首页 > 最新文献

William and Mary law review最新文献

英文 中文
A Process Failure Theory of Statutory Interpretation 法定解释的过程失效理论
Pub Date : 2013-10-13 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2339698
M. Seidenfeld
This article lays out a legislative process failure theory of statutory interpretation. It first defends an intent-based approach to interpretation by arguing that Congress, in the process of drafting statutes, does not use the same mechanisms for determining meaning as do courts when they interpret them. Therefore, courts and legislatures comprise different linguistic interpretive communities. The article proceeds to define legislative process failure to occur when the mechanism of each community leads to different understandings of statutory text. The paramount question then becomes: what is the best response of the legal system to such failure? Legislative supremacy requires that the courts and Congress come to some accommodation to ensure that courts will interpret statutes in accord with the legislature’s understanding. That assumption, however, is satisfied so long as Congress knows how courts will interpret statutes and can adjust its process to ensure that the statutes it enacts will be interpreted as it intends. Legislative process failure theory therefore leads to the subsequent question: which branch should accommodate the other’s method of attaching meaning to statutes, and under what circumstances? I conclude that, generally, legislatures cannot engage in judicial type inquiries into statutory meaning while drafting statutes because the cost of engaging such statutory analysis ex-ante – before identification of the potential provisions that might exhibit process failure – is prohibitive. But, once the legislature becomes aware of a process failure, the costs of engaging in judicial type textual inquiry become manageable, and the error costs of interpretation due to strategic manipulation of legislative meaning greatly increase. Hence, in the face of such awareness, usually a textual approach is justified. Finally, having developed the legislative process failure of interpretation, the article considers several types of failures for which courts should accommodate the legislative approach to attaching meaning to statutes.
本文提出了法律解释的立法程序失效理论。它首先为基于意图的解释方法辩护,认为国会在起草法规的过程中,没有使用与法院在解释法规时相同的机制来确定其含义。因此,法院和立法机构组成了不同的语言解释群体。接着界定了各共同体的机制导致对法定文本的不同理解时所发生的立法程序失灵。那么最重要的问题就变成了:法律体系对这种失败的最佳回应是什么?立法至上要求法院和国会达成某种和解,以确保法院按照立法机关的理解来解释成文法。然而,只要国会知道法院将如何解释成文法,并能够调整其程序,以确保它颁布的成文法将按照它的意图得到解释,这种假设就可以满足。因此,立法程序失败理论导致了随后的问题:哪个部门应该适应另一个部门赋予法规意义的方法,以及在什么情况下?我的结论是,一般来说,立法机关在起草法规时不能对法律意义进行司法式的调查,因为在确定可能显示程序失败的潜在条款之前进行这种事前法律分析的费用是令人望而却步的。但是,一旦立法机关意识到程序失败,从事司法式文本查询的成本就变得可控,而由于立法意义的战略性操纵而导致的解释错误成本就会大大增加。因此,面对这种意识,通常文本方法是合理的。最后,在阐述了解释的立法程序失败之后,本文考虑了法院应采用立法方法赋予成文法意义的几种类型的失败。
{"title":"A Process Failure Theory of Statutory Interpretation","authors":"M. Seidenfeld","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2339698","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2339698","url":null,"abstract":"This article lays out a legislative process failure theory of statutory interpretation. It first defends an intent-based approach to interpretation by arguing that Congress, in the process of drafting statutes, does not use the same mechanisms for determining meaning as do courts when they interpret them. Therefore, courts and legislatures comprise different linguistic interpretive communities. The article proceeds to define legislative process failure to occur when the mechanism of each community leads to different understandings of statutory text. The paramount question then becomes: what is the best response of the legal system to such failure? Legislative supremacy requires that the courts and Congress come to some accommodation to ensure that courts will interpret statutes in accord with the legislature’s understanding. That assumption, however, is satisfied so long as Congress knows how courts will interpret statutes and can adjust its process to ensure that the statutes it enacts will be interpreted as it intends. Legislative process failure theory therefore leads to the subsequent question: which branch should accommodate the other’s method of attaching meaning to statutes, and under what circumstances? I conclude that, generally, legislatures cannot engage in judicial type inquiries into statutory meaning while drafting statutes because the cost of engaging such statutory analysis ex-ante – before identification of the potential provisions that might exhibit process failure – is prohibitive. But, once the legislature becomes aware of a process failure, the costs of engaging in judicial type textual inquiry become manageable, and the error costs of interpretation due to strategic manipulation of legislative meaning greatly increase. Hence, in the face of such awareness, usually a textual approach is justified. Finally, having developed the legislative process failure of interpretation, the article considers several types of failures for which courts should accommodate the legislative approach to attaching meaning to statutes.","PeriodicalId":75324,"journal":{"name":"William and Mary law review","volume":"56 1","pages":"467"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2013-10-13","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.2339698","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68119523","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Is Guilt Dispositive? Federal Habeas after Martinez 内疚是决定性的吗?马丁内斯之后联邦人身保护令
Pub Date : 2013-10-10 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2338588
J. Marceau
Federal habeas review of criminal convictions is not supposed to be a second opportunity to adjudge guilt. It has been said, by Oliver Wendall Holmes among others, that the sole question on federal habeas is whether the prisoner’s constitutional rights were violated. By the early 1970s, however, scholars criticized this rights-based view of habeas and sounded the alarm that post-conviction review had become too far removed from questions of innocence. Most famously, in 1970 Judge Friendly criticized the breadth of habeas corpus by posing a single question: Is innocence irrelevant? In his view habeas review that focused exclusively on questions of rights in isolation from questions of innocence was misguided.Over the last forty years the habeas landscape has changed so dramatically — both through statutory and common law limits on the writ — that it is appropriate to ask a very different question: Is guilt dispositive? Both substantive law and habeas procedure has evolved so as to substantially disadvantage a guilty habeas petitioner. In many cases regardless of the merits of the constitutional claim, strong evidence of guilt is dispositive in ensuring that relief is denied. A recent trilogy of cases from the last couple of years — Holland v. Florida, Maples v. Thomas, and most importantly, Martinez v. Ryan — signal a potential shift in the Court’s innocence orientation. This Article explores the potential impact of these decisions and in particular argues that they may provide a roadmap for a proceduralist approach to modern habeas — that is, habeas review that prioritizes fair procedures over innocence. The impact of Friendly’s call for greater focus on innocence was gradual but profound, and this Article argues that the Martinez-trilogy may be similarly important in reversing habeas’ four-decade-long infatuation with innocence.
联邦人身保护令对刑事定罪的审查不应该是判定有罪的第二次机会。奥利弗·温德尔·霍姆斯(Oliver Wendall Holmes)等人曾说过,联邦人身保护令的唯一问题是囚犯的宪法权利是否受到侵犯。然而,到20世纪70年代初,学者们批评了这种基于权利的人身保护令观点,并发出警告称,定罪后的审查已经远离了无罪的问题。最著名的是,在1970年,弗兰德利法官通过提出一个问题来批评人身保护令的广度:无罪是否无关紧要?他认为,只关注权利问题而忽视无辜问题的人身保护审查是错误的。在过去的四十年里,人身保护令的格局发生了如此巨大的变化——无论是通过成文法还是普通法对令状的限制——以至于我们有必要提出一个截然不同的问题:有罪是决定性的吗?实体法和人身保护程序都已发展到实质上对有罪的人身保护请愿人不利的地步。在许多情况下,无论宪法要求是否正确,有罪的有力证据在确保救济被拒绝方面是决定性的。最近几年的一系列案件——荷兰诉佛罗里达案、梅普尔斯诉托马斯案,以及最重要的马丁内斯诉瑞安案——标志着最高法院清白取向的潜在转变。本文探讨了这些决定的潜在影响,特别是认为它们可能为现代人身保护的程序主义方法提供了路线图-即人身保护审查优先考虑公平程序而不是无罪。弗兰德利呼吁更多地关注无辜的影响是渐进而深刻的,本文认为马丁内斯三部曲在扭转人身保护令长达40年对无辜的迷恋方面可能同样重要。
{"title":"Is Guilt Dispositive? Federal Habeas after Martinez","authors":"J. Marceau","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2338588","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2338588","url":null,"abstract":"Federal habeas review of criminal convictions is not supposed to be a second opportunity to adjudge guilt. It has been said, by Oliver Wendall Holmes among others, that the sole question on federal habeas is whether the prisoner’s constitutional rights were violated. By the early 1970s, however, scholars criticized this rights-based view of habeas and sounded the alarm that post-conviction review had become too far removed from questions of innocence. Most famously, in 1970 Judge Friendly criticized the breadth of habeas corpus by posing a single question: Is innocence irrelevant? In his view habeas review that focused exclusively on questions of rights in isolation from questions of innocence was misguided.Over the last forty years the habeas landscape has changed so dramatically — both through statutory and common law limits on the writ — that it is appropriate to ask a very different question: Is guilt dispositive? Both substantive law and habeas procedure has evolved so as to substantially disadvantage a guilty habeas petitioner. In many cases regardless of the merits of the constitutional claim, strong evidence of guilt is dispositive in ensuring that relief is denied. A recent trilogy of cases from the last couple of years — Holland v. Florida, Maples v. Thomas, and most importantly, Martinez v. Ryan — signal a potential shift in the Court’s innocence orientation. This Article explores the potential impact of these decisions and in particular argues that they may provide a roadmap for a proceduralist approach to modern habeas — that is, habeas review that prioritizes fair procedures over innocence. The impact of Friendly’s call for greater focus on innocence was gradual but profound, and this Article argues that the Martinez-trilogy may be similarly important in reversing habeas’ four-decade-long infatuation with innocence.","PeriodicalId":75324,"journal":{"name":"William and Mary law review","volume":"24 1","pages":"2071"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2013-10-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68118376","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Congress's Treaty-Implementing Power in Historical Practice 历史实践中的国会履约权
Pub Date : 2013-06-06 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2275355
J. Galbraith
Historical practice strongly influences constitutional interpretation in foreign affairs law, including most questions relating to the treaty power. Yet it is strikingly absent from the debate presently pending before the U.S. Supreme Court over whether Congress can pass legislation implementing U.S. treaties under the Necessary and Proper Clause, even if this legislation would otherwise lie outside its enumerated powers. Drawing on previously unexplored sources, this piece considers the historical roots of Congress’s power to implement U.S. treaties between the Founding and the seminal case of Missouri v. Holland in 1920. It shows that time after time, members of Congress relied on the Necessary and Proper Clause in passing legislation implementing treaties. Notably, both opponents and supporters of a strong treaty power accepted Congress’s power to implement treaties under the Necessary and Proper Clause, even though they did so for quite different reasons. This consensus helped lead to the growing practice of treaty non-self-execution, a practice that in turn has led Congress to play an increased role in treaty implementation. The historical practice revealed in this piece supports the conclusion that Congress has the power to pass legislation implementing treaties under the Necessary and Proper Clause, even where no other Article I power underlies this legislation.
历史实践强烈影响着外交事务法的宪法解释,包括大多数与条约权力有关的问题。然而,在美国最高法院目前悬而未决的关于国会是否可以根据“必要和适当条款”通过立法实施美国条约的辩论中,即使这项立法不属于其列举的权力范围,也明显缺席了这一辩论。这篇文章利用以前未开发的资源,考虑了国会执行美国条约的权力的历史根源,这些条约是从美国建国到1920年密苏里诉荷兰的开创性案例。这表明,国会议员一次又一次地依靠必要和适当条款来通过实施条约的立法。值得注意的是,强大条约权力的反对者和支持者都接受国会根据必要和适当条款执行条约的权力,尽管他们这样做的原因完全不同。这种共识有助于导致条约不自行执行的做法日益增多,这种做法反过来又导致国会在条约执行方面发挥更大的作用。这篇文章揭示的历史实践支持这样一个结论,即国会有权根据必要和适当条款通过立法来实施条约,即使没有其他第一条的权力作为这项立法的基础。
{"title":"Congress's Treaty-Implementing Power in Historical Practice","authors":"J. Galbraith","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2275355","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2275355","url":null,"abstract":"Historical practice strongly influences constitutional interpretation in foreign affairs law, including most questions relating to the treaty power. Yet it is strikingly absent from the debate presently pending before the U.S. Supreme Court over whether Congress can pass legislation implementing U.S. treaties under the Necessary and Proper Clause, even if this legislation would otherwise lie outside its enumerated powers. Drawing on previously unexplored sources, this piece considers the historical roots of Congress’s power to implement U.S. treaties between the Founding and the seminal case of Missouri v. Holland in 1920. It shows that time after time, members of Congress relied on the Necessary and Proper Clause in passing legislation implementing treaties. Notably, both opponents and supporters of a strong treaty power accepted Congress’s power to implement treaties under the Necessary and Proper Clause, even though they did so for quite different reasons. This consensus helped lead to the growing practice of treaty non-self-execution, a practice that in turn has led Congress to play an increased role in treaty implementation. The historical practice revealed in this piece supports the conclusion that Congress has the power to pass legislation implementing treaties under the Necessary and Proper Clause, even where no other Article I power underlies this legislation.","PeriodicalId":75324,"journal":{"name":"William and Mary law review","volume":"25 1","pages":"59"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2013-06-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68052683","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
CORRECTIONS FOR RACIAL DISPARITIES IN LAW ENFORCEMENT. 纠正执法中的种族差异。
Pub Date : 2013-05-22 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2104182
Christopher L. Griffin, F. Sloan, Lindsey M. Eldred
Much empirical analysis has documented racial disparities at the beginning and end stages of a criminal case. However, our understanding about the perpetuation of - and even corrections for - differential outcomes as the process unfolds remains less than complete. This Article provides a comprehensive examination of criminal dispositions using all DWI cases in North Carolina during the period 2001-2011, focusing on several major decision points in the process. Starting with pretrial hearings and culminating in sentencing results, we track differences in outcomes by race and gender. Before sentencing, significant gaps emerge in the severity of pretrial release conditions that disadvantage black and Hispanic defendants. Yet when prosecutors decide whether to pursue charges, we observe an initial correction mechanism: Hispanic men are almost two-thirds more likely to have those charges dropped relative to white men. Although few cases survive after the plea bargaining stage, a second correction mechanism arises: Hispanic men are substantially less likely to receive harsher sentences and are sent to jail for significantly less time relative to white men. The first mechanism is based in part on prosecutors' reviewing the strength of the evidence but much more on declining to invest scarce resources in the pursuit of defendants who fail to appear for trial. The second mechanism seems to follow more directly from judicial discretion to reverse decisions made by law enforcement. We discuss possible explanations for these novel empirical results and review methods for more precisely identifying causal mechanisms in criminal justice.
许多实证分析已经在刑事案件的开始和结束阶段记录了种族差异。然而,随着这一进程的展开,我们对差异结果的延续乃至纠正的理解仍然不够完整。本文对2001年至2011年期间北卡罗来纳州所有酒后驾车案件的刑事处置进行了全面考察,重点关注了该过程中的几个主要决策点。从审前听证会开始,到最终的判决结果,我们追踪了不同种族和性别的结果差异。在宣判之前,审前释放条件的严重程度出现了明显的差距,不利于黑人和西班牙裔被告。然而,当检察官决定是否追究指控时,我们观察到一种初步的纠正机制:与白人男性相比,西班牙裔男性被撤销指控的可能性几乎高出三分之二。虽然很少有案例能在辩诉交易阶段幸存下来,但第二种纠正机制出现了:与白人男性相比,西班牙裔男性受到更严厉判决的可能性要小得多,而且被送进监狱的时间也要短得多。第一种机制部分基于检察官审查证据的力度,但更多的是基于拒绝将稀缺资源投入到追捕未能出庭受审的被告上。第二种机制似乎更直接地遵循司法自由裁量权来推翻执法部门做出的决定。我们讨论了对这些新的实证结果的可能解释,并回顾了更精确地识别刑事司法因果机制的方法。
{"title":"CORRECTIONS FOR RACIAL DISPARITIES IN LAW ENFORCEMENT.","authors":"Christopher L. Griffin, F. Sloan, Lindsey M. Eldred","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2104182","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2104182","url":null,"abstract":"Much empirical analysis has documented racial disparities at the beginning and end stages of a criminal case. However, our understanding about the perpetuation of - and even corrections for - differential outcomes as the process unfolds remains less than complete. This Article provides a comprehensive examination of criminal dispositions using all DWI cases in North Carolina during the period 2001-2011, focusing on several major decision points in the process. Starting with pretrial hearings and culminating in sentencing results, we track differences in outcomes by race and gender. Before sentencing, significant gaps emerge in the severity of pretrial release conditions that disadvantage black and Hispanic defendants. Yet when prosecutors decide whether to pursue charges, we observe an initial correction mechanism: Hispanic men are almost two-thirds more likely to have those charges dropped relative to white men. Although few cases survive after the plea bargaining stage, a second correction mechanism arises: Hispanic men are substantially less likely to receive harsher sentences and are sent to jail for significantly less time relative to white men. The first mechanism is based in part on prosecutors' reviewing the strength of the evidence but much more on declining to invest scarce resources in the pursuit of defendants who fail to appear for trial. The second mechanism seems to follow more directly from judicial discretion to reverse decisions made by law enforcement. We discuss possible explanations for these novel empirical results and review methods for more precisely identifying causal mechanisms in criminal justice.","PeriodicalId":75324,"journal":{"name":"William and Mary law review","volume":"55 4 1","pages":"1365-1427"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2013-05-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67913360","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 6
Personal Curtilage: Fourth Amendment Security in Public 私人住宅:第四修正案公共安全
Pub Date : 2013-03-08 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2230653
A. Ferguson
Do citizens have any Fourth Amendment protection from sense-enhancing surveillance technologies in public? This article engages a timely question as new surveillance technologies have redefined expectations of privacy in public spaces. This article proposes a new theory of Fourth Amendment security based on the ancient theory of curtilage protection for private property. Curtilage has long been understood as a legal fiction that expands the protection of the home beyond the formal structures of the house. Curtilage recognizes a buffer zone beyond the four corners of the home that deserves protection, even in public, even if accessible to public view. Based on custom and law protecting against both nosy neighbors and the government, curtilage was defined by the actions the property owner took to signal a protected space. In simple terms, by building a wall around one’s house, the property owner marked out an area of private control. So, too, the theory of personal curtilage turns on persons being able to control the protected areas of their lives in public by similarly signifying that an area is meant to be secure from others. This article develops a theory of personal curtilage built on four overlapping foundational principles. First, persons can build a constitutional protected space secure from governmental surveillance in public. Second, to claim this space as secure from governmental surveillance, the person must affirmatively mark that space in some symbolic manner. Third, these spaces must be related to areas of personal autonomy or intimate connection, be it personal, familial, or associational. Fourth, these contested spaces – like traditional curtilage – will be evaluated by objectively balancing these factors to determine if a Fourth Amendment search has occurred. Adapting the framework of traditional trespass, an intrusion by sense-enhancing technologies into this protected personal curtilage would be a search for Fourth Amendment purposes.The article concludes that the theory of personal curtilage improves and clarifies the existing Fourth Amendment doctrine and offers a new framework for future cases. It also addresses the need for a new vision of trespass to address omnipresent sense-enhancing surveillance technologies.
公民是否受到第四修正案的保护,在公共场合不受增强感官的监控技术的影响?随着新的监控技术重新定义了对公共空间隐私的期望,这篇文章提出了一个及时的问题。本文在古代宅院私有财产保护理论的基础上,提出了一种新的第四修正案担保理论。长期以来,宅院一直被理解为一种法律虚构,它将对房屋的保护扩展到房屋的正式结构之外。宅院是在住宅四角之外的缓冲区,即使在公共场合,即使在公众视野范围内,也应该受到保护。根据习俗和法律,为了防止邻居和政府的八卦,宅院是由业主采取的行动来定义的,以表明这是一个受保护的空间。简而言之,通过在房子周围建一堵墙,业主划出了一个私人控制的区域。因此,个人住宅理论也转向了人们能够在公共场合控制自己生活的受保护区域,通过同样的方式表明一个区域是安全的。本文从四个重叠的基本原则出发,提出了个人宅院建设的理论。首先,人们可以在公共场合建立一个受宪法保护的空间,免受政府的监视。其次,要声称这个空间是安全的,不受政府监视,这个人必须以某种象征性的方式肯定地标记这个空间。第三,这些空间必须与个人自治或亲密联系有关,无论是个人的、家庭的还是社团的。第四,这些有争议的空间——就像传统的宅院一样——将通过客观地平衡这些因素来评估,以确定是否发生了第四修正案的搜查。调整传统的非法侵入的框架,通过感官增强技术侵入受保护的私人住宅将是对第四修正案目的的搜索。本文的结论是,个人宅基地理论完善和澄清了现有的第四修正案原则,并为今后的案件提供了一个新的框架。它还解决了对非法侵入的新看法的需要,以解决无处不在的增强感官的监视技术。
{"title":"Personal Curtilage: Fourth Amendment Security in Public","authors":"A. Ferguson","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2230653","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2230653","url":null,"abstract":"Do citizens have any Fourth Amendment protection from sense-enhancing surveillance technologies in public? This article engages a timely question as new surveillance technologies have redefined expectations of privacy in public spaces. This article proposes a new theory of Fourth Amendment security based on the ancient theory of curtilage protection for private property. Curtilage has long been understood as a legal fiction that expands the protection of the home beyond the formal structures of the house. Curtilage recognizes a buffer zone beyond the four corners of the home that deserves protection, even in public, even if accessible to public view. Based on custom and law protecting against both nosy neighbors and the government, curtilage was defined by the actions the property owner took to signal a protected space. In simple terms, by building a wall around one’s house, the property owner marked out an area of private control. So, too, the theory of personal curtilage turns on persons being able to control the protected areas of their lives in public by similarly signifying that an area is meant to be secure from others. This article develops a theory of personal curtilage built on four overlapping foundational principles. First, persons can build a constitutional protected space secure from governmental surveillance in public. Second, to claim this space as secure from governmental surveillance, the person must affirmatively mark that space in some symbolic manner. Third, these spaces must be related to areas of personal autonomy or intimate connection, be it personal, familial, or associational. Fourth, these contested spaces – like traditional curtilage – will be evaluated by objectively balancing these factors to determine if a Fourth Amendment search has occurred. Adapting the framework of traditional trespass, an intrusion by sense-enhancing technologies into this protected personal curtilage would be a search for Fourth Amendment purposes.The article concludes that the theory of personal curtilage improves and clarifies the existing Fourth Amendment doctrine and offers a new framework for future cases. It also addresses the need for a new vision of trespass to address omnipresent sense-enhancing surveillance technologies.","PeriodicalId":75324,"journal":{"name":"William and Mary law review","volume":"55 1","pages":"1283"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2013-03-08","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68010691","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 5
Oasis or Mirage: The Supreme Court's Thirst for Dictionaries in the Rehnquist and Roberts Eras 绿洲还是海市蜃楼:伦奎斯特和罗伯茨时代最高法院对词典的渴求
Pub Date : 2013-01-02 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2195644
J. Brudney, L. Baum
The Supreme Court’s use of dictionaries, virtually non-existent before 1987, has dramatically increased during the Rehnquist and Roberts Court eras to the point where as many as one-third of statutory decisions invoke dictionary definitions. The increase is linked to the rise of textualism and its intense focus on ordinary meaning. This Article explores the Court’s new dictionary culture in depth from empirical and doctrinal perspectives. Among our findings are (a) while textualist justices are the highest dictionary users, purposivist justices invoke dictionary definitions with comparable frequency; (b) dictionary use is especially heavy in the criminal law area, serving what we describe as a Notice function; (c) dictionary use overall is strikingly ad hoc and subjective. We demonstrate how the Court’s patterns of dictionary usage reflect a casual form of opportunistic conduct: the justices almost always invoke one or at most two dictionaries, they have varied individual brand preferences from which they often depart, they seem to use general and legal dictionaries interchangeably, and they lack a coherent position on citing to editions from the time of statutory enactment versus the time the instant case was filed.The Article then conducts a detailed doctrinal review, leading to an innovative functional analysis of how the justices use dictionaries: as way stations when dictionary meanings are indeterminate or otherwise unhelpful; as ornaments when definitions are helpful but of marginal weight compared with more traditional resources like the canons, precedent, legislative history, or agency deference; and as barriers that preclude inquiry into or reliance on other contextual resources, especially legislative history and agency guidance. Ornamental opinions (the largest category) typically locate dictionary analysis at the start of the Court’s reasoning, subtly conveying that the lexicographic method should matter more than other interpretive resources. Barrier opinions would have been inconceivable prior to 1987 but now occur with disturbing frequency: they elevate the justices’ reliance on definitions in a radically acontextual manner, ignoring persuasive interpretive evidence from the enactment process and from agency experience. Finally, the Article analyzes whether the Court’s patterns of inconsistent dictionary usage, and its tendency to cherry-pick definitions that support results reached on other grounds, distinguish dictionaries from high-profile interpretive resources such as canons and legislative history that have been criticized on a similar basis. We contend that dictionaries are different from a normative vantage point, essentially because of (i) how both wings of the Court have promoted them by featuring definitions frequently and prominently in opinions, and (ii) how dictionaries are effectively celebrated as an independently constituted source of objective meaning (unlike the canons as judicial branch creations and legislativ
1987年以前,最高法院对词典的使用几乎是不存在的,但在伦奎斯特和罗伯茨法院时代,词典的使用急剧增加,以至于多达三分之一的法定判决援引词典的定义。这种增长与文本主义的兴起及其对日常意义的强烈关注有关。本文从经验和理论的角度深入探讨了法院的新词典文化。我们的发现包括:(a)虽然文本主义法官是最高的词典使用者,但目的主义法官引用词典定义的频率相当;(b)在刑法领域,词典的使用尤其频繁,起到了我们所说的“通知”功能;(c)字典的使用总体上是特别的和主观的。我们展示了法院使用词典的模式如何反映了一种偶然形式的机会主义行为:大法官们几乎总是引用一本或最多两本词典,他们有不同的个人品牌偏好,他们经常偏离,他们似乎交替使用普通词典和法律词典,他们在引用法定制定时期的版本和即时案件提交时的版本方面缺乏连贯的立场。然后,文章进行了详细的理论回顾,对法官如何使用词典进行了创新的功能分析:当词典的含义不确定或在其他方面没有帮助时,作为中转站;当定义是有用的,但与更传统的资源(如教规、先例、立法历史或机构服从)相比,其重要性微不足道时,作为装饰品;并且作为阻碍调查或依赖其他背景资源的障碍,特别是立法历史和机构指导。装饰性意见(最大的一类)通常将词典分析置于法院推理的开始,巧妙地传达词典编纂方法应该比其他解释资源更重要。障碍意见在1987年之前是不可想象的,但现在却以令人不安的频率出现:它们以一种完全情境化的方式提升了法官对定义的依赖,忽视了来自制定过程和机构经验的有说服力的解释性证据。最后,本文分析了最高法院不一致使用词典的模式,以及它倾向于挑选支持其他理由得出的结果的定义,是否将词典与备受瞩目的解释资源(如教规和立法史)区分开来,这些资源在类似的基础上受到了批评。我们认为,字典不同于规范的优势,主要是因为(i)法院的两翼如何通过在意见中频繁突出定义来促进它们,以及(ii)字典如何有效地作为独立构成的客观意义来源而受到赞扬(不像作为司法部门创造的教规和作为国会产品的立法史)。然而,我们的研究结果表明,词典使用作为启发式和权威的形象是海市蜃楼。词典定义的崇高地位与法院在实践中使用它们的高度主观方式之间的这种对比反映了对词典固有局限性的关注不足,其他学者和一些上诉法官已经指出了这些局限性。此外,法官的主观词典文化很可能会误导律师,他们面临着为法官审查构建论据的责任。文章最后提出了一个三步走的计划,让最高法院养成一种更健康的方法来改掉查字典的习惯。
{"title":"Oasis or Mirage: The Supreme Court's Thirst for Dictionaries in the Rehnquist and Roberts Eras","authors":"J. Brudney, L. Baum","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2195644","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2195644","url":null,"abstract":"The Supreme Court’s use of dictionaries, virtually non-existent before 1987, has dramatically increased during the Rehnquist and Roberts Court eras to the point where as many as one-third of statutory decisions invoke dictionary definitions. The increase is linked to the rise of textualism and its intense focus on ordinary meaning. This Article explores the Court’s new dictionary culture in depth from empirical and doctrinal perspectives. Among our findings are (a) while textualist justices are the highest dictionary users, purposivist justices invoke dictionary definitions with comparable frequency; (b) dictionary use is especially heavy in the criminal law area, serving what we describe as a Notice function; (c) dictionary use overall is strikingly ad hoc and subjective. We demonstrate how the Court’s patterns of dictionary usage reflect a casual form of opportunistic conduct: the justices almost always invoke one or at most two dictionaries, they have varied individual brand preferences from which they often depart, they seem to use general and legal dictionaries interchangeably, and they lack a coherent position on citing to editions from the time of statutory enactment versus the time the instant case was filed.The Article then conducts a detailed doctrinal review, leading to an innovative functional analysis of how the justices use dictionaries: as way stations when dictionary meanings are indeterminate or otherwise unhelpful; as ornaments when definitions are helpful but of marginal weight compared with more traditional resources like the canons, precedent, legislative history, or agency deference; and as barriers that preclude inquiry into or reliance on other contextual resources, especially legislative history and agency guidance. Ornamental opinions (the largest category) typically locate dictionary analysis at the start of the Court’s reasoning, subtly conveying that the lexicographic method should matter more than other interpretive resources. Barrier opinions would have been inconceivable prior to 1987 but now occur with disturbing frequency: they elevate the justices’ reliance on definitions in a radically acontextual manner, ignoring persuasive interpretive evidence from the enactment process and from agency experience. Finally, the Article analyzes whether the Court’s patterns of inconsistent dictionary usage, and its tendency to cherry-pick definitions that support results reached on other grounds, distinguish dictionaries from high-profile interpretive resources such as canons and legislative history that have been criticized on a similar basis. We contend that dictionaries are different from a normative vantage point, essentially because of (i) how both wings of the Court have promoted them by featuring definitions frequently and prominently in opinions, and (ii) how dictionaries are effectively celebrated as an independently constituted source of objective meaning (unlike the canons as judicial branch creations and legislativ","PeriodicalId":75324,"journal":{"name":"William and Mary law review","volume":"55 1","pages":"483"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2013-01-02","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67979156","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 17
Privacy as a Tool for Antidiscrimination 隐私作为反歧视的工具
Pub Date : 2013-01-01 DOI: 10.2139/ssrn.2263583
Jessica Roberts
Traditionally, laws that protect privacy and laws that prohibit discrimination have been considered distinct kinds of legal protections. This Essay challenges that binary on both practical and theoretical grounds. Using the Genetic Information Nondiscrimination Act (GINA) as a case study, it argues that lawmakers can use privacy law to further antidiscrimination goals. GINA, which prohibits geneticinformation discrimination in health insurance and employment, does more than simply outlaw discriminatory conduct. It also prohibits employers from requiring—or even requesting—their employees’ genetic information. While GINA’s privacy and antidiscrimination protections have previously been viewed as discrete, this Essay reads them in concert, arguing that restricting access to information about protected status can thwart future discrimination by denying potential discriminators the very information they would use to discriminate. Informed by this perspective, the Essay explores the advantages and disadvantages of using privacy law as a tool for antidiscrimination, in the context of genetic information and beyond. Finally, the Essay concludes that the weaknesses endemic to privacy law might be addressed by adopting an explicit antidiscrimination purpose. Thus, just as advocates of antidiscrimination may look to privacy law, advocates of privacy protections can look to antidiscrimination. * Assistant Professor of Law, University of Houston Law Center. Thank you to Aaron Bruhl, Brad Areheart, Jessica Clarke, Dave Fagundes, and Mark Rothstein for reading and commenting on drafts. I presented early versions of this Essay during the 3rd Annual National Conference on Genetics, Ethics, & the Law at the University of Virginia Law School and the 2013 ASU Legal Scholars Conference, so my gratitude likewise goes to the participants of those workshops. Many thanks to Chelsea Averill and Zachary White for research assistance and Emily Lawson for library help. ii PRIVACY 1 August 2013
传统上,保护隐私的法律和禁止歧视的法律被认为是不同种类的法律保护。本文从实践和理论两个方面对这种二元对立提出了挑战。以《遗传信息非歧视法案》(GINA)为例,它认为立法者可以利用隐私法来进一步实现反歧视目标。GINA禁止在医疗保险和就业方面的基因信息歧视,它不仅仅是禁止歧视行为。它还禁止雇主要求——甚至要求——员工提供基因信息。虽然GINA的隐私保护和反歧视保护以前被视为是分开的,但本文将它们结合起来,认为限制获取有关受保护状态的信息可以通过阻止潜在的歧视者获得他们用来歧视的信息来阻止未来的歧视。根据这一观点,本文探讨了在遗传信息和其他背景下使用隐私法作为反歧视工具的优点和缺点。最后,本文得出结论,隐私法特有的弱点可以通过采用明确的反歧视目的来解决。因此,正如反歧视的倡导者可能会关注隐私法一样,隐私保护的倡导者也可以关注反歧视。休斯顿大学法律中心法学助理教授。感谢Aaron Bruhl, Brad Areheart, Jessica Clarke, Dave Fagundes和Mark Rothstein对草稿的阅读和评论。我在弗吉尼亚大学法学院举行的第三届全国遗传学、伦理学和法律年度会议和2013年亚利桑那州立大学法律学者会议上展示了这篇文章的早期版本,所以我也要感谢那些研讨会的参与者。非常感谢Chelsea Averill和Zachary White的研究协助和Emily Lawson的图书馆帮助。ii隐私2013年8月1日
{"title":"Privacy as a Tool for Antidiscrimination","authors":"Jessica Roberts","doi":"10.2139/ssrn.2263583","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2263583","url":null,"abstract":"Traditionally, laws that protect privacy and laws that prohibit discrimination have been considered distinct kinds of legal protections. This Essay challenges that binary on both practical and theoretical grounds. Using the Genetic Information Nondiscrimination Act (GINA) as a case study, it argues that lawmakers can use privacy law to further antidiscrimination goals. GINA, which prohibits geneticinformation discrimination in health insurance and employment, does more than simply outlaw discriminatory conduct. It also prohibits employers from requiring—or even requesting—their employees’ genetic information. While GINA’s privacy and antidiscrimination protections have previously been viewed as discrete, this Essay reads them in concert, arguing that restricting access to information about protected status can thwart future discrimination by denying potential discriminators the very information they would use to discriminate. Informed by this perspective, the Essay explores the advantages and disadvantages of using privacy law as a tool for antidiscrimination, in the context of genetic information and beyond. Finally, the Essay concludes that the weaknesses endemic to privacy law might be addressed by adopting an explicit antidiscrimination purpose. Thus, just as advocates of antidiscrimination may look to privacy law, advocates of privacy protections can look to antidiscrimination. * Assistant Professor of Law, University of Houston Law Center. Thank you to Aaron Bruhl, Brad Areheart, Jessica Clarke, Dave Fagundes, and Mark Rothstein for reading and commenting on drafts. I presented early versions of this Essay during the 3rd Annual National Conference on Genetics, Ethics, & the Law at the University of Virginia Law School and the 2013 ASU Legal Scholars Conference, so my gratitude likewise goes to the participants of those workshops. Many thanks to Chelsea Averill and Zachary White for research assistance and Emily Lawson for library help. ii PRIVACY 1 August 2013","PeriodicalId":75324,"journal":{"name":"William and Mary law review","volume":"1 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2013-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"68042397","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Provocation Manslaughter as Partial Justification and Partial Excuse 挑衅过失杀人作为部分正当理由和部分借口
Pub Date : 2012-08-16 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2130692
Ian P. Farrell, Mitchell N. Berman
The partial defense of provocation provides that a person who kills in the heat of passion brought on by legally adequate provocation is guilty of manslaughter rather than murder. The defense traces back to the twelfth century and exists today, in some form, in almost every U.S. state and other common law jurisdictions. But long history and wide application have not produced agreement on the rationale for the doctrine. To the contrary, the search for a coherent and satisfying rationale remains among the main occupations of criminal law theorists.The dominant scholarly view holds that provocation is best explained and defended as a partial excuse on the grounds that the killer’s inflamed emotional state so compromised his ability to conform his conduct to the demands of reason and law as to render him substantially less blameworthy for his conduct. In contrast,a small minority of scholars have maintained, without significant argumentative support, that provocation is best understood as a partial justification on the ground that the provoked killing is less wrongful than is an unprovoked killing, ceteris paribus. Recently, other commentators have argued that provocation mitigation is neither partial excuse nor partial justification.Against all of these familiar positions, we argue that partial excuse and partial justification are necessary and sufficient conditions for provocation manslaughter. In our view, an intentional killing deserves to be punished and labeled as manslaughter rather than murder only when, because of provocation, this particular killing is significantly less wrongful than the standard intentional killing and when, because of the actor’s partial lack of control, he is less blameworthy for committing an act that remains all-things-considered wrongful. In elaborating and defending our account, we rebut the oft-repeated but rarely challenged propositions that justification and excuse, even in partial forms, are mutually exclusive, and that the very notion of partial justification is incoherent. We also draw forth implications for how the sentencing ranges for murder and manslaughter should be related.
对挑衅的部分辩护规定,一个人在法律上适当的挑衅引起的激情下杀人是过失杀人罪,而不是谋杀罪。这种辩护可以追溯到12世纪,并以某种形式存在于美国几乎每一个州和其他普通法管辖区。但是,长期的历史和广泛的应用并没有对这一学说的基本原理产生一致意见。相反,寻找连贯和令人满意的基本原理仍然是刑法理论家的主要职业之一。占主导地位的学术观点认为,挑衅是最好的解释和辩护,作为一个部分的借口,理由是,杀手的愤怒的情绪状态损害了他的能力,使他的行为符合理性和法律的要求,从而使他对自己的行为基本上不应受到指责。相比之下,少数学者在没有充分论证支持的情况下坚持认为,挑衅最好被理解为部分正当理由,理由是挑起的杀戮比非挑起的杀戮更不违法,其他条件相同。最近,其他评论员认为,减少挑衅既不是部分借口,也不是部分理由。针对这些常见的立场,我们认为部分辩解和部分正当是挑衅过失杀人的必要和充分条件。在我们看来,故意杀人应该受到惩罚,并被标记为过失杀人,而不是谋杀,只有当,由于挑衅,这种特殊的杀人比标准的故意杀人的错误程度要小得多,并且,由于行为人部分缺乏控制,他犯下的行为仍然被认为是错误的,应该受到较少的指责。在阐述和辩护我们的解释时,我们反驳了经常被重复但很少受到挑战的命题,即辩护和借口,即使是部分形式,也是相互排斥的,部分辩护的概念本身就是不连贯的。我们还提出了谋杀和过失杀人的量刑范围应该如何相关的含义。
{"title":"Provocation Manslaughter as Partial Justification and Partial Excuse","authors":"Ian P. Farrell, Mitchell N. Berman","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2130692","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2130692","url":null,"abstract":"The partial defense of provocation provides that a person who kills in the heat of passion brought on by legally adequate provocation is guilty of manslaughter rather than murder. The defense traces back to the twelfth century and exists today, in some form, in almost every U.S. state and other common law jurisdictions. But long history and wide application have not produced agreement on the rationale for the doctrine. To the contrary, the search for a coherent and satisfying rationale remains among the main occupations of criminal law theorists.The dominant scholarly view holds that provocation is best explained and defended as a partial excuse on the grounds that the killer’s inflamed emotional state so compromised his ability to conform his conduct to the demands of reason and law as to render him substantially less blameworthy for his conduct. In contrast,a small minority of scholars have maintained, without significant argumentative support, that provocation is best understood as a partial justification on the ground that the provoked killing is less wrongful than is an unprovoked killing, ceteris paribus. Recently, other commentators have argued that provocation mitigation is neither partial excuse nor partial justification.Against all of these familiar positions, we argue that partial excuse and partial justification are necessary and sufficient conditions for provocation manslaughter. In our view, an intentional killing deserves to be punished and labeled as manslaughter rather than murder only when, because of provocation, this particular killing is significantly less wrongful than the standard intentional killing and when, because of the actor’s partial lack of control, he is less blameworthy for committing an act that remains all-things-considered wrongful. In elaborating and defending our account, we rebut the oft-repeated but rarely challenged propositions that justification and excuse, even in partial forms, are mutually exclusive, and that the very notion of partial justification is incoherent. We also draw forth implications for how the sentencing ranges for murder and manslaughter should be related.","PeriodicalId":75324,"journal":{"name":"William and Mary law review","volume":"52 1","pages":"1027"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2012-08-16","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67932858","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 10
A General Theory of Governance: Due Process and Lawmaking Power 治理的一般理论:正当程序与立法权
Pub Date : 2012-08-06 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2125474
L. Weinberg
This replaces an unauthorized heavily cut upload which I must disclaim. A late draft, this may be somewhat closer to my intention than the published piece as well.This Article proposes a general theory describing the nature and sources of law in American courts. Erie Railroad Co. v. Tompkins is rejected for this purpose. Better, more general theory is available, flowing from the Due Process Clauses. At its narrowest, the proposed theory is consonant with Erie but generalizes it, embracing federal as well as state law and statutory as well as decisional law in both state and federal courts. More broadly, beyond this unification of systemic thinking, the interest-analytic methodology characteristic of due process extends to a range of substantive constitutional problems. These include problems concerning both the intrinsic sources of power and the individual rights that are power’s extrinsic limits. This Article argues, further, that in rights-based constitutional litigation, substantial scrutiny should become, and as a practical matter is, the general rule, and that certain economic rights should have the benefit of substantial scrutiny. Among the current and recent cases briefly discussed are Sebelius, the “Obamacare” case; Morrison, the Virginia Tech rape case; Kiobel, the Nigerian torture case; Kelo, the failed redevelopment case; Astrue, the in vitro child Social Security case, and Arizona v. U.S., the immigration case.
这取代了未经授权的大量剪切上传,我必须否认。一个较晚的草稿,这可能比发表的文章更接近我的意图。本文提出了一种描述美国法院法律的性质和渊源的一般理论。伊利铁路公司诉汤普金斯案因此被驳回。从正当程序条款中可以得到更好、更一般的理论。从最狭义的角度来看,该理论与伊利法一致,但对其进行了概括,包括联邦法和州法,以及州和联邦法院的成文法和判决法。更广泛地说,除了这种系统思维的统一之外,正当程序所特有的利益分析方法延伸到一系列实质性宪法问题。这些问题既涉及权力的内在来源,也涉及作为权力外在限制的个人权利。本文进一步认为,在以权利为基础的宪法诉讼中,实质性审查应该成为一般规则,并且作为一个实际问题,某些经济权利应该具有实质性审查的好处。简要讨论的当前和最近的案例包括“奥巴马医改”案西贝利厄斯;莫里森,弗吉尼亚理工大学强奸案;尼日利亚酷刑案Kiobel;失败的重建案Kelo;阿斯特鲁,试管婴儿社会保障案,以及亚利桑那诉美国移民案。
{"title":"A General Theory of Governance: Due Process and Lawmaking Power","authors":"L. Weinberg","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2125474","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2125474","url":null,"abstract":"This replaces an unauthorized heavily cut upload which I must disclaim. A late draft, this may be somewhat closer to my intention than the published piece as well.This Article proposes a general theory describing the nature and sources of law in American courts. Erie Railroad Co. v. Tompkins is rejected for this purpose. Better, more general theory is available, flowing from the Due Process Clauses. At its narrowest, the proposed theory is consonant with Erie but generalizes it, embracing federal as well as state law and statutory as well as decisional law in both state and federal courts. More broadly, beyond this unification of systemic thinking, the interest-analytic methodology characteristic of due process extends to a range of substantive constitutional problems. These include problems concerning both the intrinsic sources of power and the individual rights that are power’s extrinsic limits. This Article argues, further, that in rights-based constitutional litigation, substantial scrutiny should become, and as a practical matter is, the general rule, and that certain economic rights should have the benefit of substantial scrutiny. Among the current and recent cases briefly discussed are Sebelius, the “Obamacare” case; Morrison, the Virginia Tech rape case; Kiobel, the Nigerian torture case; Kelo, the failed redevelopment case; Astrue, the in vitro child Social Security case, and Arizona v. U.S., the immigration case.","PeriodicalId":75324,"journal":{"name":"William and Mary law review","volume":"54 1","pages":"1057"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2012-08-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.2139/SSRN.2125474","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67927693","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Why Jurisprudence Doesn't Matter for Customary International Law 为什么法理学对习惯国际法不重要
Pub Date : 2012-06-09 DOI: 10.2139/SSRN.2080476
S. Walt
It is often thought that the judicial recognition of customary international law depends on jurisprudential assumptions about the nature of legal norms, law, and legal validity. This is a mistake. The limits on a judicial reliance on customary international law are constitutional or evidentiary, not jurisprudential. Although Erie Railroad Co. v. Tompkins fairly can be read to require domestic authorization for customary international law to have domestic legal effect, the case and its reasoning do not rely on commitments to a theory of law. Acceptance of the claims of legal positivism is neither necessary nor sufficient for Erie’s result, nor for its application to customary international law. In fact, reliance on positivism has an unwelcome consequence for the legally binding character of customary international law even on states. Finally, the same conception of law or legal validity can ground different views about the relation between international and domestic law. Positions on the priority of customary international law are determined by views about that relation, not by views on the source of its authority. Taken together, these considerations suggest that jurisprudence isn’t needed to answer the questions that courts and legal authorities ask about customary international law's content, the legal obligations it creates, and its domestic legal effect.
人们通常认为,对习惯国际法的司法承认取决于对法律规范、法律和法律效力性质的法理学假设。这是一个错误。对习惯国际法的司法依赖的限制是宪法或证据,而不是法理学。虽然伊利铁路公司诉汤普金斯案可以被公平地解读为要求习惯国际法具有国内法律效力的国内授权,但该案件及其推理并不依赖于对法律理论的承诺。接受法律实证主义的主张既不是伊利的结果的必要条件,也不是它适用于习惯国际法的充分条件。事实上,对实证主义的依赖对习惯国际法的法律约束力(甚至对国家)产生了不受欢迎的后果。最后,同样的法律概念或法律效力的概念可能会导致对国际法与国内法关系的不同看法。关于习惯国际法优先次序的立场取决于对这种关系的看法,而不是对其权威来源的看法。综上所述,这些考虑表明,法院和法律当局对习惯国际法的内容、它所创造的法律义务及其国内法律效力所提出的问题并不需要法理学来回答。
{"title":"Why Jurisprudence Doesn't Matter for Customary International Law","authors":"S. Walt","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2080476","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2080476","url":null,"abstract":"It is often thought that the judicial recognition of customary international law depends on jurisprudential assumptions about the nature of legal norms, law, and legal validity. This is a mistake. The limits on a judicial reliance on customary international law are constitutional or evidentiary, not jurisprudential. Although Erie Railroad Co. v. Tompkins fairly can be read to require domestic authorization for customary international law to have domestic legal effect, the case and its reasoning do not rely on commitments to a theory of law. Acceptance of the claims of legal positivism is neither necessary nor sufficient for Erie’s result, nor for its application to customary international law. In fact, reliance on positivism has an unwelcome consequence for the legally binding character of customary international law even on states. Finally, the same conception of law or legal validity can ground different views about the relation between international and domestic law. Positions on the priority of customary international law are determined by views about that relation, not by views on the source of its authority. Taken together, these considerations suggest that jurisprudence isn’t needed to answer the questions that courts and legal authorities ask about customary international law's content, the legal obligations it creates, and its domestic legal effect.","PeriodicalId":75324,"journal":{"name":"William and Mary law review","volume":"54 1","pages":"1023"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2012-06-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"67903004","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
期刊
William and Mary law review
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1