首页 > 最新文献

Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement最新文献

英文 中文
Meaning in Lives Nearing Their End 生命即将结束的意义
Pub Date : 2021-10-01 DOI: 10.1017/S1358246121000321
F. Kamm
Abstract In this paper, I consider the idea of meaning in life as I believe it has arisen in some discussions of ageing and death. I critically examine and compare the views of Atul Gawande and Ezekiel Emanuel, connecting their views to the idea of meaning in life. I further consider the relation of meaning in life to both the dignity of the person and the reasonableness of continuing or not continuing to live. In considering these issues, I evaluate and draw on Bernard Williams’ distinction between categorical and conditional desires, Susan Wolf's work on meaning in life, and Jeremy Waldron's views on dignity in old age.
在这篇论文中,我认为生命的意义这个概念是在一些关于衰老和死亡的讨论中出现的。我批判性地考察和比较了Atul Gawande和Ezekiel Emanuel的观点,将他们的观点与生命的意义联系起来。我进一步考虑了生命的意义与人的尊严和继续或不继续活下去的合理性之间的关系。在考虑这些问题时,我评估并借鉴了伯纳德·威廉姆斯对绝对欲望和条件欲望的区分,苏珊·沃尔夫关于生活意义的著作,以及杰里米·沃尔德伦关于老年尊严的观点。
{"title":"Meaning in Lives Nearing Their End","authors":"F. Kamm","doi":"10.1017/S1358246121000321","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S1358246121000321","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract In this paper, I consider the idea of meaning in life as I believe it has arisen in some discussions of ageing and death. I critically examine and compare the views of Atul Gawande and Ezekiel Emanuel, connecting their views to the idea of meaning in life. I further consider the relation of meaning in life to both the dignity of the person and the reasonableness of continuing or not continuing to live. In considering these issues, I evaluate and draw on Bernard Williams’ distinction between categorical and conditional desires, Susan Wolf's work on meaning in life, and Jeremy Waldron's views on dignity in old age.","PeriodicalId":269662,"journal":{"name":"Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement","volume":"14 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"134085442","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Meaning and Anti-Meaning in Life and What Happens After We Die 生命的意义和反意义以及我们死后会发生什么
Pub Date : 2021-10-01 DOI: 10.1017/S1358246121000217
Sven Nyholm
Abstract The absence of meaningfulness in life is meaninglessness. But what is the polar opposite of meaningfulness? In recent and ongoing work together with Stephen Campbell and Marcello di Paola respectively, I have explored what we dub ‘anti-meaning’: the negative counterpart of positive meaning in life. Here, I relate this idea of ‘anti-meaningful’ actions, activities, and projects to the topic of death, and in particular the deaths or suffering of those who will live after our own deaths. Connecting this idea of anti-meaning and what happens after our own deaths to recent work by Samuel Scheffler on what he calls ‘the collective afterlife’ and his four reasons to care about future generations, I argue that if we today make choices or have lifestyles that later lead to unnecessarily early deaths and otherwise avoidable suffering of people who will live after we have died, this robs our current choices and lifestyles of some of their meaning, perhaps even making them the opposite of meaningful in the long run.
生活中没有意义就是没有意义。但是意义的对立面是什么呢?在最近和正在进行的与Stephen Campbell和Marcello di Paola的合作中,我分别探索了我们称之为“反意义”的东西:生活中积极意义的消极对应。在这里,我将这种“反意义”的行为、活动和项目的概念与死亡的主题联系起来,特别是那些在我们死后活着的人的死亡或痛苦。将反意义的观点和我们死后会发生的事情与塞缪尔·舍弗勒最近关于他所谓的“集体来世”的研究以及他关心后代的四个理由联系起来,我认为,如果我们今天做出的选择或生活方式,后来会导致不必要的过早死亡,或者在我们死后会活下来的人遭受本来可以避免的痛苦,这就剥夺了我们当前选择和生活方式的一些意义,也许从长远来看,它们甚至会变得毫无意义。
{"title":"Meaning and Anti-Meaning in Life and What Happens After We Die","authors":"Sven Nyholm","doi":"10.1017/S1358246121000217","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S1358246121000217","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract The absence of meaningfulness in life is meaninglessness. But what is the polar opposite of meaningfulness? In recent and ongoing work together with Stephen Campbell and Marcello di Paola respectively, I have explored what we dub ‘anti-meaning’: the negative counterpart of positive meaning in life. Here, I relate this idea of ‘anti-meaningful’ actions, activities, and projects to the topic of death, and in particular the deaths or suffering of those who will live after our own deaths. Connecting this idea of anti-meaning and what happens after our own deaths to recent work by Samuel Scheffler on what he calls ‘the collective afterlife’ and his four reasons to care about future generations, I argue that if we today make choices or have lifestyles that later lead to unnecessarily early deaths and otherwise avoidable suffering of people who will live after we have died, this robs our current choices and lifestyles of some of their meaning, perhaps even making them the opposite of meaningful in the long run.","PeriodicalId":269662,"journal":{"name":"Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement","volume":"122 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"126020597","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 7
When Death Comes Too Late: Radical Life Extension and the Makropulos Case 当死亡来得太晚:激进的延长生命和Makropulos案例
Pub Date : 2021-10-01 DOI: 10.1017/s1358246121000278
M. Hauskeller
Abstract Famously, Bernard Williams has argued that although death is an evil if it occurs when we still have something to live for, we have no good reason to desire that our lives be radically extended because any such life would at some point reach a stage when we become indifferent to the world and ourselves. This is supposed to be so bad for us that it would be better if we died before that happens. Most critics have rejected Williams’ arguments on the grounds that it is far from certain that we will run out of things to live for, and I don't contest these objections. Instead, I am trying to show that they do not affect the persuasiveness of Williams’ argument, which in my reading does not rely on the claim that we will inevitably run out of things to live for, but on the far less contentious claim that it is not unthinkable we will do so and the largely ignored claim that if that happens, we will have died too late.
伯纳德·威廉姆斯(Bernard Williams)有一个著名的观点,他认为,尽管死亡是一种邪恶,如果它发生在我们还有活着的理由的时候,我们没有充分的理由希望我们的生命从根本上延长,因为任何这样的生命都会在某个时候达到一个阶段,那时我们对世界和自己都变得冷漠。这对我们来说太糟糕了,如果我们在那之前死去会更好。大多数评论家都拒绝了威廉姆斯的论点,理由是我们远不能确定我们会耗尽生活的目标,我不反对这些反对意见。相反,我试图表明,它们不会影响威廉姆斯论点的说服力,在我的阅读中,威廉姆斯的论点并不依赖于我们将不可避免地耗尽生命的理由这一说法,而是依赖于一个争议小得多的说法,即我们会这样做并非不可想象,以及一个基本上被忽视的说法,即如果发生这种情况,我们就会死得太晚。
{"title":"When Death Comes Too Late: Radical Life Extension and the Makropulos Case","authors":"M. Hauskeller","doi":"10.1017/s1358246121000278","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/s1358246121000278","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Famously, Bernard Williams has argued that although death is an evil if it occurs when we still have something to live for, we have no good reason to desire that our lives be radically extended because any such life would at some point reach a stage when we become indifferent to the world and ourselves. This is supposed to be so bad for us that it would be better if we died before that happens. Most critics have rejected Williams’ arguments on the grounds that it is far from certain that we will run out of things to live for, and I don't contest these objections. Instead, I am trying to show that they do not affect the persuasiveness of Williams’ argument, which in my reading does not rely on the claim that we will inevitably run out of things to live for, but on the far less contentious claim that it is not unthinkable we will do so and the largely ignored claim that if that happens, we will have died too late.","PeriodicalId":269662,"journal":{"name":"Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"130836484","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Grieving Our Way Back to Meaningfulness 悲伤让我们回到有意义的生活
Pub Date : 2021-10-01 DOI: 10.1017/S1358246121000308
M. Cholbi
Abstract The deaths of those on whom our practical identities rely generate a sense of disorientation or alienation from the world seemingly at odds with life being meaningful. In the terms put forth in Cheshire Calhoun's recent account of meaningfulness in life, because their existence serves as a metaphysical presupposition of our practical identities, their deaths threaten to upend a background frame of agency against which much of our choice and deliberation takes place. Here I argue for a dual role for grief in addressing this threat to life's meaningfulness. Inasmuch as grief's object is the loss of our relationship with the deceased as it was prior to their death, grief serves to alert us to the threat to our practical identities that their deaths pose to us and motivates us to defuse this threat by revising our practical identities to reflect the modification in our relationship necessitated by their deaths. Simultaneously, the emotional complexity and richness of grief episodes provides an abundance of normative evidence regarding our relationship with the deceased and our practical identities, evidence that can enable us to re-establish our practical identities and thereby recover a sense of our lives as meaningful.
我们的现实身份所依赖的人的死亡使我们产生一种迷失方向或与世界疏远的感觉,似乎与生活的意义不一致。用柴郡·卡尔霍恩(Cheshire Calhoun)最近对生命意义的描述来说,因为它们的存在是我们实际身份的形而上学前提,它们的死亡可能会颠覆我们的选择和思考所依据的主体背景框架。在这里,我认为在解决这种对生命意义的威胁时,悲伤扮演着双重角色。因为悲伤的目标是失去我们与死者生前的关系,悲伤提醒我们,他们的死亡对我们的实际身份构成了威胁,并激励我们通过修改我们的实际身份来缓解这种威胁,以反映他们的死亡所必需的我们关系的改变。同时,悲伤事件的情感复杂性和丰富性为我们与死者的关系和我们的实际身份提供了大量的规范性证据,这些证据可以使我们重新建立我们的实际身份,从而恢复我们生活的意义感。
{"title":"Grieving Our Way Back to Meaningfulness","authors":"M. Cholbi","doi":"10.1017/S1358246121000308","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S1358246121000308","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract The deaths of those on whom our practical identities rely generate a sense of disorientation or alienation from the world seemingly at odds with life being meaningful. In the terms put forth in Cheshire Calhoun's recent account of meaningfulness in life, because their existence serves as a metaphysical presupposition of our practical identities, their deaths threaten to upend a background frame of agency against which much of our choice and deliberation takes place. Here I argue for a dual role for grief in addressing this threat to life's meaningfulness. Inasmuch as grief's object is the loss of our relationship with the deceased as it was prior to their death, grief serves to alert us to the threat to our practical identities that their deaths pose to us and motivates us to defuse this threat by revising our practical identities to reflect the modification in our relationship necessitated by their deaths. Simultaneously, the emotional complexity and richness of grief episodes provides an abundance of normative evidence regarding our relationship with the deceased and our practical identities, evidence that can enable us to re-establish our practical identities and thereby recover a sense of our lives as meaningful.","PeriodicalId":269662,"journal":{"name":"Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement","volume":"93 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"115799031","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 4
‘Creatures of a Day’: Contingency, Mortality, and Human Limits “一天的生物”:偶然性、死亡率和人类的极限
Pub Date : 2021-10-01 DOI: 10.1017/S1358246121000369
H. Carel
Abstract This paper offers a nexus of terms – mortality, limits, contingency and vulnerability – painting a picture of human life as marked by limitation and finitude. I suggest that limitations of possibility, capacity, and resource are deep features of human life, but not only restrict it. Limits are also the conditions of possibility for human life and as such have productive, normative, and creative powers that not only delimit life but also scaffold growth and transformation within it. The paper takes a less known interpretation of the term ‘ephēmeros', to mean ‘of the day', rather than ‘short-lived' and suggests that as ephemeral, human life is contingent and mutable, subject to events beyond our control. However, virtue can still be exercised – indeed, can be exuberantly displayed – when we respond to contingent events marked by adversity.
摘要本文提出了死亡、极限、偶然性和脆弱性等术语的联系,描绘了一幅以限制和有限性为标志的人类生活图景。我认为可能性、能力和资源的限制是人类生活的深层特征,但不仅仅是限制。限制也是人类生活可能性的条件,因此具有生产性、规范性和创造性的力量,不仅限定了生活,而且还支撑着生活中的成长和转变。这篇论文采用了对“ephēmeros”一词的一种鲜为人知的解释,意思是“当天”,而不是“短暂的”,并表明人类的生命是短暂的,是偶然的,多变的,受我们无法控制的事件的影响。然而,当我们对以逆境为标志的偶然事件作出反应时,美德仍然可以被运用——实际上,可以被充分展示出来。
{"title":"‘Creatures of a Day’: Contingency, Mortality, and Human Limits","authors":"H. Carel","doi":"10.1017/S1358246121000369","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S1358246121000369","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract This paper offers a nexus of terms – mortality, limits, contingency and vulnerability – painting a picture of human life as marked by limitation and finitude. I suggest that limitations of possibility, capacity, and resource are deep features of human life, but not only restrict it. Limits are also the conditions of possibility for human life and as such have productive, normative, and creative powers that not only delimit life but also scaffold growth and transformation within it. The paper takes a less known interpretation of the term ‘ephēmeros', to mean ‘of the day', rather than ‘short-lived' and suggests that as ephemeral, human life is contingent and mutable, subject to events beyond our control. However, virtue can still be exercised – indeed, can be exuberantly displayed – when we respond to contingent events marked by adversity.","PeriodicalId":269662,"journal":{"name":"Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"130619689","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Why Do People Want to Die? The Meaning of Life from the Perspective of Euthanasia 人们为什么想死?从安乐死看生命的意义
Pub Date : 2021-10-01 DOI: 10.1017/s1358246121000333
F. Svenaeus
Abstract One way to examine the enigmatic meaningfulness of human life is to ask under which conditions persons ask in earnest for assistance to die, either through euthanasia or physician assisted suicide. The counterpart of intolerable suffering must consist in some form of, however minimal, flourishing that makes people want to go on with their lives, disregarding other reasons to reject assisted dying that have more to do with religious prohibitions. To learn more about why persons want to hasten death during the last days, weeks or months of their lives, what kinds of suffering they fear and what they hold to be the main reasons to carry on or not carry on living, the paper offers some examples from a book written by the physician Uwe-Christian Arnold. He has helped hundreds of persons in Germany to die with the aid of sedative drugs the last 25 years, despite the professional societies and codes in Germany that prohibit such actions. The paper discusses various examples from Arnold's book and makes use of them to better understand not only why people sometimes want to die but what made their lives meaningful before they reached this final decision.
研究人类生命的神秘意义的一种方法是询问人们在哪些条件下认真地要求帮助死亡,无论是通过安乐死还是医生协助自杀。与无法忍受的痛苦相对应的,必须是某种形式的繁荣,无论多么微小,它都能让人们想要继续他们的生活,而不顾其他原因拒绝协助死亡,这些原因更多地与宗教禁令有关。为了进一步了解为什么人们在生命的最后几天、几周或几个月里想要加速死亡,他们害怕什么样的痛苦,以及他们认为继续或不继续生活的主要原因是什么,这篇论文提供了医生Uwe-Christian Arnold写的一本书中的一些例子。在过去的25年里,他帮助了数百名德国人在镇静剂的帮助下死去,尽管德国的专业协会和法规禁止这种行为。本文讨论了阿诺德书中的各种例子,并利用它们来更好地理解为什么人们有时想死,而且在他们做出最后决定之前,是什么让他们的生活变得有意义。
{"title":"Why Do People Want to Die? The Meaning of Life from the Perspective of Euthanasia","authors":"F. Svenaeus","doi":"10.1017/s1358246121000333","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/s1358246121000333","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract One way to examine the enigmatic meaningfulness of human life is to ask under which conditions persons ask in earnest for assistance to die, either through euthanasia or physician assisted suicide. The counterpart of intolerable suffering must consist in some form of, however minimal, flourishing that makes people want to go on with their lives, disregarding other reasons to reject assisted dying that have more to do with religious prohibitions. To learn more about why persons want to hasten death during the last days, weeks or months of their lives, what kinds of suffering they fear and what they hold to be the main reasons to carry on or not carry on living, the paper offers some examples from a book written by the physician Uwe-Christian Arnold. He has helped hundreds of persons in Germany to die with the aid of sedative drugs the last 25 years, despite the professional societies and codes in Germany that prohibit such actions. The paper discusses various examples from Arnold's book and makes use of them to better understand not only why people sometimes want to die but what made their lives meaningful before they reached this final decision.","PeriodicalId":269662,"journal":{"name":"Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement","volume":"2 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"122191904","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Introduction: Death and Meaning 导论:死亡与意义
Pub Date : 2021-10-01 DOI: 10.1017/S1358246121000205
M. Hauskeller
Due to the Covid pandemic, the Royal Institute of Philosophy Annual Conference 2020 had to be postponed and was eventually held online in July 2021. The conference, on which this volume is based, was meant to explore the connection between death and meaning (in life). What motivated me to host a conference on that particular theme was initially my interest in the philosophical debate on human enhancement and the possibility and desirability (or undesirability) of radical life extension. Naturally, that debate is complex and touches on many different aspects of the human condition. However, there is one claim in particular that captured my attention because the question it raised struck me as being of fundamental importance for the entire discussion. It is the claim, occasionally made by transhumanists and other proponents of radical life extension, that death undercuts meaning, in the sense that as long as our lives will have to end someday, our lives cannot possibly be meaningful (More, 1990). Even religion with its promise of a life after death, it is alleged, can only ever achieve the illusion of meaning, but never the real thing. This is mainly because true meaningfulness cannot be derived from being part of somebody else’s (in this case God’s) plan, which supposedly has the inevitable effect of stifling a sense of our own personal value. Yet it is claimed that without such a sense of personal value our (individual) lives must lack true meaning, for what gives our lives (true) meaning is ‘the continuation of the process of improvement and transformation of ourselves into ever higher forms’ (More, 1990, p. 10). Since this process is understood as open-ended, it is clear that death, by bringing it to an end, destroys not only the meaning that any individual life can have up to the point of its termination, but the very possibility of meaning. If our lives can only have meaning if we can pursue ‘our own expansion and progress without end’ (More, 1990, p. 12), then life can only be meaningful if it never ends. That connection to meaning may well play a part in why death is often perceived and described as the greatest evil. It is the greatest of evils not merely because it sets an end to
由于新冠肺炎疫情,英国皇家哲学研究所2020年年会不得不推迟,最终于2021年7月在网上举行。这本书的基础是这次会议,旨在探讨死亡与(生命中的)意义之间的联系。促使我举办这个特别主题会议的原因,最初是我对人类增强以及激进延长寿命的可能性和可取性(或不可取性)的哲学辩论感兴趣。当然,这场辩论是复杂的,涉及人类状况的许多不同方面。然而,有一种说法特别引起了我的注意,因为它提出的问题对整个讨论具有根本性的重要性。超人类主义者和其他激进延长生命的支持者偶尔会说,死亡削弱了生命的意义,因为只要我们的生命总有一天会结束,我们的生命就不可能有意义(More, 1990)。据称,即使是承诺死后生命的宗教,也只能实现意义的幻觉,而永远无法实现真正的意义。这主要是因为真正的意义不能从成为别人(在这种情况下是上帝)计划的一部分中获得,这被认为会不可避免地扼杀我们自己的个人价值感。然而,有人声称,如果没有这种个人价值感,我们(个体)的生活必然缺乏真正的意义,因为赋予我们生活(真正)意义的是“不断改进和将我们自己转化为更高形式的过程”(More, 1990, p. 10)。由于这一过程被理解为开放式的,很明显,死亡结束了这一过程,不仅摧毁了任何个体生命在其结束时所能拥有的意义,而且摧毁了意义的可能性。如果我们的生命只有在追求“无止境的自我扩展和进步”时才有意义(More, 1990, p. 12),那么生命只有在永不结束时才有意义。这种与意义的联系很可能在一定程度上解释了为什么死亡经常被认为是最大的邪恶。它是最大的罪恶不仅仅因为它终结
{"title":"Introduction: Death and Meaning","authors":"M. Hauskeller","doi":"10.1017/S1358246121000205","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S1358246121000205","url":null,"abstract":"Due to the Covid pandemic, the Royal Institute of Philosophy Annual Conference 2020 had to be postponed and was eventually held online in July 2021. The conference, on which this volume is based, was meant to explore the connection between death and meaning (in life). What motivated me to host a conference on that particular theme was initially my interest in the philosophical debate on human enhancement and the possibility and desirability (or undesirability) of radical life extension. Naturally, that debate is complex and touches on many different aspects of the human condition. However, there is one claim in particular that captured my attention because the question it raised struck me as being of fundamental importance for the entire discussion. It is the claim, occasionally made by transhumanists and other proponents of radical life extension, that death undercuts meaning, in the sense that as long as our lives will have to end someday, our lives cannot possibly be meaningful (More, 1990). Even religion with its promise of a life after death, it is alleged, can only ever achieve the illusion of meaning, but never the real thing. This is mainly because true meaningfulness cannot be derived from being part of somebody else’s (in this case God’s) plan, which supposedly has the inevitable effect of stifling a sense of our own personal value. Yet it is claimed that without such a sense of personal value our (individual) lives must lack true meaning, for what gives our lives (true) meaning is ‘the continuation of the process of improvement and transformation of ourselves into ever higher forms’ (More, 1990, p. 10). Since this process is understood as open-ended, it is clear that death, by bringing it to an end, destroys not only the meaning that any individual life can have up to the point of its termination, but the very possibility of meaning. If our lives can only have meaning if we can pursue ‘our own expansion and progress without end’ (More, 1990, p. 12), then life can only be meaningful if it never ends. That connection to meaning may well play a part in why death is often perceived and described as the greatest evil. It is the greatest of evils not merely because it sets an end to","PeriodicalId":269662,"journal":{"name":"Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement","volume":"88 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"122898862","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Promises to the Dead 对死者的承诺
Pub Date : 2021-10-01 DOI: 10.1017/S1358246121000242
J. Taylor
Abstract Many people attempt to give meaning to their lives by pursuing projects that they believe will bear fruit after they have died. Knowing that their death will preclude them from protecting or promoting such projects people who draw meaning from them will often attempt to secure their continuance by securing promises from others to serve as their caretakers after they die. But those who rely on such are faced with a problem: None of the four major accounts that have been developed to explain directed promissory obligation (the Authority View, the Trust View, the Assurance View, and the Reliance View) support the view that we are obligated to keep our promises to persons who are now dead. But I will provide hope for those who wish to use such promises to protect the meaning with which they have endowed their lives. I will argue that while we cannot wrong a person who is now dead by breaking a promise made to her during her life, we could wrong the living by so doing. We thus (might) have reason to keep the promises that we made to those who are now dead.
许多人试图通过追求他们相信在他们死后会有成果的项目来赋予他们的生命意义。知道他们的死亡将使他们无法保护或促进这些项目,那些从这些项目中获得意义的人往往会试图通过从其他人那里获得承诺,在他们死后担任他们的照顾者,来确保这些项目的延续。但是那些依赖这些观点的人面临着一个问题:四种主要的解释直接承诺义务的观点(权威观点、信任观点、保证观点和信赖观点)都不支持我们有义务履行我们对已经死去的人的承诺的观点。但是,对于那些希望用这样的承诺来保护自己赋予生命的意义的人,我将给他们带来希望。我认为,虽然我们不能因为违背生前对一个人的承诺而冤枉一个已经死去的人,但这样做却可能冤枉一个活着的人。因此,我们有理由遵守我们对那些已经死去的人所作的承诺。
{"title":"Promises to the Dead","authors":"J. Taylor","doi":"10.1017/S1358246121000242","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S1358246121000242","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Many people attempt to give meaning to their lives by pursuing projects that they believe will bear fruit after they have died. Knowing that their death will preclude them from protecting or promoting such projects people who draw meaning from them will often attempt to secure their continuance by securing promises from others to serve as their caretakers after they die. But those who rely on such are faced with a problem: None of the four major accounts that have been developed to explain directed promissory obligation (the Authority View, the Trust View, the Assurance View, and the Reliance View) support the view that we are obligated to keep our promises to persons who are now dead. But I will provide hope for those who wish to use such promises to protect the meaning with which they have endowed their lives. I will argue that while we cannot wrong a person who is now dead by breaking a promise made to her during her life, we could wrong the living by so doing. We thus (might) have reason to keep the promises that we made to those who are now dead.","PeriodicalId":269662,"journal":{"name":"Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement","volume":"22 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"124876309","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Notes on the Contributors 投稿人备注
Pub Date : 2021-10-01 DOI: 10.1017/S1358246121000199
H. Carel
Havi Carel is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Bristol. She recently completed a Wellcome Trust Senior Investigator Award, the Life of Breath. She was awarded the Health Humanities’ Inspiration Award 2018 for this work. Her third monograph, Phenomenology of Illness, was published by Oxford University Press in 2016. She was selected as a ‘Best of Bristol’ lecturer in 2016. Havi is the author of Illness (2008, 2013, 2018), shortlisted for the Wellcome Trust Book Prize, and of Life and Death in Freud and Heidegger (2006). She is the co-editor of Health, Illness and Disease (2012), New Takes in Film-Philosophy (2010), and of What Philosophy Is (2004).
哈维·卡瑞尔是布里斯托尔大学的哲学教授。她最近完成了威康信托高级研究员奖,呼吸的生命。她因这项工作被授予2018年健康人文学科灵感奖。她的第三部专著《疾病现象学》于2016年由牛津大学出版社出版。2016年,她被选为“布里斯托尔最佳讲师”。哈维著有《疾病》(2008年、2013年、2018年)和《弗洛伊德与海德格尔的生与死》(2006年),该书曾入围惠康信托图书奖。她是《健康、疾病与疾病》(2012年)、《电影哲学新视角》(2010年)和《哲学是什么》(2004年)的联合编辑。
{"title":"Notes on the Contributors","authors":"H. Carel","doi":"10.1017/S1358246121000199","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S1358246121000199","url":null,"abstract":"Havi Carel is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Bristol. She recently completed a Wellcome Trust Senior Investigator Award, the Life of Breath. She was awarded the Health Humanities’ Inspiration Award 2018 for this work. Her third monograph, Phenomenology of Illness, was published by Oxford University Press in 2016. She was selected as a ‘Best of Bristol’ lecturer in 2016. Havi is the author of Illness (2008, 2013, 2018), shortlisted for the Wellcome Trust Book Prize, and of Life and Death in Freud and Heidegger (2006). She is the co-editor of Health, Illness and Disease (2012), New Takes in Film-Philosophy (2010), and of What Philosophy Is (2004).","PeriodicalId":269662,"journal":{"name":"Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"115516807","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
God, The Meaning of Life, and Meaningful Lives 上帝,生命的意义,有意义的生活
Pub Date : 2021-10-01 DOI: 10.1017/S1358246121000266
D. Hill
Abstract In my 2002 piece ‘The Meaning of Life’ I argued that Life, meaning the sum of the lives of all living things, had a meaning if and only if it had been purposefully brought about by a designer or creator. Michael Hauskeller has recently criticized this argument, responding that this sense of ‘meaning’ is not the one in view when we are discussing ‘the meaning of life’. In this piece I respond to Hauskeller's argument, and, while I stand by my 2002 argument in terms of one meaning of ‘meaning’, I admit that it does not apply to the different question of what makes a life meaningful. I assert that glorifying God is the activity that contributes the most meaningfulness to a life, though I deny that this is the only activity that can contribute meaningfulness to a life. This makes me, in terms due to Thaddeus Metz, a moderate supernaturalist rather than an extreme supernaturalist. Despite this distinction, Metz has argued in this volume that moderate supernaturalism is vulnerable to the same objection as in his view defeats extreme supernaturalism, and I close by responding to this argument.
在我2002年的文章《生命的意义》中,我认为生命是所有生物生命的总和,当且仅当它被设计师或创造者有意地创造出来时才有意义。Michael Hauskeller最近批评了这种观点,他回应说,当我们讨论“生命的意义”时,这种“意义”的感觉并不是我们所考虑的。在这篇文章中,我对豪斯凯勒的观点做出了回应,虽然我坚持2002年关于“意义”的一种含义的观点,但我承认,它并不适用于使生活有意义的其他问题。我断言,荣耀上帝是使人生最有意义的活动,尽管我否认这是使人生最有意义的唯一活动。用梅斯的话来说,这使我成为一个温和的超自然主义者,而不是极端的超自然主义者。尽管有这种区别,梅斯在这本书中认为,温和的超自然主义很容易受到反对,就像他认为击败极端的超自然主义一样,我以回应这个论点来结束。
{"title":"God, The Meaning of Life, and Meaningful Lives","authors":"D. Hill","doi":"10.1017/S1358246121000266","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1017/S1358246121000266","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract In my 2002 piece ‘The Meaning of Life’ I argued that Life, meaning the sum of the lives of all living things, had a meaning if and only if it had been purposefully brought about by a designer or creator. Michael Hauskeller has recently criticized this argument, responding that this sense of ‘meaning’ is not the one in view when we are discussing ‘the meaning of life’. In this piece I respond to Hauskeller's argument, and, while I stand by my 2002 argument in terms of one meaning of ‘meaning’, I admit that it does not apply to the different question of what makes a life meaningful. I assert that glorifying God is the activity that contributes the most meaningfulness to a life, though I deny that this is the only activity that can contribute meaningfulness to a life. This makes me, in terms due to Thaddeus Metz, a moderate supernaturalist rather than an extreme supernaturalist. Despite this distinction, Metz has argued in this volume that moderate supernaturalism is vulnerable to the same objection as in his view defeats extreme supernaturalism, and I close by responding to this argument.","PeriodicalId":269662,"journal":{"name":"Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement","volume":"16 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2021-10-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"125784443","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1