首页 > 最新文献

Epistemology & Philosophy of Science最新文献

英文 中文
Post-structuralism 后结构主义
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/eps202360230
V. Schulz, Tatiana M. Lyubimova
The article draws a conceptual distinction the (French) structuralism of the 50’s–60’s and the post-structuralism of the 70’s, which are discussed as overlapping in their intellectual paths; their mutual dynamics is defined as a reaction of the intelligence to the pressure of depersonalized unified schemes within the logic of structuralism against free improvisation and loose interpretation instead of total explanations in the post-structuralism interpretation. The article establishes a conceptual identity of the paradoxical nature between post-structuralism (and deconstructionism, which is homogeneous and identical thereto in a number of aspects), on the one hand, and constructionism with its specific process of language dismantling – social/ideological languages, social group dialects, on the other hand, which naturally leads the authors to the analysis of the paradoxicality principles, defined by post-structuralism (five principles of paradoxicality of Gilles Deleuze – paradox of regress, paradox of sterile reiteration, paradox of neutrality, paradox of absurd, paradox of Levi-Strauss); poststructuralists’ paralogisms are examined through paradoxical denotation; the late Roland Barthes’ phenomenon of paradoxicality, becoming a plot-forming principle of narration, is analyzed. Poststructuralism is conceptualized in the article as the first decisive step of post-modernism; the affinity of post-structuralist and postmodernist commitment to parody, game and irony is stated; the theory of language games in post-modern interpretation is explored; one of those games – a game of carnival – is explored within the diachronic retrospective; the affinity of parody and carnival tradition of post-structuralism and post-modernism to the romantic irony of the XIXth century and its inconsistency with the popular culture of laugh is established. The genesis of poststructuralism and post-modernism is connected with the ideological restart of the Western society before the “very end” of the Resistance ideas and the disappointment of the left European intellectuals in the “great legends” and illusions of Marxism. The blurred concepts of relativism are connected with the mutual disproportion of different layers of historical experience.
文章对五六十年代的(法国)结构主义和七十年代的后结构主义进行了概念上的区分,认为它们在思想路径上是重叠的;它们的相互动态被定义为智能对结构主义逻辑中去个性化的统一方案的压力的反应,反对自由即兴和松散的解释,而不是在后结构主义解释中全面的解释。文章建立了一种矛盾性的概念认同,即后结构主义(与解构主义在许多方面同质一致)与建构主义及其具体的语言解构过程——社会/意识形态语言、社会群体方言之间的矛盾性,从而自然而然地引导作者对矛盾性原则进行分析。由后结构主义定义(德勒兹的五项悖论原则——回归的悖论、乏味的重复的悖论、中立的悖论、荒谬的悖论、列维-斯特劳斯的悖论);后结构主义者的谬误推理是通过悖论外延来检验的;分析了罗兰·巴特的悖论现象成为叙事的一种情节形成原则。文章将后结构主义定义为后现代主义的决定性的第一步;论述了后结构主义和后现代主义对戏仿、游戏和反讽的认同;后现代口译中的语言游戏理论探讨其中一个游戏——狂欢游戏——在历时回顾中被探索;确立了后结构主义和后现代主义的戏仿和狂欢传统与19世纪浪漫反讽的亲和性及其与大众笑文化的不一致性。后结构主义和后现代主义的产生与抵抗运动思想“最后”之前西方社会意识形态的重新启动以及欧洲左翼知识分子对马克思主义“伟大传说”和幻想的失望有关。相对主义概念的模糊与历史经验不同层次的相互失衡有关。
{"title":"Post-structuralism","authors":"V. Schulz, Tatiana M. Lyubimova","doi":"10.5840/eps202360230","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/eps202360230","url":null,"abstract":"The article draws a conceptual distinction the (French) structuralism of the 50’s–60’s and the post-structuralism of the 70’s, which are discussed as overlapping in their intellectual paths; their mutual dynamics is defined as a reaction of the intelligence to the pressure of depersonalized unified schemes within the logic of structuralism against free improvisation and loose interpretation instead of total explanations in the post-structuralism interpretation. The article establishes a conceptual identity of the paradoxical nature between post-structuralism (and deconstructionism, which is homogeneous and identical thereto in a number of aspects), on the one hand, and constructionism with its specific process of language dismantling – social/ideological languages, social group dialects, on the other hand, which naturally leads the authors to the analysis of the paradoxicality principles, defined by post-structuralism (five principles of paradoxicality of Gilles Deleuze – paradox of regress, paradox of sterile reiteration, paradox of neutrality, paradox of absurd, paradox of Levi-Strauss); poststructuralists’ paralogisms are examined through paradoxical denotation; the late Roland Barthes’ phenomenon of paradoxicality, becoming a plot-forming principle of narration, is analyzed. Poststructuralism is conceptualized in the article as the first decisive step of post-modernism; the affinity of post-structuralist and postmodernist commitment to parody, game and irony is stated; the theory of language games in post-modern interpretation is explored; one of those games – a game of carnival – is explored within the diachronic retrospective; the affinity of parody and carnival tradition of post-structuralism and post-modernism to the romantic irony of the XIXth century and its inconsistency with the popular culture of laugh is established. The genesis of poststructuralism and post-modernism is connected with the ideological restart of the Western society before the “very end” of the Resistance ideas and the disappointment of the left European intellectuals in the “great legends” and illusions of Marxism. The blurred concepts of relativism are connected with the mutual disproportion of different layers of historical experience.","PeriodicalId":369041,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science","volume":"72 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"126363606","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Счастливая (не)случайность: серендипность как фактор решения научных проблем 幸运(非)意外:科学问题的解决因素
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/eps20236014
Артем Маркович Фейгельман
The article considers the concept of serendipity (the ability to make unexpected discoveries) in comparison with the concept of “epistemological randomization” introduced by A.M. Dorozhkin and S.V. Shibarshina. The genesis and content of the concept of “serendipity” in the interpretation of American sociologists R. Merton and E. Barber are revealed. The division of serendipity into three types is considered depending on the source and result of an unexpected scientific discovery. The first type of serendipity refers to a situation of random observation, when neither the observation itself nor the conclusions drawn from it are part of the research already being carried out. The second type of serendipity is associated with the process of finding a solution to one problem, which suddenly leads to a solution to another. A third type of serendipity can arise when investigating a familiar problem, when the solution comes from an unexpected source. It is concluded that epistemological randomization, which is introduced into an existing study, is similar to the second and third types of serendipity, where the randomness factor is limited. In conclusion, it is emphasized that, in contrast to the principle of epistemological randomization, serendipity is an emergent phenomenon and cannot be caused consciously. Serendipity is manifested where an unexpected phenomenon meets a special type of subject who is able to notice and fruitfully interpret an unusual phenomenon.
本文将偶然性(做出意外发现的能力)的概念与A.M.引入的“认识论随机化”的概念进行比较多罗日金和S.V.柴希纳。揭示了美国社会学家默顿(R. Merton)和巴伯(E. Barber)对“偶然性”(serendipity)概念解释的起源和内容。根据意外科学发现的来源和结果,将意外发现分为三种类型。第一类意外发现指的是一种随机观察的情况,当观察本身和从中得出的结论都不是已经进行的研究的一部分。第二种类型的意外发现与找到一个问题的解决方案的过程有关,这个过程会突然导致另一个问题的解决方案。第三种类型的意外发现可能出现在调查一个熟悉的问题时,当解决方案来自一个意想不到的来源时。结论是,引入现有研究的认识论随机化与第二种和第三种偶然性相似,其中随机因素是有限的。总之,强调与认识论随机化原则相反,偶然性是一种突现现象,不能有意识地引起。当一个意想不到的现象遇到一个特殊类型的主体,他能够注意到并富有成效地解释一个不寻常的现象时,Serendipity就表现出来了。
{"title":"Счастливая (не)случайность: серендипность как фактор решения научных проблем","authors":"Артем Маркович Фейгельман","doi":"10.5840/eps20236014","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/eps20236014","url":null,"abstract":"The article considers the concept of serendipity (the ability to make unexpected discoveries) in comparison with the concept of “epistemological randomization” introduced by A.M. Dorozhkin and S.V. Shibarshina. The genesis and content of the concept of “serendipity” in the interpretation of American sociologists R. Merton and E. Barber are revealed. The division of serendipity into three types is considered depending on the source and result of an unexpected scientific discovery. The first type of serendipity refers to a situation of random observation, when neither the observation itself nor the conclusions drawn from it are part of the research already being carried out. The second type of serendipity is associated with the process of finding a solution to one problem, which suddenly leads to a solution to another. A third type of serendipity can arise when investigating a familiar problem, when the solution comes from an unexpected source. It is concluded that epistemological randomization, which is introduced into an existing study, is similar to the second and third types of serendipity, where the randomness factor is limited. In conclusion, it is emphasized that, in contrast to the principle of epistemological randomization, serendipity is an emergent phenomenon and cannot be caused consciously. Serendipity is manifested where an unexpected phenomenon meets a special type of subject who is able to notice and fruitfully interpret an unusual phenomenon.","PeriodicalId":369041,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science","volume":"10 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"126551132","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Structure of Agentive Awareness in Kent Bach’s Representational Theory of Action 肯特·巴赫表征行为理论中的代理意识结构
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/eps202360229
Artem S. Yashin
This paper analyzes Kent Bach’s representational theory of action, one of the causal theories of action. Bach’s theory sets requirements not only for the cause of an action, but also for how it unfolds in time and transitions into another action. These requirements suggest a sequential emergence of two components of the agent’s action awareness: the representation of the prepared movement and the perception of its sensory consequences. Bach introduces the concepts of “effective representation” (ER) and “receptive representation” (RR) to denote these components of awareness. According to representational theory, action has a cyclic three-step causal structure, where ER is the cause of a movement, the movement is the cause of RR, and RR is the cause of ER of subsequent movement. In constructing his theory, Bach tries to take into account the problem of deviant causal chains and to introduce the so-called minimal actions into the purview of the philosophy of action. Relying on the behavioral data on blindfolded deafferentated patients, in this paper I argue that RRs are not a necessary element of action. I also analyze Bach’s distinction between ER and RR and compare it with J. Searle’s approach, placing Bach’s theory within the context of studies of the structure of intentional states. I show that Bach’s theory occupies a unique position among views on the structure of action awareness. At the same time, I conclude that the frameworks of Bach and Searle are insufficient for describing the metaphysical difference between the two kinds of intentional states, and I also point out the difficulties facing the notion of ER. Based on this reasoning and the data on deafferentated patients, I propose a modification of the causal structure of action proposed by Bach, making a remark about the inadequate definition of ER. In the proposed modification, RR and the agent’s prior intention serve as alternative components of action awareness.
本文分析了肯特·巴赫的因果行为理论之一的表征行为理论。巴赫的理论不仅对一个动作的原因设定了要求,而且对它如何在时间中展开并过渡到另一个动作也设定了要求。这些要求表明,主体的动作意识的两个组成部分依次出现:准备动作的表示和其感官结果的感知。巴赫引入了“有效表征”(ER)和“接受表征”(RR)的概念来表示意识的这些组成部分。表征理论认为,动作有一个循环的三步因果结构,ER是一个动作的原因,动作是RR的原因,RR是后续动作的ER的原因。巴赫在建构他的理论时,试图考虑到偏差因果链的问题,并将所谓的最小行动引入行动哲学的范围。根据蒙眼失联患者的行为数据,在本文中,我认为rr不是行动的必要因素。我还分析了巴赫对ER和RR的区分,并将其与J. Searle的方法进行了比较,将巴赫的理论置于意图状态结构研究的背景下。巴赫的理论在关于行动意识结构的各种观点中占有独特的地位。同时,我得出结论,巴赫和塞尔的框架不足以描述两种意向状态之间的形而上学差异,我也指出了ER概念面临的困难。基于这一推理和去分化患者的数据,我提出对Bach提出的作用的因果结构进行修改,对ER的定义不充分进行评论。在提议的修改中,RR和agent的先前意图作为行动意识的替代成分。
{"title":"The Structure of Agentive Awareness in Kent Bach’s Representational Theory of Action","authors":"Artem S. Yashin","doi":"10.5840/eps202360229","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/eps202360229","url":null,"abstract":"This paper analyzes Kent Bach’s representational theory of action, one of the causal theories of action. Bach’s theory sets requirements not only for the cause of an action, but also for how it unfolds in time and transitions into another action. These requirements suggest a sequential emergence of two components of the agent’s action awareness: the representation of the prepared movement and the perception of its sensory consequences. Bach introduces the concepts of “effective representation” (ER) and “receptive representation” (RR) to denote these components of awareness. According to representational theory, action has a cyclic three-step causal structure, where ER is the cause of a movement, the movement is the cause of RR, and RR is the cause of ER of subsequent movement. In constructing his theory, Bach tries to take into account the problem of deviant causal chains and to introduce the so-called minimal actions into the purview of the philosophy of action. Relying on the behavioral data on blindfolded deafferentated patients, in this paper I argue that RRs are not a necessary element of action. I also analyze Bach’s distinction between ER and RR and compare it with J. Searle’s approach, placing Bach’s theory within the context of studies of the structure of intentional states. I show that Bach’s theory occupies a unique position among views on the structure of action awareness. At the same time, I conclude that the frameworks of Bach and Searle are insufficient for describing the metaphysical difference between the two kinds of intentional states, and I also point out the difficulties facing the notion of ER. Based on this reasoning and the data on deafferentated patients, I propose a modification of the causal structure of action proposed by Bach, making a remark about the inadequate definition of ER. In the proposed modification, RR and the agent’s prior intention serve as alternative components of action awareness.","PeriodicalId":369041,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science","volume":"46 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"132380319","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Epistemic Autonomy, Authority and Trust: In Defense of Zagzebski’s Theory 认识自治、权威与信任:为扎格布斯基理论辩护
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/eps202259346
D. Maslov
Epistemic authority, according to L. Zagzebski’s theory, is essentially based on deliberative or first-personal reasons, which originate from epistemic admiration. In what follows, I shortly reconstruct her theory and try to defend it against two critical arguments. The first argument calls attention to circular relation of epistemic autonomy and authority. In order to determine the authoritative person for me, I always have to possess epistemic autonomy, which is understood as knowledge in the given domain. Thus I myself have to have authority in the given domain in order to invest authority. I try to show that the investment of trust is based upon autonomy interpreted as an ability to exercise epistemic actions, accompanied by normative foreknowledge, that allows us to assess epistemic abilities and invest our trust without having sufficient propositional knowledge. The second argument insists on theoretical control for authoritative evidence and testimony. That contradicts preemptive character and content-independence inherent to authoritative testimony. Hence, this argument entirely misses the point of epistemic authority. Instead, as I argue, one can control epistemic authority by future reflexion on its conscientiousness and epistemic exercise as well as on origins of my admiration for authority. As a consequence, the trust invested in authority can be withdrawn and redistributed.
根据L. Zagzebski的理论,认识论的权威本质上是基于深思熟虑的或第一人称的原因,这源于对认识论的钦佩。在接下来的文章中,我简要地重构了她的理论,并试图反驳两个关键的论点。第一个论点要求注意认识自主性和权威的循环关系。为了为我确定权威的人,我总是必须拥有认知自主权,这被理解为给定领域的知识。因此,我自己必须在给定的领域拥有权威,才能赋予权威。我试图证明信任的投入是建立在自主性的基础上的,自主性被解释为一种行使认知行为的能力,伴随着规范性的预知,这使我们能够在没有足够的命题知识的情况下评估认知能力并投入信任。第二种观点坚持对权威证据和证言进行理论控制。这与权威证词固有的抢先性和内容独立性相矛盾。因此,这个论点完全忽略了认识论的权威。相反,正如我所说的,人们可以通过未来对认识论权威的严谨性和认识论实践的反思以及对我对权威的钦佩的起源的反思来控制认识论权威。因此,投资于权威的信任可以撤回并重新分配。
{"title":"Epistemic Autonomy, Authority and Trust: In Defense of Zagzebski’s Theory","authors":"D. Maslov","doi":"10.5840/eps202259346","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/eps202259346","url":null,"abstract":"Epistemic authority, according to L. Zagzebski’s theory, is essentially based on deliberative or first-personal reasons, which originate from epistemic admiration. In what follows, I shortly reconstruct her theory and try to defend it against two critical arguments. The first argument calls attention to circular relation of epistemic autonomy and authority. In order to determine the authoritative person for me, I always have to possess epistemic autonomy, which is understood as knowledge in the given domain. Thus I myself have to have authority in the given domain in order to invest authority. I try to show that the investment of trust is based upon autonomy interpreted as an ability to exercise epistemic actions, accompanied by normative foreknowledge, that allows us to assess epistemic abilities and invest our trust without having sufficient propositional knowledge. The second argument insists on theoretical control for authoritative evidence and testimony. That contradicts preemptive character and content-independence inherent to authoritative testimony. Hence, this argument entirely misses the point of epistemic authority. Instead, as I argue, one can control epistemic authority by future reflexion on its conscientiousness and epistemic exercise as well as on origins of my admiration for authority. As a consequence, the trust invested in authority can be withdrawn and redistributed.","PeriodicalId":369041,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"130050661","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
From “Paradigm” to “Disciplinary Matrix”: A Fatal Step 从“范式”到“学科矩阵”:致命的一步
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/eps202259459
Nataliya I. Kuznetsova
The citation index of Thomas Kuhn’s work may strike any imagination. “The Structure of Scientific Revolutions” (first edition 1962) is undoubtedly a twentieth-century record-breaker in the field of philosophy of science in terms of such a scientometric parameter. But such fame has been bitter in many ways and placed a heavy burden on the author. For several decades he has been the target of the harshest and most severe criticism. Often the concept of “normal science” and the “scientific revolution” as a “Gestalt switch” was declared ridiculous and absurd. The paper analyses three lines of criticism of Kuhn’s concept: the first came from practicing scientists, the second from specialists in the philosophy of science (primarily proponents of “critical rationalism”), and the third from the field of social epistemology. Reproaches about the political bias of Kuhn’s concept were taken to extremes, since his views were widely popular. In our opinion, Kuhn should be called a victim of spontaneous hypercriticism. This circumstance did not allow him to improve the original model of scientific revolutions. In this respect, replacing the concept of “paradigm” with the concept of “disciplinary matrix” was a step backwards, not forwards. However, it is impossible to deny that in the field of the historiography of science, he acted as a real reformer. With the courage of Don Quixote, he defended the rights of historical reconstruction, the preservation of the historical past of science, which should not be completely assimilated within the framework of the modern system of knowledge. His motto was – “penetrate the minds of other people who lived in the past.” He boldly argued that in the process of historical development, science changes not only ideas about the object of knowledge (representations of the object), but also the reference of its ideas and concepts. Such a formulation of the question has not yet been fully reflected in modern epistemological concepts.
托马斯·库恩著作的引文索引可能会出乎任何人的想象。《科学革命的结构》(1962年第一版)就科学计量参数而言,无疑是20世纪科学哲学领域的破纪录之作。但这样的名声在很多方面都是痛苦的,给作者带来了沉重的负担。几十年来,他一直是最严厉和最严厉批评的目标。通常,“常规科学”和“科学革命”的概念被认为是“格式塔开关”,是荒谬和荒谬的。本文分析了对库恩概念的三种批评:第一种来自实践科学家,第二种来自科学哲学专家(主要是“批判理性主义”的支持者),第三种来自社会认识论领域。由于库恩的观点广受欢迎,对他的政治偏见的指责被推向了极端。在我们看来,库恩应该被称为自发的过度批评的受害者。这种情况不允许他改进最初的科学革命模型。在这方面,用“学科矩阵”的概念取代“范式”的概念是一种倒退,而不是进步。然而,不可否认的是,在科学史学领域,他是一个真正的改革者。以堂吉诃德的勇气,他捍卫了重建历史的权利,捍卫了保存科学的历史,不应该完全被现代知识体系的框架所同化。他的座右铭是“洞悉生活在过去的人们的思想”。他大胆地认为,在历史发展的过程中,科学不仅改变了关于知识对象的观念(对象的表征),而且改变了其思想和概念的参照。这种问题的提法尚未充分反映在现代认识论概念中。
{"title":"From “Paradigm” to “Disciplinary Matrix”: A Fatal Step","authors":"Nataliya I. Kuznetsova","doi":"10.5840/eps202259459","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/eps202259459","url":null,"abstract":"The citation index of Thomas Kuhn’s work may strike any imagination. “The Structure of Scientific Revolutions” (first edition 1962) is undoubtedly a twentieth-century record-breaker in the field of philosophy of science in terms of such a scientometric parameter. But such fame has been bitter in many ways and placed a heavy burden on the author. For several decades he has been the target of the harshest and most severe criticism. Often the concept of “normal science” and the “scientific revolution” as a “Gestalt switch” was declared ridiculous and absurd. The paper analyses three lines of criticism of Kuhn’s concept: the first came from practicing scientists, the second from specialists in the philosophy of science (primarily proponents of “critical rationalism”), and the third from the field of social epistemology. Reproaches about the political bias of Kuhn’s concept were taken to extremes, since his views were widely popular. In our opinion, Kuhn should be called a victim of spontaneous hypercriticism. This circumstance did not allow him to improve the original model of scientific revolutions. In this respect, replacing the concept of “paradigm” with the concept of “disciplinary matrix” was a step backwards, not forwards. However, it is impossible to deny that in the field of the historiography of science, he acted as a real reformer. With the courage of Don Quixote, he defended the rights of historical reconstruction, the preservation of the historical past of science, which should not be completely assimilated within the framework of the modern system of knowledge. His motto was – “penetrate the minds of other people who lived in the past.” He boldly argued that in the process of historical development, science changes not only ideas about the object of knowledge (representations of the object), but also the reference of its ideas and concepts. Such a formulation of the question has not yet been fully reflected in modern epistemological concepts.","PeriodicalId":369041,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science","volume":"42 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"132996841","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Russian Aristocracy and Private Forms of Scientific Organization: The Case of Grand Duke Nikolai Mikhailovich 俄国贵族与科学组织的私人形式:以尼古拉·米哈伊洛维奇大公为例
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/eps202360116
M. Vinarski, T. Yusupova
The structure of Russian science of the XIX century was dominated by state forms of its organization. At the same time, there were also a few private (non-governmental) forms of research communities. One of the little-studied phenomena of scientific privacy is the so-called “kruzhok” (a little circle in Russian). The article examines the history of the formation and activity of one of such “kruzhoks”, formed in the 1880s–1890s around Grand Duke Nikolai Mikhailovich, who was seriously engaged in research in the field of lepidopterology (the branch of entomology studying butterflies, Lepidoptera). The role and significance of this “kruzhok” for the development of descriptive entomology in the situation of its weak institutionalization in Russia at the end of the XIX century are briefly considered, the course of scientific research of the Grand Duke and his entourage and the reasons for the termination of their activity are discussed. The history of this informal association is interpreted by us as a manifestation of the purposeful life-making of the Grand Duke, who thus tried to professionalize his hobby and enter the scientific community of entomologists on an equal footing, without breaking with his social environment and without going beyond the behavioral norms established by society for persons of his status. It is shown that the Nikolai Mikhailovich’s “kruzhok” became not only an instrument of his life-making, but also an influential center of Russian lepidopterology, the development of which was thereby given a powerful impetus.
十九世纪俄国科学的结构是由其组织的国家形式所支配的。与此同时,也有一些私人(非政府)形式的研究团体。一个很少被研究的科学隐私现象是所谓的“kruzhok”(俄语中的一个小圆圈)。这篇文章考察了一个这样的“kruzhoks”的形成和活动的历史,它是在19世纪80年代至90年代由尼古拉·米哈伊洛维奇大公(Nikolai Mikhailovich)周围形成的,他认真从事鳞翅目学领域的研究(昆虫学研究蝴蝶的分支,鳞翅目)。本文简要论述了在19世纪末俄罗斯描述昆虫学制度化薄弱的情况下,这位“kruzhok”对描述昆虫学发展的作用和意义,并讨论了大公及其随行人员的科学研究过程及其活动终止的原因。我们把这个非正式协会的历史解释为大公有目的的生活方式的表现,他试图将自己的爱好专业化,在平等的基础上进入昆虫学家的科学社区,而不打破他的社会环境,也不超越社会为他这种地位的人建立的行为规范。由此可见,Nikolai Mikhailovich的“kruzhok”不仅成为他一生的工具,而且成为俄罗斯鳞翅目学的一个有影响力的中心,从而有力地推动了鳞翅目学的发展。
{"title":"Russian Aristocracy and Private Forms of Scientific Organization: The Case of Grand Duke Nikolai Mikhailovich","authors":"M. Vinarski, T. Yusupova","doi":"10.5840/eps202360116","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/eps202360116","url":null,"abstract":"The structure of Russian science of the XIX century was dominated by state forms of its organization. At the same time, there were also a few private (non-governmental) forms of research communities. One of the little-studied phenomena of scientific privacy is the so-called “kruzhok” (a little circle in Russian). The article examines the history of the formation and activity of one of such “kruzhoks”, formed in the 1880s–1890s around Grand Duke Nikolai Mikhailovich, who was seriously engaged in research in the field of lepidopterology (the branch of entomology studying butterflies, Lepidoptera). The role and significance of this “kruzhok” for the development of descriptive entomology in the situation of its weak institutionalization in Russia at the end of the XIX century are briefly considered, the course of scientific research of the Grand Duke and his entourage and the reasons for the termination of their activity are discussed. The history of this informal association is interpreted by us as a manifestation of the purposeful life-making of the Grand Duke, who thus tried to professionalize his hobby and enter the scientific community of entomologists on an equal footing, without breaking with his social environment and without going beyond the behavioral norms established by society for persons of his status. It is shown that the Nikolai Mikhailovich’s “kruzhok” became not only an instrument of his life-making, but also an influential center of Russian lepidopterology, the development of which was thereby given a powerful impetus.","PeriodicalId":369041,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science","volume":"60 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"133012532","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Color Concepts as a Factor of Cognitive Penetration of Perception 色彩概念作为感知认知渗透的一个因素
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/eps202259229
K. G. Frolov, A. I. Ponomarev
The aim of the paper is to analyse the influence of linguistic concepts of an agent on the qualitative aspects of her perception. We examine conceptualist and non-conceptualist approaches to the problem of what the content of perceptions is. The conceptualist approach asserts that the content of perception is similar to the content of beliefs: both types of content are assumed to be expressible in language. The non-conceptualist approach to the content of perception assumes that the content of perception cannot be conceptualized due to too much information available to the agent through visual perception. However, the assumption about non-conceptual content of perception leads to some serious difficulties with explaining the phenomenon of cognitive penetration of perception. This is an empirically established fact that some cognitive states may influence on the qualitative aspects of agent’s perception. We show that cognitive penetration of perception implies that perception and those cognitive states which affect it should have comparable content and this mechanism is based on the influence of expectations on perception.
本文的目的是分析代理人的语言概念对其感知的定性方面的影响。我们检查概念主义和非概念主义的方法来解决什么是知觉的内容的问题。概念主义的观点认为,感知的内容与信念的内容是相似的:这两种类型的内容都被假定为可以用语言表达。感知内容的非概念化方法假设,由于主体通过视觉感知获得的信息太多,感知内容无法概念化。然而,关于知觉的非概念性内容的假设在解释知觉的认知渗透现象时带来了一些严重的困难。这是一个经验证明的事实,某些认知状态可能会影响主体感知的定性方面。我们的研究表明,感知的认知渗透意味着感知和那些影响它的认知状态应该具有可比性的内容,这种机制是基于期望对感知的影响。
{"title":"Color Concepts as a Factor of Cognitive Penetration of Perception","authors":"K. G. Frolov, A. I. Ponomarev","doi":"10.5840/eps202259229","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/eps202259229","url":null,"abstract":"The aim of the paper is to analyse the influence of linguistic concepts of an agent on the qualitative aspects of her perception. We examine conceptualist and non-conceptualist approaches to the problem of what the content of perceptions is. The conceptualist approach asserts that the content of perception is similar to the content of beliefs: both types of content are assumed to be expressible in language. The non-conceptualist approach to the content of perception assumes that the content of perception cannot be conceptualized due to too much information available to the agent through visual perception. However, the assumption about non-conceptual content of perception leads to some serious difficulties with explaining the phenomenon of cognitive penetration of perception. This is an empirically established fact that some cognitive states may influence on the qualitative aspects of agent’s perception. We show that cognitive penetration of perception implies that perception and those cognitive states which affect it should have comparable content and this mechanism is based on the influence of expectations on perception.","PeriodicalId":369041,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"133509553","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
The Medium Is the Message? К. Танкреди и Я. Шарвит о семантике высказываний об установках 中间是中间吗?唐克雷蒂和我查维斯关于安装语义
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/eps202360344
Даниил Борисович Тискин
Среди неоднозначностей, наблюдаемых в высказываниях о пропозициональных установках, некоторые связаны с возможностью понять то или иное слово в общепринятом значении или же в идиолекте носителя установки, которую передает высказывание. Хотя этот факт известен уже около двух десятилетий, первой работой, где на этом в известной мере основана вся теория интерпретации высказываний об установках, можно назвать недавнюю статью [Tancredi, Sharvit, 2022]. Значительная гибкость ее формального аппарата обусловлена тем, что выражающее установку придаточное рассматривается как еще не проинтерпретированный языковой объект, так что его интерпретация в высказывании об установке может отличаться от его интерпретации в качестве отдельного высказывания и денотативно (в мирах, совместимых с содержанием установки, у входящих в него выражений могут быть не те же денотаты, что в реальном мире), и сигнификативно (в отношении смыслов, или толкований, этих выражений). Настоящая статья, помимо исторического очерка (§1) и краткого представления идей К. Танкреди и Я. Шарвит (§2), критикует такие аспекты их теории, как отсутствие в ней возможности прямо отсылать к возможным мирам (§3) и нужда в синтаксическом передвижении для предсказания невозможности некоторых интерпретаций (§4). С другой стороны, мы показываем, как подобная теория, разделяющая сигнификативный и денотативный аспекты интерпретации, позволяет развить представление о шкалах, связанных с высказываниями об установках, и, соответственно, о порождаемых ими скалярных импликатурах (§5).
在关于稳定器的发言中所观察到的模棱两可之处中,有一些涉及到能够理解传统意义上的一个词,或应用程序载体的成语。尽管这一事实在20多年前就为人所知,但第一部以这一理论为基础的作品是最近的一篇文章(Tancredi, Sharvit, 2022)。相当灵活性正式机是因为它表达安装同位语被视为语言对象来还没解释,所以他诠释的命题都安装能有别于他作为个别言论和诠释денотативн(世界上兼容的内容设置,进入他的表达可能有不一样денотат在现实世界),сигнификативн(在关系意义或解释,这个表达式)。本文除了历史概要(第1节)和简要介绍c . tancredi和i . charvet(第2节)之外,还批评了他们理论的某些方面,即缺乏直接引用可能的世界(第3节)和预测某些解释不可能(第4节)的句法运动的需要。另一方面,我们展示了这样一种理论,将字母和数字解释区分开来,使我们能够更好地了解与安装相关的量表,从而了解它们产生的量表(5)。
{"title":"The Medium Is the Message? К. Танкреди и Я. Шарвит о семантике высказываний об установках","authors":"Даниил Борисович Тискин","doi":"10.5840/eps202360344","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/eps202360344","url":null,"abstract":"Среди неоднозначностей, наблюдаемых в высказываниях о пропозициональных установках, некоторые связаны с возможностью понять то или иное слово в общепринятом значении или же в идиолекте носителя установки, которую передает высказывание. Хотя этот факт известен уже около двух десятилетий, первой работой, где на этом в известной мере основана вся теория интерпретации высказываний об установках, можно назвать недавнюю статью [Tancredi, Sharvit, 2022]. Значительная гибкость ее формального аппарата обусловлена тем, что выражающее установку придаточное рассматривается как еще не проинтерпретированный языковой объект, так что его интерпретация в высказывании об установке может отличаться от его интерпретации в качестве отдельного высказывания и денотативно (в мирах, совместимых с содержанием установки, у входящих в него выражений могут быть не те же денотаты, что в реальном мире), и сигнификативно (в отношении смыслов, или толкований, этих выражений). Настоящая статья, помимо исторического очерка (§1) и краткого представления идей К. Танкреди и Я. Шарвит (§2), критикует такие аспекты их теории, как отсутствие в ней возможности прямо отсылать к возможным мирам (§3) и нужда в синтаксическом передвижении для предсказания невозможности некоторых интерпретаций (§4). С другой стороны, мы показываем, как подобная теория, разделяющая сигнификативный и денотативный аспекты интерпретации, позволяет развить представление о шкалах, связанных с высказываниями об установках, и, соответственно, о порождаемых ими скалярных импликатурах (§5).","PeriodicalId":369041,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science","volume":"29 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"133191758","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Digital Humanities Projects 数字人文项目
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/eps202360234
E. Chebotareva
The author considers the Digital Humanities as a tendency towards a constructive synthesis of computer technology and humanitarian science in the context of their claim to make a paradigm shift in the humanities. As part of this review, the author raises a question about the role of interactive multimedia tools in the humanities, and tried to evaluate the novelty and content that scientific and educational projects receive with their help. The author develops and justifies the principle of systematization of Digital Humanities projects, based on the priority of distinguishing projects by the nature of the relationship between their humanitarian and computer (technological) components. Considering both the actual digital projects and the academic publications devoted to them in the context of their systematization, the author observes that many projects are largely experimental in nature due to the use of ever new multimedia tools, so it is premature to talk about a meaningful transformation of humanitarian science. Focusing on the issue of a successful synthesis of digital technologies and the humanities, the author notes that new technological tools (multimedia, AI or neural networks, etc) allow raising new questions, updating additional objects of research and creating new methods. However, new tools do not always set the completeness of the new content, only supplementing it, and the acquired interactivity does not always directly work for scientific character. In this case, we face with the reverse situation, when the claims of technologically determined disciplines to be scientific are intertwined with the claims of disciplinary science to manufacturability. As a result, the author concludes that the direction of Digital Humanities is significantly influenced by technoscience with its dissolution of the boundaries between fundamental and applied research and the desire for new technologies that transform the processes under study, which makes McLuhan’s concept especially relevant.
作者认为数字人文学科是计算机技术和人文科学在其声称在人文学科中进行范式转变的背景下的一种建设性综合的趋势。作为回顾的一部分,作者提出了一个关于互动多媒体工具在人文学科中的作用的问题,并试图评估科学和教育项目在它们的帮助下获得的新颖性和内容。作者根据人文学科与计算机(技术)组成部分之间关系的性质区分项目的优先级,提出并论证了数字人文学科项目系统化的原则。考虑到实际的数字项目和在其系统化背景下致力于它们的学术出版物,作者注意到,由于使用了新的多媒体工具,许多项目在本质上很大程度上是实验性的,因此谈论人道主义科学的有意义的转变还为时过早。作者将重点放在数字技术与人文科学成功结合的问题上,指出新的技术工具(多媒体、人工智能或神经网络等)可以提出新的问题,更新额外的研究对象并创造新的方法。然而,新工具并不总是设置新内容的完整性,只是补充它,并且获得的交互性并不总是直接对科学性质起作用。在这种情况下,我们面临着相反的情况,当技术决定的学科是科学的主张与学科科学的可制造性的主张交织在一起。因此,作者得出结论,数字人文学科的方向受到技术科学的显著影响,它消解了基础研究和应用研究之间的界限,并渴望新技术改变所研究的过程,这使得麦克卢汉的概念特别相关。
{"title":"Digital Humanities Projects","authors":"E. Chebotareva","doi":"10.5840/eps202360234","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/eps202360234","url":null,"abstract":"The author considers the Digital Humanities as a tendency towards a constructive synthesis of computer technology and humanitarian science in the context of their claim to make a paradigm shift in the humanities. As part of this review, the author raises a question about the role of interactive multimedia tools in the humanities, and tried to evaluate the novelty and content that scientific and educational projects receive with their help. The author develops and justifies the principle of systematization of Digital Humanities projects, based on the priority of distinguishing projects by the nature of the relationship between their humanitarian and computer (technological) components. Considering both the actual digital projects and the academic publications devoted to them in the context of their systematization, the author observes that many projects are largely experimental in nature due to the use of ever new multimedia tools, so it is premature to talk about a meaningful transformation of humanitarian science. Focusing on the issue of a successful synthesis of digital technologies and the humanities, the author notes that new technological tools (multimedia, AI or neural networks, etc) allow raising new questions, updating additional objects of research and creating new methods. However, new tools do not always set the completeness of the new content, only supplementing it, and the acquired interactivity does not always directly work for scientific character. In this case, we face with the reverse situation, when the claims of technologically determined disciplines to be scientific are intertwined with the claims of disciplinary science to manufacturability. As a result, the author concludes that the direction of Digital Humanities is significantly influenced by technoscience with its dissolution of the boundaries between fundamental and applied research and the desire for new technologies that transform the processes under study, which makes McLuhan’s concept especially relevant.","PeriodicalId":369041,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science","volume":"2 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"133838990","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Creativity in Science as a Social Phenomenon 科学中的创造力是一种社会现象
Pub Date : 1900-01-01 DOI: 10.5840/eps202259336
I. Kasavin
The philosophical understanding of scientific creativity cannot be limited to the analysis of cognitive abilities or ways of solving problems. It is always anthropologically-laden, based on a historically specific image image of a human being that acquires knowledge. The problem of creativity also articulates a well-known paradox of novelty: the new does not arise from the old, since it is significantly different from it, but it cannot arise from nothing, because then it remains incomprehensible. Paul Feyerabend criticizes such a “mysterianic” concept of scientific creativity, which emphasizes its emergent character, i.e. its suddenness and inexplicability. The distance between subject and object, man and nature, knowledge and reality in this case remains insurmountable. To solve this problem, it is necessary to place creativity in the space between the uniqueness of the creative personality and the mechanisms of social recognition. This, in turn, requires rethinking of the ontological content of creativity, as well as the concept of “labor” with reference to its treatment by Karl Marx’ rethinking of it as the production of not only material goods, but also of the person itself. Moreover, creativity does not just form a person: it is a way of cultivating the entire social space. An unexpected move is provided by an appeal to a new social group – the precariat, which in science gives a lesson in openness to novelty and theoretical freedom. As a result, a deeper understanding of the social base of creativity arises, and a new strategy for the interaction of the scientific community with extra-paradigm groups and marginal individuals is being built.
对科学创造力的哲学理解不能局限于对认知能力或解决问题的方法的分析。它总是人类学的,基于历史上特定的形象,一个人获取知识的形象。创造力的问题也阐明了一个众所周知的新奇悖论:新事物不是从旧事物中产生的,因为它与旧事物有很大的不同,但新事物也不能凭空产生,因为那样的话,它仍然是不可理解的。保罗·费耶阿本德批评了这种“神秘”的科学创造力概念,强调它的突发性和不可解释性。在这种情况下,主体与客体、人与自然、知识与现实之间的距离仍然是不可逾越的。要解决这一问题,必须将创造力置于创造性人格的独特性与社会认同机制之间的空间中。反过来,这需要重新思考创造力的本体论内容,以及“劳动”的概念,参考卡尔·马克思对它的重新思考,它不仅是物质产品的生产,而且是人本身的生产。此外,创造力不只是塑造一个人,它是培育整个社会空间的一种方式。一个意想不到的举动是对一个新的社会群体的呼吁——无产者,这在科学上给了一个对新奇事物和理论自由开放的教训。因此,对创造力的社会基础有了更深入的了解,科学界与超范式群体和边缘个人的互动的新策略正在建立。
{"title":"Creativity in Science as a Social Phenomenon","authors":"I. Kasavin","doi":"10.5840/eps202259336","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.5840/eps202259336","url":null,"abstract":"The philosophical understanding of scientific creativity cannot be limited to the analysis of cognitive abilities or ways of solving problems. It is always anthropologically-laden, based on a historically specific image image of a human being that acquires knowledge. The problem of creativity also articulates a well-known paradox of novelty: the new does not arise from the old, since it is significantly different from it, but it cannot arise from nothing, because then it remains incomprehensible. Paul Feyerabend criticizes such a “mysterianic” concept of scientific creativity, which emphasizes its emergent character, i.e. its suddenness and inexplicability. The distance between subject and object, man and nature, knowledge and reality in this case remains insurmountable. To solve this problem, it is necessary to place creativity in the space between the uniqueness of the creative personality and the mechanisms of social recognition. This, in turn, requires rethinking of the ontological content of creativity, as well as the concept of “labor” with reference to its treatment by Karl Marx’ rethinking of it as the production of not only material goods, but also of the person itself. Moreover, creativity does not just form a person: it is a way of cultivating the entire social space. An unexpected move is provided by an appeal to a new social group – the precariat, which in science gives a lesson in openness to novelty and theoretical freedom. As a result, a deeper understanding of the social base of creativity arises, and a new strategy for the interaction of the scientific community with extra-paradigm groups and marginal individuals is being built.","PeriodicalId":369041,"journal":{"name":"Epistemology & Philosophy of Science","volume":"402 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"114932447","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
期刊
Epistemology & Philosophy of Science
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1