首页 > 最新文献

Annals of Science最新文献

英文 中文
The elements: a visual history of their discovery 元素:它们发现的视觉历史
IF 0.3 3区 哲学 Q2 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2022-06-18 DOI: 10.1080/00033790.2022.2087903
Evan Hepler-Smith
{"title":"The elements: a visual history of their discovery","authors":"Evan Hepler-Smith","doi":"10.1080/00033790.2022.2087903","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/00033790.2022.2087903","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":8086,"journal":{"name":"Annals of Science","volume":"79 1","pages":"406 - 408"},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2022-06-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"42418274","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Cold War social science: transnational entanglements 冷战社会科学:跨国纠葛
IF 0.3 3区 哲学 Q2 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2022-06-14 DOI: 10.1080/00033790.2022.2087904
J. Krige
{"title":"Cold War social science: transnational entanglements","authors":"J. Krige","doi":"10.1080/00033790.2022.2087904","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/00033790.2022.2087904","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":8086,"journal":{"name":"Annals of Science","volume":"79 1","pages":"416 - 417"},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2022-06-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43064060","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Confessionalization and comets. John Bainbridge on the comet of 1618 忏悔和彗星。约翰·班布里奇在1618年的彗星上
IF 0.3 3区 哲学 Q2 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2022-06-12 DOI: 10.1080/00033790.2022.2086300
R. Vermij, P. Vieth
ABSTRACT At first sight, the English astronomer John Bainbridge's treatise on the great comet of 1618 appears rather idiosyncratic. It regards the comet as a favourable omen and applies an astrological explanation that is completely metaphorical. At closer look, however, Bainbridge's interpretation appears well in line with the meaning commonly attributed to comets at the time. We should realize that an important function of the discourse on prodigious phenomena, such as comets, was to uphold and strengthen the confessional social order. Moreover, the treatise was addressed to the King rather than to the common population. To understand the early modern interpretation of comets, the processes of confessionalization and de-confessionalization deserve more consideration.
乍一看,英国天文学家约翰·班布里奇关于1618年大彗星的论文显得相当独特。它认为彗星是一个有利的预兆,并采用一种完全隐喻的占星术解释。然而,仔细观察,班布里奇的解释似乎与当时普遍赋予彗星的含义完全一致。我们应该认识到,彗星等巨象话语的一个重要功能是维护和加强忏悔的社会秩序。此外,这篇论文是写给国王而不是普通民众的。要理解近代早期对彗星的解释,忏悔录和去忏悔录的过程值得更多的考虑。
{"title":"Confessionalization and comets. John Bainbridge on the comet of 1618","authors":"R. Vermij, P. Vieth","doi":"10.1080/00033790.2022.2086300","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/00033790.2022.2086300","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT At first sight, the English astronomer John Bainbridge's treatise on the great comet of 1618 appears rather idiosyncratic. It regards the comet as a favourable omen and applies an astrological explanation that is completely metaphorical. At closer look, however, Bainbridge's interpretation appears well in line with the meaning commonly attributed to comets at the time. We should realize that an important function of the discourse on prodigious phenomena, such as comets, was to uphold and strengthen the confessional social order. Moreover, the treatise was addressed to the King rather than to the common population. To understand the early modern interpretation of comets, the processes of confessionalization and de-confessionalization deserve more consideration.","PeriodicalId":8086,"journal":{"name":"Annals of Science","volume":"79 1","pages":"275 - 291"},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2022-06-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46894110","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Mechanism. A visual, lexical and conceptual history 机制。视觉,词汇和概念的历史
IF 0.3 3区 哲学 Q2 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2022-05-20 DOI: 10.1080/00033790.2022.2078506
S. Roux
Domenico Bertoloni Meli’sMechanism. A Visual, Lexical and Conceptual History began as the A. W. Mellon Distinguished Lectures in the History of Science presented at the University of Pittsburgh in 2006. It is focused on the emergence, development, and systematization of the notion of mechanism in the seventeenth century, particularly in anatomy, medicine and the life sciences. The first chapter is devoted to defining mechanism by comparison with allied notions – e.g. machines or artificial devices – and by contrast with others – e.g. faculties of the soul, vital properties or teleological explanations – but also to underlining the ambivalence of ferments, active principles, seminal principles and plastic virtues, all of which could refer to something immaterial yet also be ‘mechanized’. An excursus on Galen opposes mechanisms to the immaterial faculties of the soul, and some of the tensions involved in the search for mechanisms are revealed – the tension between the notions that intervene in the explanations of macroscopic phenomena and the ambition to reduce these phenomena to the motions of microscopic corpuscles endowed with merely quantitative properties, but also the tension between imperfect machines made by us and the perfect machines of nature made by God. The second chapter explores the affinity between visual representations and mechanisms, which consist of spatial arrangements of moving parts: after a nuanced view of the historiographical controversy between David Edgerton and Michael Mahoney about the effect new forms of representation might have had on the transformation of knowledge during the Scientific Revolution, the bulk of this chapter analyses anatomical representations in the long century between Andreas Vesalius (1514–1564) and Robert Hooke (1635–1703). The third chapter studies the emergence of the term ‘mechanism’ at the beginnings of the Royal Society, whether it intervened in the explanations of specific natural phenomena or in discussions of philosophical and theological issues; two theses, quite correct in my opinion, are defended: first, the thesis that what is mechanical is defined by contrast with what is not mechanical, and, second, the thesis that what is not mechanical has varied in history. The main figure of the fourth and last chapter is Marcello Malpighi (1628–1694), to whom Bertoloni Meli had already devoted two books; the present chapter focuses on the generation of animals, which brings together different threads previously encountered. This brief book (142 pages, including a number of black and white illustrations, plus notes, bibliography and index) is very rich in detailed analyses. It is sure to impress even the most critical of readers in the history of science and medicine. More generally, it is also incisive and thought-provoking because of some of its methodological commitments, which were already present in Bertoloni Meli’s previous books. First, as in Thinking with Objects, the reader is invited
Domenico Bertoloni Meli的机制。《视觉、词汇和概念史》始于2006年在匹兹堡大学举行的A·w·梅隆科学史杰出讲座。它的重点是17世纪机制概念的出现、发展和系统化,特别是在解剖学、医学和生命科学方面。第一章致力于通过与相关概念(如机器或人工设备)的比较来定义机制,并通过与其他概念(如灵魂的能力、生命属性或目的论解释)的对比来定义机制,但也强调了发酵、活动原则、种子原则和可塑性美德的矛盾心理,所有这些都可以指非物质的东西,但也可以被“机械化”。关于盖伦的一篇短途文章将机制与灵魂的非物质能力进行了对比,揭示了寻找机制所涉及的一些紧张关系——干预宏观现象解释的概念与将这些现象简化为仅具有定量特性的微观微粒运动的野心之间的紧张关系,以及我们制造的不完美机器与上帝制造的完美自然机器之间的紧张关系。第二章探讨了视觉表征与机制之间的关系,机制是由运动部件的空间安排构成的:在对大卫·埃杰顿和迈克尔·马奥尼之间关于科学革命期间新表现形式可能对知识转变产生的影响的史学争论进行细致的分析之后,本章的大部分内容分析了安德里亚斯·维萨里(Andreas Vesalius, 1514-1564)和罗伯特·胡克(Robert Hooke, 1635-1703)之间漫长世纪的解剖学表现。第三章研究了“机制”一词在皇家学会成立之初的出现,无论它是否介入对特定自然现象的解释,还是在哲学和神学问题的讨论中;有两个论点在我看来是非常正确的:第一,机械是通过与非机械的对比来定义的论点;第二,非机械的论点在历史上是不同的。第四章也是最后一章的主要人物是马塞洛·马尔皮吉(1628-1694),贝托洛尼·梅利已经为他写了两本书;本章的重点是动物的世代,它汇集了以前遇到的不同线索。这本简短的书(142页,包括一些黑白插图,加上注释,参考书目和索引)非常丰富的详细分析。即使是科学史和医学史上最挑剔的读者,它也一定会给他们留下深刻的印象。更一般地说,它也是深刻的和发人深省的,因为它的一些方法论承诺,已经出现在Bertoloni Meli之前的书中。首先,就像在《用对象思考》中一样,读者被邀请去关注那些让科学家在他们的日常智力生活中忙碌的小问题,而不是那些构成科学规划视野的几个一般陈述。《用物体思考》一书的一个重要观点是,要重建17世纪的力学,人们不仅要考虑一些基本的运动定律,还要考虑像牛顿这样的小物体
{"title":"Mechanism. A visual, lexical and conceptual history","authors":"S. Roux","doi":"10.1080/00033790.2022.2078506","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/00033790.2022.2078506","url":null,"abstract":"Domenico Bertoloni Meli’sMechanism. A Visual, Lexical and Conceptual History began as the A. W. Mellon Distinguished Lectures in the History of Science presented at the University of Pittsburgh in 2006. It is focused on the emergence, development, and systematization of the notion of mechanism in the seventeenth century, particularly in anatomy, medicine and the life sciences. The first chapter is devoted to defining mechanism by comparison with allied notions – e.g. machines or artificial devices – and by contrast with others – e.g. faculties of the soul, vital properties or teleological explanations – but also to underlining the ambivalence of ferments, active principles, seminal principles and plastic virtues, all of which could refer to something immaterial yet also be ‘mechanized’. An excursus on Galen opposes mechanisms to the immaterial faculties of the soul, and some of the tensions involved in the search for mechanisms are revealed – the tension between the notions that intervene in the explanations of macroscopic phenomena and the ambition to reduce these phenomena to the motions of microscopic corpuscles endowed with merely quantitative properties, but also the tension between imperfect machines made by us and the perfect machines of nature made by God. The second chapter explores the affinity between visual representations and mechanisms, which consist of spatial arrangements of moving parts: after a nuanced view of the historiographical controversy between David Edgerton and Michael Mahoney about the effect new forms of representation might have had on the transformation of knowledge during the Scientific Revolution, the bulk of this chapter analyses anatomical representations in the long century between Andreas Vesalius (1514–1564) and Robert Hooke (1635–1703). The third chapter studies the emergence of the term ‘mechanism’ at the beginnings of the Royal Society, whether it intervened in the explanations of specific natural phenomena or in discussions of philosophical and theological issues; two theses, quite correct in my opinion, are defended: first, the thesis that what is mechanical is defined by contrast with what is not mechanical, and, second, the thesis that what is not mechanical has varied in history. The main figure of the fourth and last chapter is Marcello Malpighi (1628–1694), to whom Bertoloni Meli had already devoted two books; the present chapter focuses on the generation of animals, which brings together different threads previously encountered. This brief book (142 pages, including a number of black and white illustrations, plus notes, bibliography and index) is very rich in detailed analyses. It is sure to impress even the most critical of readers in the history of science and medicine. More generally, it is also incisive and thought-provoking because of some of its methodological commitments, which were already present in Bertoloni Meli’s previous books. First, as in Thinking with Objects, the reader is invited ","PeriodicalId":8086,"journal":{"name":"Annals of Science","volume":"79 1","pages":"411 - 413"},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2022-05-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"41329262","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Kindred fatalisms: debating science, Islam, and free will in the Darwinian era 温和的宿命论:达尔文时代的科学、伊斯兰教和自由意志辩论
IF 0.3 3区 哲学 Q2 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2022-05-12 DOI: 10.1080/00033790.2022.2075938
M. A. Yalcinkaya
ABSTRACT An important aspect of the nineteenth century debate on the relationship between science and religion concerned the popularity of deterministic views among scientists. An integral part of Comte's positivism, the idea of immutable laws that determined natural and social phenomena became an increasingly prevalent component of scientific perspectives in the Darwinian era. Referring to this tendency as ‘scientific fatalism,’ critics likened it to Calvinist predestination, which transformed the debate into one involving polemics about different branches of Christianity as well. This paper focuses on a neglected aspect of this debate, namely, the role that references to Islam and Turks played in it. ‘Mohammedan fatalism,’ already a common theme in justifications of colonialism, promptly became a tool with which to condemn new scientific views. Comparing French, British, and American writings on the topic, the paper illustrates that while there emerged approaches that praised the fatalism of Muslims while making a case for scientific determinism, most scientists and thinkers resorted to condemning the fatalism of Muslims in order to distinguish their views from it. In this respect, the paper demonstrates how political and religious discourses played a significant part in the shaping of scientific discourse in the Victorian era.
19世纪关于科学与宗教关系的辩论的一个重要方面涉及科学家中确定性观点的流行。作为孔特实证主义的一个组成部分,决定自然和社会现象的不可变定律在达尔文时代成为科学观点中越来越普遍的组成部分。批评者将这种倾向称为“科学宿命论”,并将其比作加尔文主义的宿命论,后者将这场辩论转变为关于基督教不同分支的争论。本文关注这场辩论中被忽视的一个方面,即提及伊斯兰教和土耳其人在其中所起的作用。“穆罕默德宿命论”已经是殖民主义辩护中的一个常见主题,但很快就成为了谴责新科学观点的工具。通过比较法国、英国和美国关于这一主题的著作,本文表明,尽管出现了赞扬穆斯林宿命论的方法,同时为科学决定论辩护,但大多数科学家和思想家都诉诸于谴责穆斯林的宿命论,以区分他们的观点,本文论证了政治和宗教话语在维多利亚时代科学话语的形成过程中是如何发挥重要作用的。
{"title":"Kindred fatalisms: debating science, Islam, and free will in the Darwinian era","authors":"M. A. Yalcinkaya","doi":"10.1080/00033790.2022.2075938","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/00033790.2022.2075938","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT An important aspect of the nineteenth century debate on the relationship between science and religion concerned the popularity of deterministic views among scientists. An integral part of Comte's positivism, the idea of immutable laws that determined natural and social phenomena became an increasingly prevalent component of scientific perspectives in the Darwinian era. Referring to this tendency as ‘scientific fatalism,’ critics likened it to Calvinist predestination, which transformed the debate into one involving polemics about different branches of Christianity as well. This paper focuses on a neglected aspect of this debate, namely, the role that references to Islam and Turks played in it. ‘Mohammedan fatalism,’ already a common theme in justifications of colonialism, promptly became a tool with which to condemn new scientific views. Comparing French, British, and American writings on the topic, the paper illustrates that while there emerged approaches that praised the fatalism of Muslims while making a case for scientific determinism, most scientists and thinkers resorted to condemning the fatalism of Muslims in order to distinguish their views from it. In this respect, the paper demonstrates how political and religious discourses played a significant part in the shaping of scientific discourse in the Victorian era.","PeriodicalId":8086,"journal":{"name":"Annals of Science","volume":"79 1","pages":"364 - 385"},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2022-05-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47034460","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Inefficient Attentional Control Explains Verbal-Memory Deficits Among Military Veterans With Posttraumatic Reexperiencing Symptoms. 低效的注意力控制解释了创伤后再经历症状的退伍军人的语言记忆缺陷。
IF 0.9 3区 哲学 Q2 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2022-05-01 Epub Date: 2021-07-07 DOI: 10.1177/21677026211025018
Craig A Marquardt, Victor J Pokorny, Seth G Disner, Nathaniel W Nelson, Kathryn A McGuire, Scott R Sponheim

Among individuals with posttraumatic stress disorder (PTSD), verbal learning and memory are areas of weakness compared with other cognitive domains (e.g., visuospatial memory). In this study, previously deployed military veterans completed clinical assessments of word memory and vocabulary (n = 243) and a laboratory task measuring encoding, free recall, repetition priming, and recognition of words (n = 147). Impaired verbal memory was selectively related to reexperiencing symptoms of PTSD but was not associated with other symptom groupings or blast-induced traumatic brain injury. Implicit priming of response times following word repetition was also unrelated to clinical symptoms. Instead, slowed response times during encoding explained associations between reexperiencing and memory performance. These findings are consistent with alterations in attentional control explaining PTSD-related verbal-memory deficits. Such findings have implications for understanding trauma-focused psychotherapy and recovery, which may depend on efficient attentional processing of words to alter posttraumatic reexperiencing symptoms.

在创伤后应激障碍(PTSD)患者中,与其他认知领域(如视觉空间记忆)相比,言语学习和记忆是薄弱的领域。在这项研究中,以前部署的退伍军人完成了单词记忆和词汇的临床评估(n = 243)和实验室任务测量编码,自由回忆,重复启动和单词识别(n = 147)。言语记忆受损选择性地与PTSD症状的再经历相关,但与其他症状分组或爆炸引起的创伤性脑损伤无关。单词重复后的内隐启动反应时间也与临床症状无关。相反,编码过程中缓慢的反应时间解释了再体验和记忆表现之间的联系。这些发现与解释ptsd相关言语记忆缺陷的注意控制改变是一致的。这些发现对理解以创伤为中心的心理治疗和康复具有启示意义,这可能依赖于对文字的有效注意力处理来改变创伤后再体验症状。
{"title":"Inefficient Attentional Control Explains Verbal-Memory Deficits Among Military Veterans With Posttraumatic Reexperiencing Symptoms.","authors":"Craig A Marquardt, Victor J Pokorny, Seth G Disner, Nathaniel W Nelson, Kathryn A McGuire, Scott R Sponheim","doi":"10.1177/21677026211025018","DOIUrl":"10.1177/21677026211025018","url":null,"abstract":"<p><p>Among individuals with posttraumatic stress disorder (PTSD), verbal learning and memory are areas of weakness compared with other cognitive domains (e.g., visuospatial memory). In this study, previously deployed military veterans completed clinical assessments of word memory and vocabulary (<i>n</i> = 243) and a laboratory task measuring encoding, free recall, repetition priming, and recognition of words (<i>n</i> = 147). Impaired verbal memory was selectively related to reexperiencing symptoms of PTSD but was not associated with other symptom groupings or blast-induced traumatic brain injury. Implicit priming of response times following word repetition was also unrelated to clinical symptoms. Instead, slowed response times during encoding explained associations between reexperiencing and memory performance. These findings are consistent with alterations in attentional control explaining PTSD-related verbal-memory deficits. Such findings have implications for understanding trauma-focused psychotherapy and recovery, which may depend on efficient attentional processing of words to alter posttraumatic reexperiencing symptoms.</p>","PeriodicalId":8086,"journal":{"name":"Annals of Science","volume":"21 1","pages":"499-513"},"PeriodicalIF":0.9,"publicationDate":"2022-05-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC10663645/pdf/","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"80645474","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Minerva’s French Sisters: Women of Science in Enlightenment France 密涅瓦的法国姐妹:启蒙时期法国的科学女性
IF 0.3 3区 哲学 Q2 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2022-04-20 DOI: 10.1080/00033790.2022.2066178
M. Carlyle
cal analysis he proposes is ‘as complex and intellectually challenging as a philosophical one’ (p. 139). Third, to view the sciences as conceptual and theoretical structures does not commit one to conceptual or theoretical purity. The epistemic reliability of the sciences, but also their capacity to evolve in time while presenting a certain stability, derives from the way in which the sciences weave together diverse procedures into a coherent whole: mathematical models and computer simulations, observations and experiments, images, narratives andmetaphors, arguments and thought experiments, etc. From this point of view too, it is tempting to compare Mechanism with Thinking with Objects, even though the former concerns the life sciences, while the later deals with mechanics. Both books succeed in showing that at their best the sciences activate all the resources of our cognitive faculties, albeit in different ways according to the scientific fields. Mechanism thus shows that early modern mechanisms involved textual comparisons (for example to textiles, p. 21, or to musical instruments, pp. 57, 60, 68–69, 136, 141), visual illustrations (pp. 25–78), observations and experiments, whether it be the use of microscopes (pp. 21, 67–71, 77–78, 85–93, 119–120), the practice of ligatures (pp. 48–52, 140– 141), dissections and vivisections (pp. 12–15, 39–40, 59, 67) or injections (pp. 54, 60). It is this richness, complexity and flexibility that made the enterprise of searching for mechanisms a fruitful one. It helps correcting any misperception of mechanical philosophy as a grandiose, but somewhat vain, programme of reducing all natural phenomena to the motions of corpuscles endowed with merely quantitative properties. We can be grateful to Bertoloni Meli for having not only clarified the notion of mechanism, but also for having opened new perspectives on the mechanical philosophy. To conclude, I will make two general remarks. First, it is interesting that the same historian worked alternatively on early modern mechanics and on early modern life sciences, whereas today these disciplines are totally separated: Bertoloni Meli makes manifest the strong conceptual links that existed between mechanics and the life sciences in the early modern period, beyond their differences in style. Second,Mechanism is an important book not only for those working on the early modern period: the three methodological commitments I have just outlined form a discourse on method that will be useful to all those, philosophers and historians alike, who wish to make sense of the sciences as conceptual and theoretical structures.
他提出的卡尔分析“和哲学分析一样复杂和具有智力挑战性”(第139页)。第三,将科学视为概念和理论结构并不能保证概念或理论的纯粹性。科学的认识可靠性,以及它们在呈现一定稳定性的同时随时间进化的能力,源于科学将不同的程序编织成一个连贯的整体的方式:数学模型和计算机模拟、观察和实验、图像、叙事和隐喻、论点和思想实验等,人们很容易将“机制”与“用物体思考”进行比较,尽管前者涉及生命科学,而后者涉及力学。这两本书都成功地表明,科学在最佳状态下激活了我们认知能力的所有资源,尽管根据科学领域的不同,其方式不同。因此,机制表明,早期现代机制涉及文本比较(例如与纺织品,第21页,或与乐器,第57、60、68–69、136、141页)、视觉插图(第25–78页)、观察和实验,无论是显微镜的使用(第21、67–71、77–78、85–93、119–120页)、结扎术(第48–52、140–141页),解剖和活体解剖(第12-15、39-40、59、67页)或注射(第54、60页)。正是这种丰富性、复杂性和灵活性使寻找机制的事业富有成果。它有助于纠正人们对机械哲学的误解,认为它是一个宏大但有点徒劳的计划,将所有自然现象简化为仅具有定量性质的微粒的运动。我们应该感谢梅利不仅阐明了机械的概念,而且为机械哲学开辟了新的视角。最后,我将作两个一般性发言。首先,有趣的是,同一位历史学家交替研究早期现代力学和早期现代生命科学,而今天这些学科完全分离:Bertoloni Meli表明了力学和生命科学在早期现代时期存在的强大的概念联系,超越了它们的风格差异。其次,《机制》是一本重要的书,不仅适用于那些研究现代早期的人:我刚刚概述的三项方法论承诺形成了一篇关于方法的论述,对所有希望将科学理解为概念和理论结构的哲学家和历史学家都很有用。
{"title":"Minerva’s French Sisters: Women of Science in Enlightenment France","authors":"M. Carlyle","doi":"10.1080/00033790.2022.2066178","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/00033790.2022.2066178","url":null,"abstract":"cal analysis he proposes is ‘as complex and intellectually challenging as a philosophical one’ (p. 139). Third, to view the sciences as conceptual and theoretical structures does not commit one to conceptual or theoretical purity. The epistemic reliability of the sciences, but also their capacity to evolve in time while presenting a certain stability, derives from the way in which the sciences weave together diverse procedures into a coherent whole: mathematical models and computer simulations, observations and experiments, images, narratives andmetaphors, arguments and thought experiments, etc. From this point of view too, it is tempting to compare Mechanism with Thinking with Objects, even though the former concerns the life sciences, while the later deals with mechanics. Both books succeed in showing that at their best the sciences activate all the resources of our cognitive faculties, albeit in different ways according to the scientific fields. Mechanism thus shows that early modern mechanisms involved textual comparisons (for example to textiles, p. 21, or to musical instruments, pp. 57, 60, 68–69, 136, 141), visual illustrations (pp. 25–78), observations and experiments, whether it be the use of microscopes (pp. 21, 67–71, 77–78, 85–93, 119–120), the practice of ligatures (pp. 48–52, 140– 141), dissections and vivisections (pp. 12–15, 39–40, 59, 67) or injections (pp. 54, 60). It is this richness, complexity and flexibility that made the enterprise of searching for mechanisms a fruitful one. It helps correcting any misperception of mechanical philosophy as a grandiose, but somewhat vain, programme of reducing all natural phenomena to the motions of corpuscles endowed with merely quantitative properties. We can be grateful to Bertoloni Meli for having not only clarified the notion of mechanism, but also for having opened new perspectives on the mechanical philosophy. To conclude, I will make two general remarks. First, it is interesting that the same historian worked alternatively on early modern mechanics and on early modern life sciences, whereas today these disciplines are totally separated: Bertoloni Meli makes manifest the strong conceptual links that existed between mechanics and the life sciences in the early modern period, beyond their differences in style. Second,Mechanism is an important book not only for those working on the early modern period: the three methodological commitments I have just outlined form a discourse on method that will be useful to all those, philosophers and historians alike, who wish to make sense of the sciences as conceptual and theoretical structures.","PeriodicalId":8086,"journal":{"name":"Annals of Science","volume":"79 1","pages":"413 - 415"},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2022-04-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47602795","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
The poison trials: wonder drugs, experiment, and the battle for authority in renaissance science 毒药试验:神奇药物、实验和文艺复兴时期科学的权威之争
IF 0.3 3区 哲学 Q2 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2022-04-17 DOI: 10.1080/00033790.2022.2063388
Georgiana D. Hedesan
readership as an introduction to the history of the chemical elements and, more broadly, the history of chemistry. The brief length of sections would make for appropriate supplementary reading in history of science survey courses or science classes at secondary and university levels. Or just put it on a coffee table in home, office, or department, where visitors can peruse it for a new favourite element.
读者作为介绍化学元素的历史,更广泛地说,化学的历史。各节篇幅较短,可作为中学和大学的科学史概览课程或科学课的适当补充读物。或者只是把它放在家里、办公室或部门的咖啡桌上,游客可以在那里仔细阅读,寻找新的喜爱元素。
{"title":"The poison trials: wonder drugs, experiment, and the battle for authority in renaissance science","authors":"Georgiana D. Hedesan","doi":"10.1080/00033790.2022.2063388","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/00033790.2022.2063388","url":null,"abstract":"readership as an introduction to the history of the chemical elements and, more broadly, the history of chemistry. The brief length of sections would make for appropriate supplementary reading in history of science survey courses or science classes at secondary and university levels. Or just put it on a coffee table in home, office, or department, where visitors can peruse it for a new favourite element.","PeriodicalId":8086,"journal":{"name":"Annals of Science","volume":"79 1","pages":"408 - 410"},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2022-04-17","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46866803","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Conceptualizing paradigms: on reading Kuhn’s history of the quantum 概念化范式——读库恩的量子史
IF 0.3 3区 哲学 Q2 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2022-04-12 DOI: 10.1080/00033790.2022.2063945
Jan Potters
ABSTRACT In this article, I discuss the criticisms raised against Thomas Kuhn’s Black-Body Theory. These criticisms concern two issues: how to understand Planck’s position with regards to the quantization of energy in 1901, and how to understand the book’s relation to The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Both criticisms, I argue, concern the notion of a paradigm: the first concerns how Boltzmann acted as an exemplar for Planck, and the second whether the book provides a paradigm change. I will then argue that both criticisms presume a conceptualization of paradigms that does not align well with Kuhn’s conceptualization of it in both Structure and later work: they assume, more specifically, that sharing a paradigm presupposes sharing an interpretation of it, and that paradigm changes are essentially identical to gestalt switches. On the basis of this, I will then argue that the criticisms are misguided, that Kuhn’s position regarding Planck’s work is in fact quite close to the indetermination-view developed by some of his critics, and that the book fits Structure quite well. In conclusion, I will then reflect on how the narrative provided in Black-Body Theory connects with Kuhn’s views on the relation between history and philosophy of science.
摘要本文论述了对库恩的黑体理论提出的批评。这些批评涉及两个问题:如何理解普朗克关于1901年能量量子化的立场,以及如何理解这本书与《科学革命的结构》的关系。我认为,这两种批评都与范式的概念有关:第一种是关于玻尔兹曼如何作为普朗克的榜样,第二种是关于这本书是否提供了范式的改变。然后,我会争辩说,这两种批评都假设范式的概念化与库恩在《结构》和后来的作品中对其的概念化不太一致:更具体地说,他们假设共享范式的前提是共享对其的解释,范式的变化本质上与格式塔转换相同。基于此,我将认为这些批评是误导性的,库恩对普朗克工作的立场实际上与他的一些批评者提出的不确定性观点非常接近,这本书非常符合《结构》。最后,我将反思《黑体理论》中的叙述与库恩关于历史与科学哲学关系的观点是如何联系在一起的。
{"title":"Conceptualizing paradigms: on reading Kuhn’s history of the quantum","authors":"Jan Potters","doi":"10.1080/00033790.2022.2063945","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/00033790.2022.2063945","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT In this article, I discuss the criticisms raised against Thomas Kuhn’s Black-Body Theory. These criticisms concern two issues: how to understand Planck’s position with regards to the quantization of energy in 1901, and how to understand the book’s relation to The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Both criticisms, I argue, concern the notion of a paradigm: the first concerns how Boltzmann acted as an exemplar for Planck, and the second whether the book provides a paradigm change. I will then argue that both criticisms presume a conceptualization of paradigms that does not align well with Kuhn’s conceptualization of it in both Structure and later work: they assume, more specifically, that sharing a paradigm presupposes sharing an interpretation of it, and that paradigm changes are essentially identical to gestalt switches. On the basis of this, I will then argue that the criticisms are misguided, that Kuhn’s position regarding Planck’s work is in fact quite close to the indetermination-view developed by some of his critics, and that the book fits Structure quite well. In conclusion, I will then reflect on how the narrative provided in Black-Body Theory connects with Kuhn’s views on the relation between history and philosophy of science.","PeriodicalId":8086,"journal":{"name":"Annals of Science","volume":"79 1","pages":"386 - 405"},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2022-04-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43441680","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Monteiro da Rocha and the international debate in the 1760s on astronomical methods to find the longitude at sea: his proposals and criticisms to Lacaille’s lunar-distance method 蒙泰罗·达·罗查和18世纪60年代国际上关于在海上寻找经度的天文学方法的辩论:他对拉卡耶的月距法的建议和批评
IF 0.3 3区 哲学 Q2 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2022-04-03 DOI: 10.1080/00033790.2022.2059567
F. Figueiredo, G. Boistel
ABSTRACT In the 1760s, the international debate on the solution to determining longitude at sea is at its acme. Two solutions emerge, the mechanical and the astronomical ones. The Portuguese mathematician and astronomer José Monteiro da Rocha (1734–1819) is well aware of that debate. For him, Harrison’s No. 4 marine timekeeper cannot be seen as a solution. The desirable solution could only be astronomical. In a manuscript from c. 1765, which unfortunately he fails to publish, Monteiro da Rocha is very critical of Lacaille's lunar-distance method (1759) and proposes another one. In this paper, we intend to analyse Monteiro da Rocha’s criticisms and proposals, trying to understand how this manuscript fits into the international longitude debate and the Portuguese scientific scenario at the time. Concurrently, we will re-examine the classical historiography around the English vs. French priority proposal of the lunar-distance method, purging it from its mythologies to shift it towards a more open, less linear history.
18世纪60年代,国际上关于如何确定海上经度的争论达到了顶峰。有两种解决办法,机械的和天文的。葡萄牙数学家和天文学家约瑟·蒙泰罗·达·罗查(1734-1819)很清楚这种争论。对他来说,哈里森的4号航海计时器不能被视为解决方案。理想的解决方案只能是天文数字。在大约1765年的一份手稿中(不幸的是他没有出版),蒙泰罗·达·罗查对拉卡耶的月球距离方法(1759年)非常批评,并提出了另一种方法。在本文中,我们打算分析蒙泰罗·达·罗查的批评和建议,试图理解这个手稿如何适应国际经度辩论和当时的葡萄牙科学情景。与此同时,我们将重新审视围绕英国和法国优先提出的月球距离方法的古典史学,将其从神话中清除出来,将其转向更开放,更少线性的历史。
{"title":"Monteiro da Rocha and the international debate in the 1760s on astronomical methods to find the longitude at sea: his proposals and criticisms to Lacaille’s lunar-distance method","authors":"F. Figueiredo, G. Boistel","doi":"10.1080/00033790.2022.2059567","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1080/00033790.2022.2059567","url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACT In the 1760s, the international debate on the solution to determining longitude at sea is at its acme. Two solutions emerge, the mechanical and the astronomical ones. The Portuguese mathematician and astronomer José Monteiro da Rocha (1734–1819) is well aware of that debate. For him, Harrison’s No. 4 marine timekeeper cannot be seen as a solution. The desirable solution could only be astronomical. In a manuscript from c. 1765, which unfortunately he fails to publish, Monteiro da Rocha is very critical of Lacaille's lunar-distance method (1759) and proposes another one. In this paper, we intend to analyse Monteiro da Rocha’s criticisms and proposals, trying to understand how this manuscript fits into the international longitude debate and the Portuguese scientific scenario at the time. Concurrently, we will re-examine the classical historiography around the English vs. French priority proposal of the lunar-distance method, purging it from its mythologies to shift it towards a more open, less linear history.","PeriodicalId":8086,"journal":{"name":"Annals of Science","volume":"79 1","pages":"215 - 258"},"PeriodicalIF":0.3,"publicationDate":"2022-04-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43369472","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Annals of Science
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1