structuring and filling gaps in the judicial architecture, that practice is, in contrast to the practices in Noel Canning and Zivotofsky, rarely entrenched against ordinary legal change. Second, the authority of historical practice in high-profile separation-of-powers disputes generally rests on a theory of acquiescence by one branch in the other’s actions; the federal courts cases, in contrast, ignore acquiescence and instead ground practice’s authority in its longstanding observance.The use of historical practice in federal courts law rests on a theory of prescription — that is, past practice derives authority from its sheer past-ness. This essay explores the centrality of prescription in Burkean political theory and suggests that cases relying on past practices can contribute to the development of a distinctively Burkean theory of constitutional law. This theory suggests that past practice plays an important constitutive role, but as in the federal courts cases, that role is not entrenched against ordinary legal change. The fact that historical practice is not entrenched — and can be changed through democratic processes — helps to answer several key criticisms of relying on practice in constitutional adjudication.
研究在宪法裁决中使用历史实践的学者们把注意力集中在一些引人注目的三权分立纠纷上,比如最近的NLRB诉诺埃尔·坎宁案和齐沃托夫斯基诉克里案的判决。这篇文章认为,“大案件产生坏理论”——对这类引人注目的案件的关注扭曲了我们对历史实践如何更普遍地影响宪法裁决的理解。在这里,我将重点转移到联邦法院法律中更为平淡无奇的领域,在这一领域,实践发挥着无处不在的作用。这一转变揭示了两个重要的洞见:首先,虽然历史实践在构建和填补司法架构的空白方面发挥着重要的构成作用,但与诺埃尔·坎宁和齐沃托夫斯基的做法相反,历史实践很少对普通的法律变革形成根深蒂固的抵制。其次,在备受瞩目的三权分立争端中,历史实践的权威性通常建立在一个分支默许另一个分支行动的理论之上;相比之下,联邦法院的案件忽略了默许,而是将实践的权威置于其长期遵守的基础上。联邦法院对历史实践的运用建立在时效理论的基础上——也就是说,过去的实践从其纯粹的过去性中获得权威。本文探讨了规定在伯克政治理论中的中心地位,并提出依赖于过去实践的案例可以有助于发展一种独特的伯克宪法理论。这一理论表明,过去的实践起着重要的构成作用,但正如在联邦法院的案件中一样,这一作用在普通的法律变革中并不根深蒂固。历史实践并非根深蒂固——而且可以通过民主进程加以改变——这一事实有助于回答对宪法裁决依赖实践的几个关键批评。
{"title":"Our Prescriptive Judicial Power: Constitutive and Entrenchment Effects of Historical Practice in Federal Courts Law","authors":"E. A. Young","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2739305","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2739305","url":null,"abstract":"Scholars examining the use of historical practice in constitutional adjudication have focused on a few high-profile separation-of-powers disputes, such as the recent decisions in NLRB v. Noel Canning and Zivotofsky v. Kerry. This essay argues that “big cases make bad theory” — that the focus on high-profile cases of this type distorts our understanding of how historical practice figures in constitutional adjudication more generally. I shift focus here to the more prosaic terrain of federal courts law, in which practice plays a pervasive role. That shift reveals two important insights: First, while historical practice plays an important constitutive role, structuring and filling gaps in the judicial architecture, that practice is, in contrast to the practices in Noel Canning and Zivotofsky, rarely entrenched against ordinary legal change. Second, the authority of historical practice in high-profile separation-of-powers disputes generally rests on a theory of acquiescence by one branch in the other’s actions; the federal courts cases, in contrast, ignore acquiescence and instead ground practice’s authority in its longstanding observance.The use of historical practice in federal courts law rests on a theory of prescription — that is, past practice derives authority from its sheer past-ness. This essay explores the centrality of prescription in Burkean political theory and suggests that cases relying on past practices can contribute to the development of a distinctively Burkean theory of constitutional law. This theory suggests that past practice plays an important constitutive role, but as in the federal courts cases, that role is not entrenched against ordinary legal change. The fact that historical practice is not entrenched — and can be changed through democratic processes — helps to answer several key criticisms of relying on practice in constitutional adjudication.","PeriodicalId":75324,"journal":{"name":"William and Mary law review","volume":"58 1","pages":"535"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2016-02-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68281718","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
期刊
William and Mary law review
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1