首页 > 最新文献

Journal of ancient philosophy最新文献

英文 中文
O justo cívico em Ethica Nicomachea V.6 Ethica Nicomachea V.6 中的公民正义
Pub Date : 2023-10-31 DOI: 10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i2p90-133
André Luiz Cruz Sousa
{"title":"O justo cívico em Ethica Nicomachea V.6","authors":"André Luiz Cruz Sousa","doi":"10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i2p90-133","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i2p90-133","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":185531,"journal":{"name":"Journal of ancient philosophy","volume":"66 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139308989","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Entre ética e ciência: necessidade e contingência na teoria da ação em Aristóteles 在伦理与科学之间:亚里士多德行动理论中的必然性与偶然性
Pub Date : 2023-10-31 DOI: 10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i2p71-89
Jaqueline Stefani
Este artigo investiga a possibilidade de questões morais possuírem a mesma natureza de ocorrências no mais das vezes (ὡς ἐπὶ τὸ πολύ) discutidas na Física, Metafísica e nos Analíticos, em contraste com as categorias de necessário sem mais e de acaso/acidente. Tal categoria (ὡς ἐπὶ τὸ πολύ) ora é aproximada daquilo que é necessário (necessidade sem mais), quando Aristóteles realça a exclusão do acaso/acidente da ciência, ora é afastada do necessário sem mais, quando busca especificar as diferenças entre essas categorias em termos das conclusões passíveis de serem obtidas em silogismos de ambos os tipos. O que parece é que as ações decorrentes de um caráter formado são ὡς ἐπὶ τὸ πολύ, podendo ser compreendidas no registro de um necessário hipotético, dado que o caráter é como uma “segunda natureza” do agente. Se tal hipótese for correta, ações decorrentes de um caráter formado não possuiriam estatuto de abertura aos contrários.
本文探讨了《物理学》、《形而上学》和《分析学》中讨论的道德问题与 "必然而非更多 "和 "偶然/巧合 "这两个范畴相比,具有 "经常发生"(ὡς ἐπὶ τὸ πολύ)性质的可能性。当亚里士多德强调将偶然/巧合排除在科学之外时,这个范畴(ὡς ἐπὶ τὸ πολύ)有时会更接近必然性(没有更多的必然性);当他试图从这两种类型的三段论所能得出的结论的角度来说明这两个范畴的区别时,这个范畴有时会与没有更多的必然性拉开距离。现在的情况是,形成的性格所导致的行动是ὡς ἐπὶ τὸ πολύ,可以从假设的必然性的角度来理解,因为性格就像是行为者的 "第二本性"。如果这一假设是正确的,那么由已形成的性格所导致的行动就不会具有向对立面开放的地位。
{"title":"Entre ética e ciência: necessidade e contingência na teoria da ação em Aristóteles","authors":"Jaqueline Stefani","doi":"10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i2p71-89","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i2p71-89","url":null,"abstract":"Este artigo investiga a possibilidade de questões morais possuírem a mesma natureza de ocorrências no mais das vezes (ὡς ἐπὶ τὸ πολύ) discutidas na Física, Metafísica e nos Analíticos, em contraste com as categorias de necessário sem mais e de acaso/acidente. Tal categoria (ὡς ἐπὶ τὸ πολύ) ora é aproximada daquilo que é necessário (necessidade sem mais), quando Aristóteles realça a exclusão do acaso/acidente da ciência, ora é afastada do necessário sem mais, quando busca especificar as diferenças entre essas categorias em termos das conclusões passíveis de serem obtidas em silogismos de ambos os tipos. O que parece é que as ações decorrentes de um caráter formado são ὡς ἐπὶ τὸ πολύ, podendo ser compreendidas no registro de um necessário hipotético, dado que o caráter é como uma “segunda natureza” do agente. Se tal hipótese for correta, ações decorrentes de um caráter formado não possuiriam estatuto de abertura aos contrários.","PeriodicalId":185531,"journal":{"name":"Journal of ancient philosophy","volume":"236 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139309568","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Some remarks against non-epistemic accounts of immediate premises in Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics 针对亚里士多德《后分析》中关于直接前提的非表义论述的一些评论
Pub Date : 2023-10-31 DOI: 10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i2p29-43
Breno Zuppolini
Most interpretations of Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics believe that the term ‘ameson’ is used to describe the principles or foundations of a given system of justification or explanation as epistemically prior to or more fundamental than the other propositions in the system. Epistemic readings (as I shall call them) arguably constitute a majority in the secondary literature. This predominant view has been challenged by Robin Smith (1986) and Michael Ferejohn (1994; 2013), who propose interpretations that should be classified as non-epistemic according to the definition above. My aim in this article is purely negative. I intend to show that these non-epistemic interpretations are liable to serious objections and are in conflict with some important features of Aristotle’s theory of demonstration.
对亚里士多德《后析》的大多数解释都认为,"ameon "一词是用来描述某一论证或解释体系的原则或基础,在认识论上先于或高于该体系中的其他命题。在二手文献中,认识论解读(我将称之为认识论解读)可以说占了大多数。罗宾-史密斯(Robin Smith,1986 年)和迈克尔-费雷约翰(Michael Ferejohn,1994 年;2013 年)对这一主流观点提出了质疑,他们根据上述定义提出了应归类为非认识论的解释。我在本文中的目的纯粹是否定的。我打算说明,这些非表义解释容易遭到严重反对,并且与亚里士多德的证明理论的一些重要特征相冲突。
{"title":"Some remarks against non-epistemic accounts of immediate premises in Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics","authors":"Breno Zuppolini","doi":"10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i2p29-43","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i2p29-43","url":null,"abstract":"Most interpretations of Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics believe that the term ‘ameson’ is used to describe the principles or foundations of a given system of justification or explanation as epistemically prior to or more fundamental than the other propositions in the system. Epistemic readings (as I shall call them) arguably constitute a majority in the secondary literature. This predominant view has been challenged by Robin Smith (1986) and Michael Ferejohn (1994; 2013), who propose interpretations that should be classified as non-epistemic according to the definition above. My aim in this article is purely negative. I intend to show that these non-epistemic interpretations are liable to serious objections and are in conflict with some important features of Aristotle’s theory of demonstration.","PeriodicalId":185531,"journal":{"name":"Journal of ancient philosophy","volume":"333 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139308918","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
O ponto de intersecção entre compostos naturais propriamente e não propriamente substanciais em Aristóteles 亚里士多德中适当的和不适当的实质性自然化合物的交叉点
Pub Date : 2023-10-31 DOI: 10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i2p44-70
Rodrigo Romão de Carvalho
Ao longo da Metafísica e dos tratados de filosofia natural, Aristóteles toma os organismos vivos como os exemplos paradigmáticos de οὐσίαι (substâncias) naturais. No entanto, além dos organismos vivos, em certas passagens o filósofo menciona, também, as partes dos viventes e os elementos como exemplos de substâncias. Contudo, em outras passagens, Aristóteles parece considerar que as partes dos seres vivos e os corpos elementares não representariam, genuinamente ou propriamente, entidades substanciais. Por outro lado, em nenhum momento, o filósofo parece indicar expressamente os corpos homogêneos inanimados (metais e minerais), tratados no livro IV dos Meteorológicos, enquanto tipos de seres substanciais. Neste artigo, pretendo, então, examinar se as partes do vivente e os elementos poderiam, de fato, contar ou não como exemplares genuínos de substâncias naturais; e em que medida os corpos homogêneos inanimados, a despeito de não serem explicitamente citados na condição de entes substanciais, poderiam, a partir do exame de suas naturezas composicionais, sustentarem, de uma maneira estrita, o título de οὐσίαι naturais.
在《形而上学》和有关自然哲学的论文中,亚里士多德始终把生物作为自然物质的典型例子。然而,除了生物体之外,在某些段落中,哲学家还提到生物的各个部分和元素也是物质的例子。然而,在其他段落中,亚里士多德似乎认为生物的部分和基本体并不能真正或恰当地代表实质实体。另一方面,亚里士多德似乎从未明确指出《气象学》第四卷中论述的同质无生命体(金属和矿物)是实体的类型。因此,在本文中,我打算探讨生物的各个部分和各种元素事实上是否可以算作自然物质的真正例子;以及同质的无生命体尽管没有被明确称为实体存在物,但通过对其构成性质的考察,它们在多大程度上可以严格地维持自然οὐσίαι的称号。
{"title":"O ponto de intersecção entre compostos naturais propriamente e não propriamente substanciais em Aristóteles","authors":"Rodrigo Romão de Carvalho","doi":"10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i2p44-70","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i2p44-70","url":null,"abstract":"Ao longo da Metafísica e dos tratados de filosofia natural, Aristóteles toma os organismos vivos como os exemplos paradigmáticos de οὐσίαι (substâncias) naturais. No entanto, além dos organismos vivos, em certas passagens o filósofo menciona, também, as partes dos viventes e os elementos como exemplos de substâncias. Contudo, em outras passagens, Aristóteles parece considerar que as partes dos seres vivos e os corpos elementares não representariam, genuinamente ou propriamente, entidades substanciais. Por outro lado, em nenhum momento, o filósofo parece indicar expressamente os corpos homogêneos inanimados (metais e minerais), tratados no livro IV dos Meteorológicos, enquanto tipos de seres substanciais. Neste artigo, pretendo, então, examinar se as partes do vivente e os elementos poderiam, de fato, contar ou não como exemplares genuínos de substâncias naturais; e em que medida os corpos homogêneos inanimados, a despeito de não serem explicitamente citados na condição de entes substanciais, poderiam, a partir do exame de suas naturezas composicionais, sustentarem, de uma maneira estrita, o título de οὐσίαι naturais.","PeriodicalId":185531,"journal":{"name":"Journal of ancient philosophy","volume":"3 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139307083","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Linguistic (and Ontological?) encounters between Plato and Karl Popper 柏拉图与卡尔-波普尔的语言学(和本体论?
Pub Date : 2023-10-31 DOI: 10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i2p01-28
Terezis Christos
In this study, I attempt to shed light on whether some passages from the Platonic dialogue Cratylus that deal with language correspond to Karl Popper’s theory on the third world. Specifically, I attempt to prove that Plato’s third world contains both divine and human properties, something that is provided through language, that is, through the human rational and developing in objective terms construction. In the four subchapters of my study, I basically investigate the relationship between the thinking subject and the noumenon as well as the role of the coiner of names and the dialectician with respect to the scientific foundation of the names. The most important conclusion drawn is that according to Plato these two are responsible for connecting a thinking subject with a noumenon by adding objective certainty to the meaning of everything is said. I also investigate how Plato’s archetypal Ideas could be considered to be the third world.
在本研究中,我试图揭示柏拉图对话《克拉提洛斯》中涉及语言的一些段落是否与卡尔-波普尔的第三世界理论相对应。具体来说,我试图证明柏拉图的第三世界包含神性和人性,这是通过语言提供的,即通过人类的理性和在客观术语建构中的发展提供的。在研究的四个分章中,我基本上探讨了思维主体与本体之间的关系,以及名称创造者和辩证法家在名称的科学基础方面的作用。得出的最重要的结论是,根据柏拉图的观点,这两个人负责将思维主体与本体联系起来,为一切言说的意义增添客观的确定性。我还研究了如何将柏拉图的原型 "理念 "视为第三世界。
{"title":"Linguistic (and Ontological?) encounters between Plato and Karl Popper","authors":"Terezis Christos","doi":"10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i2p01-28","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i2p01-28","url":null,"abstract":"In this study, I attempt to shed light on whether some passages from the Platonic dialogue Cratylus that deal with language correspond to Karl Popper’s theory on the third world. Specifically, I attempt to prove that Plato’s third world contains both divine and human properties, something that is provided through language, that is, through the human rational and developing in objective terms construction. In the four subchapters of my study, I basically investigate the relationship between the thinking subject and the noumenon as well as the role of the coiner of names and the dialectician with respect to the scientific foundation of the names. The most important conclusion drawn is that according to Plato these two are responsible for connecting a thinking subject with a noumenon by adding objective certainty to the meaning of everything is said. I also investigate how Plato’s archetypal Ideas could be considered to be the third world.","PeriodicalId":185531,"journal":{"name":"Journal of ancient philosophy","volume":"21 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139306909","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
On Becoming Fearful Quickly: A Reinterpretation of Aristotle’s Somatic Model of Socratean akrasia. 关于迅速变得恐惧:重新诠释亚里士多德的苏格拉底 "akrasia "躯体模型》(Areinterpretation of Aristotle's Somatic Model of Socratean akrasia)。
Pub Date : 2023-10-31 DOI: 10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i2p134-161
Brian Andrew Lightbody
The Protagoras is the touchstone of Socrates’ moral intellectualist stance. The position in a nutshell stipulates that the proper reevaluation of a desire is enough to neutralize it.[1] The implication of this position is that akrasia or weakness of will is not the result of desire (or fear for that matter) overpowering reason but is due to ignorance.   Socrates’ eliminativist position on weakness of will, however, flies in the face of the common-sense experience regarding akratic action and thus Aristotle was at pains to render Socrates’ account of moral incontinence intelligible. The key improvement Aristotle makes to Socrates’s model is to underscore that the conditioning of the akratic’s body plays a critical role in determining the power of one’s appetites and, accordingly, the capacity of one to resist the temptations these appetites present for rational evaluation.  As Aristotle puts it, “For the incontinent man is like the people who get drunk quickly and on little wine, i.e., on less than most people.” (1151a 3-4). Aristotle presents what I shall call a somatic paradigm (i.e. the drunkard analogy) in order to tackle the problem of akrasia and it is this somatic solution that marks a significant improvement over Socrates’s intellectualist or informational model or so the tradition tells us. In this paper, I wish to push back on the above Aristotelian explanation. I argue that when one fully examines Socrates’ account of weakness of will that Aristotle’s solution is less effective than is traditionally thought. In fact, Socrates can bring Aristotle’s model into his own; just as Aristotle absorbs what is right about Socrates’s model, namely, that akratic action utilizes reason but to a limited degree, Socrates in Meno (77C-78A) develops his own somatic model of weakness of will that connects to the intellectualist paradigm of the Protagoras.   To achieve this rapprochement between the two models, I zero in on the description provided by Socrates of those individuals who desire bad things knowing they are bad as “ill-starred” or “bad spirited” (κακοδαίμων ). The “bad-spirited” is the coward and, in contrast to Aristotle’s drunkard, becomes fearful quickly from little danger. This additional somatic component, when connected to Socrates’s position on akrasia in Protagoras adds a new twist to Socrates’s model in the following way: while no one wishes to be ill-starred such that more harm than good will befall one, one may become so as a result of the bad choices one knowingly makes.   [1] “After him came Socrates, who spoke better and further about this subject, but even he was not successful. For he used to make the virtues into sciences, and this is impossible. For the sciences all involve reason, and reason is to be found in the intellectual part of the soul. So that all the virtues, according to him arise in the rational part of the soul. The result is that in making the virtues into sciences he is doing away with the nonrational part
普罗泰戈拉》是苏格拉底道德知识分子立场的试金石。[1]这一立场的含义是,"闇 "或意志薄弱不是欲望(或恐惧)压倒理性的结果,而是由于无知。 然而,苏格拉底关于意志薄弱的消解主义立场与关于 "闇 "行动的常识经验背道而驰,因此亚里士多德不遗余力地使苏格拉底关于道德失禁的论述变得可以理解。亚里士多德对苏格拉底模式的关键改进在于强调,"嗜欲者 "身体的条件在决定一个人的食欲力量以及相应地决定一个人抵御这些食欲诱惑的能力方面起着至关重要的作用。 正如亚里士多德所说:"因为大小便失禁的人就像那些很快就醉倒的人,酒喝得很少,也就是说,比大多数人喝得少"。(1151a 3-4).亚里士多德提出了一种我称之为躯体范式(即醉汉类比)的方法来解决akrasia问题,而正是这种躯体解决方案标志着苏格拉底的知识论或信息论模式的重大改进,这也是传统告诉我们的。 在本文中,我希望反驳上述亚里士多德式的解释。我认为,当我们全面研究苏格拉底关于意志薄弱的论述时,亚里士多德的解决方案并没有传统上认为的那么有效。事实上,苏格拉底可以将亚里士多德的模式引入自己的模式;正如亚里士多德吸收了苏格拉底模式的正确之处,即 "傲慢行动 "利用了理性,但程度有限,苏格拉底在《美诺》(77C-78A)中发展了自己的意志薄弱的躯体模式,与《普罗塔哥拉》的理智主义范式相联系。 为了实现这两种模式之间的和解,我把苏格拉底对那些明知是坏事却仍然渴望得到的人的描述归结为 "坏心眼 "或 "坏脾气"(κακοδαίμων)。坏脾气 "是懦夫,与亚里士多德笔下的酒鬼不同,他遇到一点危险就会迅速变得恐惧。这一额外的躯体成分与苏格拉底在《普罗塔哥拉》(Protagoras)中关于 "akrasia "的立场相联系,为苏格拉底的模式增添了以下新的转折:虽然没有人希望自己心怀不轨,以致弊大于利,但一个人可能会因为明知故犯的错误选择而变得心怀不轨。 [1] "在他之后是苏格拉底,他对这个问题讲得更好、更深入,但即使是他也没有成功。因为他习惯于把美德变成科学,而这是不可能的。因为科学都涉及理性,而理性存在于灵魂的智力部分。因此,他认为所有美德都产生于灵魂的理性部分。结果是,他把美德变成了科学,就等于抹杀了灵魂的非理性部分,从而抹杀了激情和性格......"(亚里士多德,《道德大全》1.1.1182 a15-26)
{"title":"On Becoming Fearful Quickly: A Reinterpretation of Aristotle’s Somatic Model of Socratean akrasia.","authors":"Brian Andrew Lightbody","doi":"10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i2p134-161","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i2p134-161","url":null,"abstract":"The Protagoras is the touchstone of Socrates’ moral intellectualist stance. The position in a nutshell stipulates that the proper reevaluation of a desire is enough to neutralize it.[1] The implication of this position is that akrasia or weakness of will is not the result of desire (or fear for that matter) overpowering reason but is due to ignorance.   Socrates’ eliminativist position on weakness of will, however, flies in the face of the common-sense experience regarding akratic action and thus Aristotle was at pains to render Socrates’ account of moral incontinence intelligible. The key improvement Aristotle makes to Socrates’s model is to underscore that the conditioning of the akratic’s body plays a critical role in determining the power of one’s appetites and, accordingly, the capacity of one to resist the temptations these appetites present for rational evaluation.  As Aristotle puts it, “For the incontinent man is like the people who get drunk quickly and on little wine, i.e., on less than most people.” (1151a 3-4). Aristotle presents what I shall call a somatic paradigm (i.e. the drunkard analogy) in order to tackle the problem of akrasia and it is this somatic solution that marks a significant improvement over Socrates’s intellectualist or informational model or so the tradition tells us. In this paper, I wish to push back on the above Aristotelian explanation. I argue that when one fully examines Socrates’ account of weakness of will that Aristotle’s solution is less effective than is traditionally thought. In fact, Socrates can bring Aristotle’s model into his own; just as Aristotle absorbs what is right about Socrates’s model, namely, that akratic action utilizes reason but to a limited degree, Socrates in Meno (77C-78A) develops his own somatic model of weakness of will that connects to the intellectualist paradigm of the Protagoras.   To achieve this rapprochement between the two models, I zero in on the description provided by Socrates of those individuals who desire bad things knowing they are bad as “ill-starred” or “bad spirited” (κακοδαίμων ). The “bad-spirited” is the coward and, in contrast to Aristotle’s drunkard, becomes fearful quickly from little danger. This additional somatic component, when connected to Socrates’s position on akrasia in Protagoras adds a new twist to Socrates’s model in the following way: while no one wishes to be ill-starred such that more harm than good will befall one, one may become so as a result of the bad choices one knowingly makes.   [1] “After him came Socrates, who spoke better and further about this subject, but even he was not successful. For he used to make the virtues into sciences, and this is impossible. For the sciences all involve reason, and reason is to be found in the intellectual part of the soul. So that all the virtues, according to him arise in the rational part of the soul. The result is that in making the virtues into sciences he is doing away with the nonrational part ","PeriodicalId":185531,"journal":{"name":"Journal of ancient philosophy","volume":"13 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-10-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"139308254","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A Note on Aristotle’s De Anima Α 1, 403a10-16
Pub Date : 2023-05-31 DOI: 10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i1p139-146
Orestis Karasmanis
In this paper I discuss passage 403a10-16 from Aristotle’s De Anima. In this passage Aristotle deals with whether the soul could be separate from the body and presents an analogy with geometrical entities. This passage is highly obscure and it presents many textual difficulties. The interpretation I offer resolves the textual problems without requiring emendations to the text as many commentators suggest.
在本文中,我将讨论亚里士多德《论阿尼玛》中的403a10-16段。在这篇文章中,亚里士多德讨论了灵魂是否可以从身体中分离出来,并提出了一个与几何实体的类比。这段话非常晦涩难懂,在文本上有很多困难。我提供的解释解决了文本问题,而不需要像许多评论家建议的那样对文本进行修改。
{"title":"A Note on Aristotle’s De Anima Α 1, 403a10-16","authors":"Orestis Karasmanis","doi":"10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i1p139-146","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i1p139-146","url":null,"abstract":"In this paper I discuss passage 403a10-16 from Aristotle’s De Anima. In this passage Aristotle deals with whether the soul could be separate from the body and presents an analogy with geometrical entities. This passage is highly obscure and it presents many textual difficulties. The interpretation I offer resolves the textual problems without requiring emendations to the text as many commentators suggest.","PeriodicalId":185531,"journal":{"name":"Journal of ancient philosophy","volume":"18 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-05-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"126997744","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Percepción Moral y Conocimiento Práctico en el Estoicismo 斯多葛主义中的道德知觉与实践知识
Pub Date : 2023-05-31 DOI: 10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i1p121-138
C. Pineda
In a paper published in 1998, Ricardo Salles argues that the Stoic theory of action cannot account for practical knowledge, i.e., knowledge about what action is appropriate to be carried out in certain circumstances. The aim of this paper is to propose a solution to this problem. For this aim, I argue that the Stoics developed a perceptual theory of moral knowledge. According to this theory, the moral properties instantiated in objects, people, and actions are known through perception. After explaining this theory, I argue that it allows us to show that the Stoics deemed perception as a source of practical knowledge.
在1998年发表的一篇论文中,Ricardo Salles认为斯多葛学派的行动理论不能解释实践知识,即关于在特定情况下采取何种行动是合适的知识。本文的目的是提出解决这一问题的方法。为此,我认为斯多葛学派发展了一种道德知识的感性理论。根据这一理论,在物体、人和行为中实例化的道德属性是通过感知知道的。在解释了这一理论之后,我认为它使我们能够证明斯多葛学派将感知视为实践知识的来源。
{"title":"Percepción Moral y Conocimiento Práctico en el Estoicismo","authors":"C. Pineda","doi":"10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i1p121-138","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i1p121-138","url":null,"abstract":"In a paper published in 1998, Ricardo Salles argues that the Stoic theory of action cannot account for practical knowledge, i.e., knowledge about what action is appropriate to be carried out in certain circumstances. The aim of this paper is to propose a solution to this problem. For this aim, I argue that the Stoics developed a perceptual theory of moral knowledge. According to this theory, the moral properties instantiated in objects, people, and actions are known through perception. After explaining this theory, I argue that it allows us to show that the Stoics deemed perception as a source of practical knowledge.","PeriodicalId":185531,"journal":{"name":"Journal of ancient philosophy","volume":"52 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-05-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"125190217","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
How Does Aristotle Understand the Paradox of the Meno? 亚里士多德如何理解弥诺的悖论?
Pub Date : 2023-05-31 DOI: 10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i1p80-95
Nathan Elvidge
I focus on the distinction between universal and particular knowledge or knowledge simpliciter in APr 2.21 and APo 1.1 as Aristotle’s explicit response to the paradox of the Meno. I attempt to derive a picture of Aristotle’s understanding of the philosophical problem underlying that paradox by asking what that problem would have to be in order for this distinction to make sense as a response to it. I consider two ways of taking the distinction, and argue that both point towards a problem about deriving knowledge of particulars from knowledge of universals as the fundamental problem underlying Aristotle’s understanding of the Meno paradox.
在APr 2.21和APo 1.1中,作为亚里士多德对Meno悖论的明确回应,我将重点讨论普遍知识和特殊知识或更简单的知识之间的区别。我试图推导出亚里士多德对这个悖论背后的哲学问题的理解,通过问这个问题必须是什么,才能使这种区别作为对它的回应有意义。我考虑了两种区分的方式,并认为两者都指向一个问题,即从共相的知识中推导出关于细节的知识,这是亚里士多德对Meno悖论理解的根本问题。
{"title":"How Does Aristotle Understand the Paradox of the Meno?","authors":"Nathan Elvidge","doi":"10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i1p80-95","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i1p80-95","url":null,"abstract":"I focus on the distinction between universal and particular knowledge or knowledge simpliciter in APr 2.21 and APo 1.1 as Aristotle’s explicit response to the paradox of the Meno. I attempt to derive a picture of Aristotle’s understanding of the philosophical problem underlying that paradox by asking what that problem would have to be in order for this distinction to make sense as a response to it. I consider two ways of taking the distinction, and argue that both point towards a problem about deriving knowledge of particulars from knowledge of universals as the fundamental problem underlying Aristotle’s understanding of the Meno paradox.","PeriodicalId":185531,"journal":{"name":"Journal of ancient philosophy","volume":"24 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-05-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"114264540","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Callicles as a Potential Tyrant in Plato's Gorgias 在柏拉图的《高尔吉亚篇》中卡利克勒斯是一个潜在的暴君
Pub Date : 2023-05-31 DOI: 10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i1p01-35
D. R. N. Lopes
This essay argues that Callicles is depicted by Plato in the Gorgias as a potential tyrant from a psychological standpoint. To this end I will contend that the Calliclean moral psychology sketched at 491e-492c points towards the analysis of the tyrannical individual pursued by Plato in books VIII and IX of the Republic based upon the tripartite theory of the soul. I will thereby attempt to show that (i) in the Gorgias, Callicles does not actually personify the ideal of the superior person advocated by himself insofar as he is still susceptible to shame, as evinced by Socrates' cross-examination (494c-495a); and that (ii) looking forward to the Republic, he can be understood for this same reason as being precisely on the threshold between the democratic and the tyrannical soul.
本文从心理学的角度论证柏拉图在《高尔吉亚篇》中将卡利克勒斯描绘成一个潜在的暴君。为了达到这个目的,我将争辩说,在491e-492c中概述的卡利克利道德心理学,指向柏拉图在《理想国》第八和第九卷中所追求的基于灵魂三段论的暴虐个人的分析。因此,我将试图表明:(1)在《高尔吉亚篇》中,卡利克勒斯实际上并没有将他自己所提倡的高人一等的理想人格化,因为他仍然容易受到羞耻的影响,正如苏格拉底的盘问(494c-495a)所证明的那样;(2)期待《理想国》,他可以被理解为正是站在民主灵魂和专制灵魂之间的门槛上。
{"title":"Callicles as a Potential Tyrant in Plato's Gorgias","authors":"D. R. N. Lopes","doi":"10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i1p01-35","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.11606/issn.1981-9471.v17i1p01-35","url":null,"abstract":"This essay argues that Callicles is depicted by Plato in the Gorgias as a potential tyrant from a psychological standpoint. To this end I will contend that the Calliclean moral psychology sketched at 491e-492c points towards the analysis of the tyrannical individual pursued by Plato in books VIII and IX of the Republic based upon the tripartite theory of the soul. I will thereby attempt to show that (i) in the Gorgias, Callicles does not actually personify the ideal of the superior person advocated by himself insofar as he is still susceptible to shame, as evinced by Socrates' cross-examination (494c-495a); and that (ii) looking forward to the Republic, he can be understood for this same reason as being precisely on the threshold between the democratic and the tyrannical soul.","PeriodicalId":185531,"journal":{"name":"Journal of ancient philosophy","volume":"47 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-05-31","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"115751333","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Journal of ancient philosophy
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1