首页 > 最新文献

IPPR Progressive Review最新文献

英文 中文
Working for the future 为未来而努力
Q4 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2023-11-07 DOI: 10.1111/newe.12358
Tony Wilson
{"title":"Working for the future","authors":"Tony Wilson","doi":"10.1111/newe.12358","DOIUrl":"10.1111/newe.12358","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":37420,"journal":{"name":"IPPR Progressive Review","volume":"30 3","pages":"233-238"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135539927","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Don't forget demand 不要忘记需求
Q4 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2023-11-07 DOI: 10.1111/newe.12356
Craig Berry
{"title":"Don't forget demand","authors":"Craig Berry","doi":"10.1111/newe.12356","DOIUrl":"10.1111/newe.12356","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":37420,"journal":{"name":"IPPR Progressive Review","volume":"30 3","pages":"221-227"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-11-07","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"135539489","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Building on broad support for better social security 建立对改善社会保障的广泛支持
Q4 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2023-08-30 DOI: 10.1111/newe.12346
Daniel Edmiston, Kate Summers, Ben Baumberg Geiger, Robert de Vries, Lisa Scullion, David Young, Jo Ingold

In this article, we present new evidence of broad public support for higher benefit levels in the UK, in line with a more generous Minimum Income Standard. Benchmarking entitlements against a publicly agreed Minimum Income Standard could build on this support and better engage with questions of human need in our social security system. Provision of this would contribute towards a so-called ‘civic minimum’ that serves as a transformative basis on which to redefine the social contract between citizens, the state and markets.2

Beyond the current cost-of-living crisis, welfare reforms and austerity measures introduced since 2010 mean the real terms value of non-pensioner benefits has fallen considerably. For example, the value of Child Benefit has fallen by more than a fifth (-22.7 per cent) since 2010 and Universal Credit has fallen by 15.5 per cent in value since its introduction in 2013 (See Figure 1).5 As the value of benefits has fallen, reliance on crisis support and charitable food aid has risen sharply, with food bank use being strongly linked to problems with or inadequacy of social security payments.6

As the value of benefits has fallen, the risk and depth of poverty has increased considerably.7 Progress made towards reducing child poverty has stalled significantly, and children, larger families and black and minority ethnic communities are more likely to be in deeper forms of poverty than they were a decade ago.8 In response, there have been growing concerns about the adequacy of social security payments and their capacity to mitigate against the causes and consequences of poverty.9

Proponents of a social contract rooted in ‘fair reciprocity’ argue that the “institutions governing economic life” have a duty to provide a “sufficiently generous share of the social product” to all citizens.12 They argue that if a set of “core commitments” is not fulfilled, those disadvantaged have a “proportionately reduced obligation” to perform the duties prescribed by the state.13 Such an argument reframes debates about the permissiveness of welfare, to refocus attention on the duties of economic citizenship held by the government and the legitimacy of welfare contractualism when adequate protection is missing.

What the public think benefit payments are is one question. What they think they should be is another. Historically, low benefit levels have often been politically justified as necessary to discourage ‘welfare dependency’ and encourage people to work. These sorts of arguments respond to and reinforce hackneyed caricatures of ‘skivers’ and ‘strivers’ and are often assumed to reflect the intuitions of the wider public.21 However, the level at which benefits are set or should be is often left ambiguous and rarely specified in public debates and discussion. When asked about the specific level at which benefits should be set, the majority of the survey respondents supported more generous payments. Specifica

在这篇文章中,我们提出了新的证据,证明英国公众广泛支持更高的福利水平,符合更慷慨的最低收入标准。根据公众认可的最低收入标准对福利进行基准测试,可以在这种支持的基础上,更好地解决我们社会保障体系中人类需求的问题。这一规定将有助于实现所谓的“公民最低限度”,作为重新定义公民、国家和市场之间社会契约的变革基础。除了当前的生活成本危机之外,自2010年以来引入的福利改革和紧缩措施意味着,非养老金领取者福利的实际价值大幅下降。例如,自2010年以来,儿童福利(Child Benefit)的价值下降了逾五分之一(- 22.7%),而通用信贷(Universal Credit)自2013年推出以来,价值下降了15.5%(见图1)随着福利价值的下降,对危机支持和慈善食品援助的依赖急剧上升,食品银行的使用与社会保障支付的问题或不足密切相关。随着福利价值的下降,贫困的风险和深度大大增加了在减少儿童贫困方面取得的进展已明显停滞,儿童、大家庭以及黑人和少数民族社区比十年前更有可能陷入更深形式的贫困因此,人们越来越关注社会保障的支付是否足够,以及它们是否有能力减轻贫穷的原因和后果。基于“公平互惠”的社会契约的支持者认为,“管理经济生活的机构”有责任向所有公民提供“足够慷慨的社会产品份额”他们认为,如果一套“核心承诺”没有得到履行,那些处于不利地位的人履行国家规定的职责的“义务就会相应减少”这样的观点重新定义了关于福利放任性的辩论,重新将注意力集中在政府所承担的经济公民义务上,以及在缺乏充分保护的情况下福利契约主义的合法性。公众对福利金的看法是一个问题。他们认为自己应该成为的是另一回事。从历史上看,低福利水平经常被认为是政治上合理的,因为它是劝阻“福利依赖”和鼓励人们工作的必要条件。这类论点回应并强化了对“逃工”和“奋斗者”的陈腐讽刺,通常被认为反映了广大公众的直觉但是,在公开辩论和讨论中,确定或应该确定的福利水平往往含糊不清,很少具体说明。当被问及福利应该设定的具体水平时,大多数受访者支持更慷慨的支付。具体来说,大多数英国人认为领取救济金的人应该至少能负担得起“他们真正需要的一切”(如果不一定是社会上大多数人认为理所当然的一切),也就是说,救济金应该符合最低收入标准。公众对更慷慨和更广泛的社会保障制度的支持根据所认识的情况和索赔人的特点而有很大的不同。例如,73%的英国公众认为,在工作中的索赔者至少应该获得能够负担得起“他们真正需要的一切”(即营养丰富的饮食、安全干燥的住宿、水电费、衣服、儿童保育和交通费用)的支付水平。对无法工作的残疾索赔人的支持大致相同(72%)。然而,对于失业的单身父母来说,这一比例降至65%,对于没有孩子的单身失业人士来说,这一比例降至56%。然而,这意味着,即使是最不受支持的群体(没有孩子的失业单身人士),大多数人也支持福利应该涵盖所有必需品的想法。在支持最慷慨的社会参与标准(使人们能够负担得起必需品和大多数人认为理所当然的东西的福利)方面,态度再次因索赔人的类型而异。英国公众最有可能支持这一标准的是无法工作的残疾人(42%),其次是在职索赔者(33%),失业单亲(22%),最后是没有孩子的失业单身人士(16%)。还值得注意的是,领取福利者本身的态度和政策偏好大体上反映了一般公众的态度和政策偏好。 虽然福利申领人更倾向于支持更高水平的社会保障权利,但似乎他们在不同申领群体的假定需求、环境和“应得性”之间划出了类似的区别。例如,对社会参与标准的支持在无法工作的残疾人中是最高的,有46%的福利申领人支持这一标准,而在没有孩子的失业单身人士中是最低的,只有23%的福利申领人支持这一标准(见图3)。22在此基础上,需要进一步的工作来提高公众对社会保障体系变化的理解,这些变化随着时间的推移已经破坏了福利的充足性和覆盖面。特别是,需要进一步的证据和战略沟通,以说明冻结福利、等待五周领取普遍津贴、扣减福利、二子女限制和福利上限的破坏性影响,所有这些都使低收入领取者陷入更严重的财政困难这包括挑战公众对索赔人情况和特征的看法——例如,通过强调许多领取社会保障的低收入家庭已经在工作或正在(重返)工作的路上。虽然这不是实现这一目标的唯一机制,但低保等例子为我们如何重新思考福利充足性问题提供了经验。目前,在英国,社会保障的支付没有考虑到它们在多大程度上减轻了贫困或促进了社会包容。尽管相当多的公众支持更慷慨的福利制度。为了确保这转化为一个更有意义和进步的社会保障政策议程,我们需要确保围绕福利的政治辩论和政策讨论与客观生活水平紧密联系在一起。我们知道,在英国社会保障体系中,普遍支持更慷慨的最低收入标准。因此,我们需要以此为基准来衡量福利权利,并在此基础上评估福利的表现。如果没有这个明确的参考点,政策讨论将永远偏离“这些钱够生活吗?”这个核心问题。由于没有认真对待这个问题并提供“公民最低限度”,26我们不仅使社会保障在保护人们免受更深形式的贫困方面无效,而且还破坏了英国公民与国家之间当前社会契约的效力。
{"title":"Building on broad support for better social security","authors":"Daniel Edmiston,&nbsp;Kate Summers,&nbsp;Ben Baumberg Geiger,&nbsp;Robert de Vries,&nbsp;Lisa Scullion,&nbsp;David Young,&nbsp;Jo Ingold","doi":"10.1111/newe.12346","DOIUrl":"10.1111/newe.12346","url":null,"abstract":"<p>In this article, we present new evidence of broad public support for higher benefit levels in the UK, in line with a more generous Minimum Income Standard. Benchmarking entitlements against a publicly agreed Minimum Income Standard could build on this support and better engage with questions of human need in our social security system. Provision of this would contribute towards a so-called ‘civic minimum’ that serves as a transformative basis on which to redefine the social contract between citizens, the state and markets.2</p><p>Beyond the current cost-of-living crisis, welfare reforms and austerity measures introduced since 2010 mean the real terms value of non-pensioner benefits has fallen considerably. For example, the value of Child Benefit has fallen by more than a fifth (-22.7 per cent) since 2010 and Universal Credit has fallen by 15.5 per cent in value since its introduction in 2013 (See Figure 1).5 As the value of benefits has fallen, reliance on crisis support and charitable food aid has risen sharply, with food bank use being strongly linked to problems with or inadequacy of social security payments.6</p><p>As the value of benefits has fallen, the risk and depth of poverty has increased considerably.7 Progress made towards reducing child poverty has stalled significantly, and children, larger families and black and minority ethnic communities are more likely to be in deeper forms of poverty than they were a decade ago.8 In response, there have been growing concerns about the adequacy of social security payments and their capacity to mitigate against the causes and consequences of poverty.9</p><p>Proponents of a social contract rooted in ‘fair reciprocity’ argue that the “institutions governing economic life” have a duty to provide a “sufficiently generous share of the social product” to all citizens.12 They argue that if a set of “core commitments” is not fulfilled, those disadvantaged have a “proportionately reduced obligation” to perform the duties prescribed by the state.13 Such an argument reframes debates about the permissiveness of welfare, to refocus attention on the duties of economic citizenship held by the government and the legitimacy of welfare contractualism when adequate protection is missing.</p><p>What the public think benefit payments <i>are</i> is one question. What they think they <i>should be</i> is another. Historically, low benefit levels have often been politically justified as necessary to discourage ‘welfare dependency’ and encourage people to work. These sorts of arguments respond to and reinforce hackneyed caricatures of ‘skivers’ and ‘strivers’ and are often assumed to reflect the intuitions of the wider public.21 However, the level at which benefits are set or should be is often left ambiguous and rarely specified in public debates and discussion. When asked about the specific level at which benefits <i>should</i> be set, the majority of the survey respondents supported more generous payments. Specifica","PeriodicalId":37420,"journal":{"name":"IPPR Progressive Review","volume":"30 2","pages":"84-91"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-08-30","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/newe.12346","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44444010","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Labour's search for credibility 工党寻求信誉
Q4 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2023-08-29 DOI: 10.1111/newe.12347
Mark Blyth
{"title":"Labour's search for credibility","authors":"Mark Blyth","doi":"10.1111/newe.12347","DOIUrl":"10.1111/newe.12347","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":37420,"journal":{"name":"IPPR Progressive Review","volume":"30 2","pages":"139-144"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-08-29","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49329584","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
An NHS fit for the 21st century 适合21世纪的NHS
Q4 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2023-08-21 DOI: 10.1111/newe.12353
Chris Thomas
{"title":"An NHS fit for the 21st century","authors":"Chris Thomas","doi":"10.1111/newe.12353","DOIUrl":"10.1111/newe.12353","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":37420,"journal":{"name":"IPPR Progressive Review","volume":"30 2","pages":"106-114"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-08-21","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44576824","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Justice and feasibility 公正与可行性
Q4 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2023-08-10 DOI: 10.1111/newe.12354
Louise Haagh

Analysis of basic income – a cash grant paid individually, monthly, unconditionally and universally in a population, and permanently – has been shaped by concerns about the grounds for and the implementation of the scheme that inevitably come up against each other in practical terms. This paper accordingly first examines the present constrained context, then champions a developmental justice case for basic income against distributive alternatives, and finally highlights risks in implementation debates linked with bending to prevailing welfare norms and crises.

However, while The Economist got it right when arguing that public ‘customers’ get less for more cost, and that in Britain, following austerity, “[o]nce-generous legal aid became miserly; in-work benefits fell; [and the] police solved fewer crimes”, rather than emphasising distributive and tax trade-offs between generations (see the ‘Feasibility’ section below), I will argue that deeper issues are at stake, linked with choice of development governance based on following the market.3 ‘Shrinkflation’ – paying (and, we might add, working) more for less – has become embedded in the workings of contemporary private and public economies. Meanwhile, global corporates hiking up inflation on the back of war and global shortages are listing huge windfalls.4 The government response in the form of windfall taxes has been too accommodating (in the UK, 90 per cent are effectively returned via subsidies), and neither this measure nor government schemes for households have been made permanent.5 The problem of establishing grounds and measures for government to subsidise household budgets encapsulates a dissonance between ideal and reality that pertains to the case for basic income as well. We need not only a new social contract, but also a new social construct, in which concerns of justice inform the design of institutions and the economy follows.

When questions about the justification for and feasibility of basic income are set together, this can generate productive insights about wider reasons and conditions for basic income, which test more theoretical arguments. In this paper, rather than looking at principled arguments in terms of fairer distribution, I focus on the institutional and democratic innovation within the political economy that a basic income can contribute by inculcating the idea and form of developmental justice.

The modern classical defence of basic income by Philippe Van Parijs focusses on the scope for free lifestyle choices involving personally set trade-offs between employment, care and leisure in a globalised economy, in which basic income as a form of distributive justice secures freedom.6 While debates have begun to shift towards anti-poverty, health, personal development, and choice of work, the notion that – with basic income – individuals can attain control over their lives and wellbeing remains quite influential.7 However, looking at freedom or well

对基本收入- -个别、每月、无条件和在人口中普遍和永久地支付的现金补助金- -的分析一直受到对该计划的理由和执行的关切的影响,这些关切在实际情况中不可避免地相互矛盾。因此,本文首先考察了当前的约束背景,然后支持基本收入与分配替代方案的发展正义案例,最后强调了与屈服于现行福利规范和危机相关的实施辩论中的风险。然而,尽管《经济学人》认为公共‘客户’付出更多却得到更少,而且在英国,在紧缩政策之后,“原本慷慨的法律援助变得吝啬;在职福利下降;(和)警察解决的犯罪更少”,而不是强调代际之间的分配和税收权衡(见下面的“可行性”部分),我将认为更深层次的问题是利害攸关的,与选择基于跟随市场的发展治理有关。“缩水式通货膨胀”——以更少的钱支付更多的钱(我们可以补充说,工作更多)——已经深入到当代私营和公共经济的运作中。与此同时,在战争和全球物资短缺的背景下,全球企业推高了通胀,列出了巨额意外之财政府以暴利税的形式做出的回应过于宽松(在英国,90%的暴利税实际上是通过补贴返还的),而且这一措施和政府针对家庭的计划都没有长久化为政府补贴家庭预算建立理由和措施的问题,体现了理想与现实之间的不协调,这也适用于基本收入的情况。我们不仅需要一种新的社会契约,而且需要一种新的社会结构,在这种社会结构中,对正义的关注影响着制度的设计和经济的发展。当有关基本收入的合理性和可行性的问题被放在一起时,这可以产生关于基本收入的更广泛的原因和条件的富有成效的见解,从而检验更多的理论论点。在本文中,我并没有着眼于更公平分配方面的原则性论点,而是将重点放在政治经济学中的制度和民主创新上,即基本收入可以通过灌输发展正义的理念和形式来做出贡献。菲利普·范·帕里斯(Philippe Van Parijs)对基本收入的现代经典辩护侧重于自由生活方式选择的范围,包括在全球化经济中个人设定就业、护理和休闲之间的权衡,在这种情况下,基本收入作为一种分配正义的形式确保了自由虽然辩论已经开始转向反贫困、健康、个人发展和工作选择,但有了基本收入,个人可以控制自己的生活和幸福的观念仍然相当有影响力然而,从个人时间分布和活动选择的角度来看待自由或幸福可能过于交易化——我们越采用这种方法,已经支配我们生活的市场就越占主导地位。退休的权利超越了我们目前对退休的概念,它被定义为在任何年龄都能生活得很好,并有权控制我们的节奏——我们自己的节奏,以及与他人的节奏。这项权利为一个更稳定的公共服务部门带来了希望,也是工会自成立以来一直为之奋斗的东西。实验研究还表明,这种形式的控制允许更深入的思考,增强人的动机和功能获得或改变稳定职业和控制时间的能力符合战后英国提出的从未真正实现的平等观念,与t.h.马歇尔在优质服务和优质生活方式方面的公民观念有关,所有人都能“像绅士一样生活”如今,利害攸关的不仅是工作时间,还有工作量,以及抵御人际竞争的侵蚀力量。原则上,基本收入是一种防止这种形式的结构性不公正的制度。(我认为)创造结构正义所要求的是不够的。然而,通过将人们部分地从结构性不公正中解救出来,基本收入——在其他制度中被恰当地理解为一种稳定的制度——向结构性公正发出了一个“沙漠”的信号,并引导我们走上一条定义这是什么以及在其他制度中需要什么的道路。在马歇尔,“像绅士一样生活”被职业“第二次机会”的理念所补充。当然,他想到的是后来从英国分层教育体系的早期恶果中逃脱出来。这个概念更广泛。真正的职业机会(以及第二次机会)必须是结构正义所要求的一部分:在一个组织更完善的经济体中,人类不能被迫离开家园,也不能被迫从事自己选择的生产性生活旅程。 从这个意义上说,基本收入作为一种稳定制度的想法是设想结构性正义的一部分,但它本身并不是整个道路。基本收入作为人类发展稳定状态设想的一部分,使我们能够从个人的角度向上看结构正义需要什么。还有许多其他的例子说明目前的机构是如何低效地花钱的16 .不稳定的合同对公共费用的影响可以从护理部门得到说明,该部门长期受到工作人员短缺的困扰,这反过来又推高了公共保健费用监管不力的代价也很高。一个恰当的例子是,在20世纪80年代住房政策自由化之后的一段时间里,住房补贴在英国发挥了非常重要的作用并不断扩大当代福利制度的结构性不公正延伸到了那些现在工作和挣钱的人身上。当人们不得不花费辛苦挣来的积蓄来满足他们的需求,直到他们完全破产,他们才能获得收入支持(以及制裁的威胁),这种情况也是对发展正义的一种冒犯基本收入的关键是不受两次惩罚的权利,即不受不幸的惩罚和不受不幸的惩罚,不幸会把暂时的坏运气变成永久的状态。如上所述,为基本收入辩护的正确理由不是它将收入重新分配给贫困人口,而是它恢复了公民的基本独立性,并减弱了目前造成发展不公正的结构性力量。最近在世界范围内对部分基本收入的实验和对经济安全来源的其他研究毫无疑问地表明了经济稳定的激励作用然而,基本安全的激励作用从来都是毋庸置疑的:它怎么可能违背公认的观点,即企业精神受益于有限的责任和稳定的税收?这场辩论需要进一步深入,准确地考虑政治经济、共享资金和权利之间的关系。在同样的背景下,将基本收入纯粹浪漫化为一种反贫困工具(更不用说一种充分的工具了)的风险在于,它可能成为倡导加强全球一体化的国际发展资助者的一种简单解决方案。在某种程度上,这已经成为现实,因为国际货币基金组织(IMF)最近提议通过简化福利制度来削减印度政府的开支,同时认为对失业人员的制裁应该在富裕国家继续实施,因为这些国家有行政能力来监管贫困人口。根据马丁·沃尔夫(Martin Wolf)的说法,在最近的一个土地税案例中,大大小小的土地所有者几乎没有或根本没有为他们的土地创造价值,作为征税的理由然而,我们能平等地说,所有的土地所有者都不配拥有他们的土地(或建筑)吗?另一方面,沃尔夫也提出了对土地征税的理由,因为它(比对流动资本征税)更容易做到。
{"title":"Justice and feasibility","authors":"Louise Haagh","doi":"10.1111/newe.12354","DOIUrl":"10.1111/newe.12354","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Analysis of basic income – a cash grant paid individually, monthly, unconditionally and universally in a population, and permanently – has been shaped by concerns about the grounds for and the implementation of the scheme that inevitably come up against each other in practical terms. This paper accordingly first examines the present constrained context, then champions a developmental justice case for basic income against distributive alternatives, and finally highlights risks in implementation debates linked with bending to prevailing welfare norms and crises.</p><p>However, while <i>The Economist</i> got it right when arguing that public ‘customers’ get less for more cost, and that in Britain, following austerity, “[o]nce-generous legal aid became miserly; in-work benefits fell; [and the] police solved fewer crimes”, rather than emphasising distributive and tax trade-offs between generations (see the ‘Feasibility’ section below), I will argue that deeper issues are at stake, linked with choice of development governance based on following the market.3 ‘Shrinkflation’ – paying (and, we might add, working) more for less – has become embedded in the workings of contemporary private and public economies. Meanwhile, global corporates hiking up inflation on the back of war and global shortages are listing huge windfalls.4 The government response in the form of windfall taxes has been too accommodating (in the UK, 90 per cent are effectively returned via subsidies), and neither this measure nor government schemes for households have been made permanent.5 The problem of establishing grounds and measures for government to subsidise household budgets encapsulates a dissonance between ideal and reality that pertains to the case for basic income as well. We need not only a new social contract, but also a new social construct, in which concerns of justice inform the design of institutions and the economy follows.</p><p>When questions about the justification for and feasibility of basic income are set together, this can generate productive insights about wider reasons and conditions for basic income, which test more theoretical arguments. In this paper, rather than looking at principled arguments in terms of fairer distribution, I focus on the institutional and democratic innovation within the political economy that a basic income can contribute by inculcating the idea and form of developmental justice.</p><p>The modern classical defence of basic income by Philippe Van Parijs focusses on the scope for free lifestyle choices involving personally set trade-offs between employment, care and leisure in a globalised economy, in which basic income as a form of distributive justice secures freedom.6 While debates have begun to shift towards anti-poverty, health, personal development, and choice of work, the notion that – with basic income – individuals can attain control over their lives and wellbeing remains quite influential.7 However, looking at freedom or well","PeriodicalId":37420,"journal":{"name":"IPPR Progressive Review","volume":"30 2","pages":"92-99"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-08-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/newe.12354","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46710830","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Reconsidering work 重新考虑工作
Q4 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2023-08-10 DOI: 10.1111/newe.12351
Heejung Chung

Work in the UK is broken. We work too hard, too long, are not getting paid enough and are not productive enough.1 What is more, our labour market is largely exclusionary. The work devotion we are asked to show is not compatible with other life commitments, resulting in the exclusion of large pockets of society. It also requires untenable levels of work commitment and overwork, especially from those whose work capacities are already questioned – namely, marginalised workers such as minority ethnic workers. The current way of thinking about work is not helping us as workers, us as a society and also our climate. It doesn't even make economic sense as it doesn't make the most of human contributions, especially considering the challenges we face in the future of work.

One of the main problems with work culture is that of the ‘ideal worker’,2 namely, that you need to prioritise work above all else in your life, work very long hours to show dedication and commitment to work and be productive. “Nobody ever changed the world on 40 hours a week”, to quote Elon Musk.3 The chief executive of Goldman Sachs expects his junior analysts to work 100 hours a week to provide value for their clients.4 Alongside the rise of digital technology, and ironically with the rise of flexible working, workers are expected to work all the time and everywhere. You have to be “always on”,5 to the point where it feels like your work now has the prerogative to demand all your waking hours and possibly your unconscious hours when we consider how much we think about work.

Not only is working such long hours detrimental to workers’ and their families’ wellbeing – for example, by not allowing parents to spend time with their family – it also largely excludes workers with any responsibilities outside of work. This includes caring for children, family or friends and self-care – namely, anyone with a disability or long-term illness, and those with responsibilities to their community, friends, pets or any other aspect of life that can collide with the long-hours work culture. Any indication that you may have responsibilities outside of work is likely to result in doubt of your work commitment and productivity, regardless of what you actually produce.6 This long-hours working can be especially detrimental for marginalised workers whose work capacity is already questioned – such as mothers, disabled people, minority ethnic workers and LGBT+ workers – as many already overwork and go above and beyond to prove their worth. In the UK, 88 per cent of workers experienced burnout recently, costing the UK £28 billion yearly,7 with burnout and other mental health problems being especially high for marginalised workers. What is worse, we are not burning out to enhance the world or bring forth a new future for humanity. Two out of five Britons feel that their work is not making any meaningful contribution to the world8 and 69 per cent report that they are burning out precisely because

英国的工作是支离破碎的。我们工作太辛苦,时间太长,却得不到足够的报酬,效率也不够高更重要的是,我们的劳动力市场在很大程度上是排外的。我们被要求表现出的工作奉献精神与其他生活承诺是不相容的,导致社会上的大部分人被排斥在外。它还需要无法维持的工作承诺和过度工作,特别是那些工作能力已经受到质疑的人-即少数民族工人等边缘化工人。目前对工作的思考方式无助于我们作为工人,我们作为一个社会,也无助于我们的气候。它甚至没有经济意义,因为它没有充分利用人类的贡献,特别是考虑到我们在未来工作中面临的挑战。工作文化的一个主要问题是“理想员工”,也就是说,你需要把工作放在生活中的其他一切之上,工作很长时间来表现出对工作的奉献和承诺,并提高工作效率。“没有人能靠每周工作40小时来改变世界,”埃隆·马斯克(Elon musk)说。高盛(Goldman Sachs)首席执行官希望他的初级分析师每周工作100小时,为客户提供价值随着数字技术的兴起,具有讽刺意味的是,随着弹性工作制的兴起,工人们被期望随时随地工作。你必须“时刻处于工作状态”,以至于现在你觉得你的工作占据了你醒着的所有时间,当我们考虑到我们对工作有多少想法时,可能还会占用你的无意识时间。如此长时间的工作不仅对员工及其家人的健康有害——例如,不允许父母与家人共度时光——而且在很大程度上也将那些在工作之外负有任何责任的员工排除在外。这包括照顾孩子、家人或朋友,以及自我照顾——也就是说,任何有残疾或长期患病的人,以及那些对社区、朋友、宠物或任何其他可能与长时间工作文化相冲突的生活方面负有责任的人。任何暗示你在工作之外可能有责任的迹象都可能导致对你的工作承诺和效率的怀疑,不管你实际生产了什么这种长时间的工作对那些工作能力已经受到质疑的边缘化工人——比如母亲、残疾人、少数民族工人和LGBT+工人——尤其有害,因为许多人已经超负荷工作,并且为了证明自己的价值而付出了更多。在英国,88%的员工最近经历了职业倦怠,每年给英国造成280亿英镑的损失,7边缘化员工的职业倦怠和其他心理健康问题尤其严重。更糟糕的是,我们并没有竭尽全力改善世界,也没有为人类创造新的未来。五分之二的英国人认为他们的工作没有对世界做出任何有意义的贡献,69%的人表示,他们感到精疲力竭正是因为他们的工作缺乏任何真正的目的。与此同时,我们的许多无意义的工作实际上正在加速全球气候危机,以及我们作为一个社会不得不间接承担的其他社会成本。尽管存在这些问题,但在家办公改变的是对生产力的观念。也就是说,如果你信任员工,并允许他们在工作上有更多的自主权,他们可能会更有效率。在家办公也在一定程度上改变了人们对员工的观念,让他们在工作之外有了身份和责任——尤其是在在线电话会议期间,我们可以看到员工在办公室以外的地方,在他们的家里。另一个有趣的新发展是四天工作制越来越受欢迎。这一运动建议将全职标准改为每周四天32小时。该公司认为,员工的长时间工作在很大程度上可能是表现性的,14这意味着,长时间工作是为了向同事和经理等其他人展示他们的敬业精神和生产力,而不是真正为公司提供价值。通过提供更多的休息时间,更短的工作周可以让工人在工作时间更好地集中精力,提高他们的工作效率,并使公司节省成本。四天工作制还消除了任何多余的工作——比如不必要的会议和文书工作——这些工作是从团队积累的专业知识和知识中提取出来的,而不是减少由经理单独决定的工作任务。然而,即使在低工资部门,投资最终也会在公司一级获得回报,因为工作保留和招聘得到改善,缺勤和疾病减少;在社会一级,通过让更多的就业人员纳税,减少健康问题和倦怠的成本,并为家庭带来福利。 考虑到这一点,卫生和社会保健等部门可以从更多的国家干预中受益,以激励那些因工作条件差和倦怠而离开该部门的工人随着新制度的引入而回来。最后,尽管四天工作周是为了保护工人的时间权,并通过认识到工人花时间从事有偿工作之外的工作的必要性,在社会层面重新调整劳动价值,但这可能还不够。因此,下一节概述了我们在考虑新的社会工作契约时需要考虑的其他问题。首先,我们需要重新考虑我们看重的工作类型。劳动产生的货币价值并不能代表投入劳动的真正价值,也不能代表劳动所获得的利益。例如,社会关怀和儿童保育是非常有价值的工作,它可以为接受照顾的人提供福祉,也可以为该人的亲人提供内心的平静;然而,它通常得到的报酬很少。这是在全球护理危机——即世界各地护理工作者短缺的情况下取得的。护理工作的价值在货币方面被如此低估,因为它是由社会规范观点塑造的-主要是妇女的无偿护理工作。历史上,护理工作主要由女性免费完成。在这个父权社会中,护理工作被视为女性的劳动,不需要得到报酬,因为妇女不被视为家庭的(主要)养家糊口者。19 .在货币价值和社会成本方面,同样的逻辑也可用于其他类型的工作,例如,环境友好型工作可能不会产生很大的利润空间,在货币价值方面可能花费更多,但在减少环境成本和社会成本方面可能非常有益。鉴于我们所处的位置以及我们在工作方面面临的全球性挑战,我们需要从根本上重新考虑我们的社会契约和工作观念。工作应该是社会成员发展世界的一项权利。此外,我们需要重新评估工作,不仅要关注它的货币价值,还要研究它在福利方面创造的社会价值,以及它如何降低潜在的社会成本,特别是在平等、凝聚力和可持续性方面。从这个意义上说,我们需要根除基于长时间工作的理想工作者规范。这并不会阻碍价值创造,而是使我们能够更好地利用人力,从而为社会带来真正的进步和价值。当我们考虑到对更广泛社会的长期影响时,这在货币方面也有意义。工作目前是中断的,但我们可以做得更好。
{"title":"Reconsidering work","authors":"Heejung Chung","doi":"10.1111/newe.12351","DOIUrl":"10.1111/newe.12351","url":null,"abstract":"<p>Work in the UK is broken. We work too hard, too long, are not getting paid enough and are not productive enough.1 What is more, our labour market is largely exclusionary. The work devotion we are asked to show is not compatible with other life commitments, resulting in the exclusion of large pockets of society. It also requires untenable levels of work commitment and overwork, especially from those whose work capacities are already questioned – namely, marginalised workers such as minority ethnic workers. The current way of thinking about work is not helping us as workers, us as a society and also our climate. It doesn't even make economic sense as it doesn't make the most of human contributions, especially considering the challenges we face in the future of work.</p><p>One of the main problems with work culture is that of the ‘ideal worker’,2 namely, that you need to prioritise work above all else in your life, work very long hours to show dedication and commitment to work and be productive. “Nobody ever changed the world on 40 hours a week”, to quote Elon Musk.3 The chief executive of Goldman Sachs expects his junior analysts to work 100 hours a week to provide value for their clients.4 Alongside the rise of digital technology, and ironically with the rise of flexible working, workers are expected to work all the time and everywhere. You have to be “always on”,5 to the point where it feels like your work now has the prerogative to demand all your waking hours and possibly your unconscious hours when we consider how much we think about work.</p><p>Not only is working such long hours detrimental to workers’ and their families’ wellbeing – for example, by not allowing parents to spend time with their family – it also largely excludes workers with any responsibilities outside of work. This includes caring for children, family or friends and self-care – namely, anyone with a disability or long-term illness, and those with responsibilities to their community, friends, pets or any other aspect of life that can collide with the long-hours work culture. Any indication that you may have responsibilities outside of work is likely to result in doubt of your work commitment and productivity, regardless of what you actually produce.6 This long-hours working can be especially detrimental for marginalised workers whose work capacity is already questioned – such as mothers, disabled people, minority ethnic workers and LGBT+ workers – as many already overwork and go above and beyond to prove their worth. In the UK, 88 per cent of workers experienced burnout recently, costing the UK £28 billion yearly,7 with burnout and other mental health problems being especially high for marginalised workers. What is worse, we are not burning out to enhance the world or bring forth a new future for humanity. Two out of five Britons feel that their work is not making any meaningful contribution to the world8 and 69 per cent report that they are burning out precisely because ","PeriodicalId":37420,"journal":{"name":"IPPR Progressive Review","volume":"30 2","pages":"121-127"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-08-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/newe.12351","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44203989","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Multiculturalism 多元文化主义
Q4 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2023-08-10 DOI: 10.1111/newe.12350
Tariq Modood

We are all aware that we live in societies with heightened diversity and that aspects of that are being used divisively. So a response is that we need to bring people together by making some kind of deal amongst ourselves, or with the state – some kind of social contract. Social contract thinking – originating in the religious divisions of the 17th century – usually emerges when trust is breaking down and society is becoming a jungle (famously for Hobbes, “nasty, brutish and short”). Yet the remedy, a contract between self-interested individuals (or between groups), may pacify but it is not enough to make people care for each other. We need something stronger than transactional thinking to deal with the stresses and strains of diversity, and to tackle the rampant polarisation we are seeing today. We need respect and belonging, a sense of the public or national good, not just contracts. I believe that multiculturalism has a contribution to make here. This may sound preposterous – for some people, multiculturalism is the problem! Well, yes, if you think that multiculturalism is all about singular identities, separatism, the privileging of minorities, racial binaries, unprovoked militancy, fundamentalism, ethnic absolutism, anti-nationalism and so on. But that is a caricature. I know of no multiculturalist theorist – as opposed to liberal globalist, aka a cosmopolitan – who has advocated any of these things. In any case, let me offer you a different vision of multiculturalism.

The subtitle of my 2007 book, Multiculturalism, was A civic idea.1 My argument was that multiculturalism was derived from a political ethics of citizenship that includes but goes beyond rights, representation, rule of law and so on, namely not just a liberal citizenship. All modes of integration should be analysed in terms of their interpretation of the triad of liberty, equality and fraternity/solidarity.

Multiculturalism is specifically concerned with the right to a subgroup identity and that subgroup identity is treated in an equal citizenship way. This means symbolic recognition but also institutional accommodation and the remaking of the whole, namely of the citizenship identity itself. This leads to a second feature, namely the recognition of the subgroup identity as part of or at least consistent with full membership, a form of inclusion that allows all citizens to have a sense of belonging to their national citizenship; sometimes expressed as fraternity or solidarity. Minorities, especially marginalised or oppressed minorities, have this right to group identity recognition because the majorities do; or, if you like, all subgroups, including the majority, have this right.

If, as I believe, multiculturalism is trying to provide minorities with what majorities have or seek to have, namely their own national or cultural identities folded into their citizenship, I also have come to appreciate that parts of majorities have become identity-a

我们都意识到,我们生活在一个多样性增强的社会中,而多样性的各个方面正在被分裂地利用。因此,我们需要通过在我们自己之间或与国家之间达成某种协议——某种社会契约,将人们团结在一起。社会契约思维起源于17世纪的宗教分裂,通常在信任破裂、社会变成丛林时出现(霍布斯的名言是“肮脏、野蛮、矮小”)。然而,这种补救措施,即自利的个人之间(或群体之间)的合同,可能会起到安抚作用,但不足以让人们相互关心。我们需要比交易思维更强大的东西来应对多样性的压力和紧张,并应对我们今天看到的猖獗的两极分化。我们需要尊重和归属感,一种公共或国家利益感,而不仅仅是合同。我相信多元文化主义在这里可以作出贡献。这听起来可能很荒谬——对一些人来说,多元文化才是问题所在!好吧,是的,如果你认为多元文化主义都是关于单一身份、分离主义、少数民族特权、种族二元主义、无端好战、原教旨主义、种族专制主义、反民族主义等等。但这是一幅漫画。据我所知,没有一位多元文化理论家——与自由主义全球主义者,也就是世界主义者——主张过这些东西。无论如何,让我为你提供一个不同的多元文化观。我2007年出版的《多元文化主义》一书的副标题是“公民理念”。1我的论点是,多元文化主义源于公民的政治伦理,包括但不限于权利、代表权、法治等,即不仅仅是自由公民。所有融合模式都应根据其对自由、平等和博爱/团结三重概念的解释进行分析。多元文化主义特别关注亚群体身份的权利,这种亚群体身份以平等的公民身份对待。这意味着象征性的承认,但也意味着制度上的包容和整体的重塑,即公民身份本身。这导致了第二个特点,即承认亚群体身份是正式成员身份的一部分或至少与正式成员身份一致,这是一种包容形式,使所有公民都能对其国家公民身份有归属感;有时表现为友爱或团结。少数群体,特别是被边缘化或受压迫的少数群体,有权获得群体身份认同,因为多数人有这样的权利;或者,如果你愿意的话,所有的子群,包括大多数,都有这个权利。如果像我认为的那样,多元文化主义试图为少数群体提供多数群体所拥有或寻求的东西,即他们自己的民族或文化身份融入他们的公民身份,我也开始意识到,部分多数群体已经变得对身份焦虑,多元文化者应该对此保持敏感,尽管这会使多元文化框架复杂化。因此,尽管多元文化主义者可能需要更多地考虑“多数人”,但现有理论并不是对多数文化本身持否定态度,甚至不是说多元文化主义是为了保护少数群体免受多数文化的影响。没有一个国家,包括自由民主国家,在文化上是中立的——所有国家都支持某种或多种语言,支持与国定假日有关的宗教日历,支持学校的宗教教学,支持宗教学校的资助,支持某些艺术、体育和休闲活动等等。自然,这种语言、宗教、艺术或体育将是大多数人口的语言、宗教或体育。即使没有恶意统治在起作用,这也是事实。因此,重要的是要区分多数文化的制度统治何时存在或不存在,以及它何时具有或可能合法具有规范价值。例如,英语在英国具有事实上的主导地位,这在很多方面都得到了体现。然而,人们也可以认识到,鉴于英语在历史上和今天对英国人民的意义,它的地位具有规范价值。这种规范性的首要地位可以在不引入任何统治概念(如白人)的情况下得到解释,或者至少不必将其简化为白人问题。然而,对于多元文化主义来说,这是一个将这种有价值的条件——建立一个基于个人文化身份的社会——扩展到包括少数群体的问题。至少,文化多数群体在塑造民族文化、象征和制度方面享有的主导地位不应以非少数群体的方式行使。
{"title":"Multiculturalism","authors":"Tariq Modood","doi":"10.1111/newe.12350","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1111/newe.12350","url":null,"abstract":"<p>We are all aware that we live in societies with heightened diversity and that aspects of that are being used divisively. So a response is that we need to bring people together by making some kind of deal amongst ourselves, or with the state – some kind of social contract. Social contract thinking – originating in the religious divisions of the 17th century – usually emerges when trust is breaking down and society is becoming a jungle (famously for Hobbes, “nasty, brutish and short”). Yet the remedy, a contract between self-interested individuals (or between groups), may pacify but it is not enough to make people care for each other. We need something stronger than transactional thinking to deal with the stresses and strains of diversity, and to tackle the rampant polarisation we are seeing today. We need respect and belonging, a sense of the public or national good, not just contracts. I believe that multiculturalism has a contribution to make here. This may sound preposterous – for some people, multiculturalism is the problem! Well, yes, if you think that multiculturalism is all about singular identities, separatism, the privileging of minorities, racial binaries, unprovoked militancy, fundamentalism, ethnic absolutism, anti-nationalism and so on. But that is a caricature. I know of no multiculturalist theorist – as opposed to liberal globalist, aka a cosmopolitan – who has advocated any of these things. In any case, let me offer you a different vision of multiculturalism.</p><p>The subtitle of my 2007 book, <i>Multiculturalism</i>, was <i>A civic idea</i>.1 My argument was that multiculturalism was derived from a political ethics of citizenship that includes but goes beyond rights, representation, rule of law and so on, namely not just a liberal citizenship. All modes of integration should be analysed in terms of their interpretation of the triad of liberty, equality and fraternity/solidarity.</p><p>Multiculturalism is specifically concerned with the right to a subgroup identity and that subgroup identity is treated in an equal citizenship way. This means symbolic recognition but also institutional accommodation and the remaking of the whole, namely of the citizenship identity itself. This leads to a second feature, namely the recognition of the subgroup identity as part of or at least consistent with full membership, a form of inclusion that allows all citizens to have a sense of belonging to their national citizenship; sometimes expressed as fraternity or solidarity. Minorities, especially marginalised or oppressed minorities, have this right to group identity recognition because the majorities do; or, if you like, all subgroups, including the majority, have this right.</p><p>If, as I believe, multiculturalism is trying to provide minorities with what majorities have or seek to have, namely their own national or cultural identities folded into their citizenship, I also have come to appreciate that parts of majorities have become identity-a","PeriodicalId":37420,"journal":{"name":"IPPR Progressive Review","volume":"30 2","pages":"77-83"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-08-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/newe.12350","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"50145871","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Rebuilding the UK's social contract 重建英国的社会契约
Q4 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2023-08-10 DOI: 10.1111/newe.12348
Anna Coote
{"title":"Rebuilding the UK's social contract","authors":"Anna Coote","doi":"10.1111/newe.12348","DOIUrl":"10.1111/newe.12348","url":null,"abstract":"","PeriodicalId":37420,"journal":{"name":"IPPR Progressive Review","volume":"30 2","pages":"69-76"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-08-10","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"43472424","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Committing a benevolent insult? 做出善意的侮辱?
Q4 Social Sciences Pub Date : 2023-08-09 DOI: 10.1111/newe.12349
Emily Kenway

In the case of care, two needs are assumed in progressive political spaces: the need of the person receiving care to be supported, and the consequent structural need of society to have a state-provided socialised service which meets that first need. This is the logic underpinning calls for a universal care service kindred to the NHS and the general sense that, if the ‘burden’ of care is falling on unpaid family and friends, it's due to the under-resourcing of state provision. Those 6 million unpaid carers are labelled as either a vestige of past and archaic arrangements that need to be removed, or a worrisome harbinger of things to come, in which social spending dips even further. Under this ‘need interpretation’, care is construed as impinging on the natural order of our capitalist lives – taking us away from productive activities – that is, wage labour – and preventing women from pursuing freedom, located in the notion of the career.

Second, many care receivers do not accept support from people outside of their family unit. One study that sought to understand caring relationships between neighbours and frail older people asked why and how the former were stepping in to support the latter.8 It found that, in some instances, it was because the older people had refused offers of government services, even lying to avoid being deemed needy. Others had simply refused support or cancelled it once it was in place. When we forget that people with care needs are people, and therefore have preferences and claims to self-determination, we fail to design a system that is truly human.

These four factors add up to one truth, which is absent from current policy prescriptions and how we understand our need for care: however good our services become, it won't change whether most of those 6 million people are carers. Instead of ignoring carers, or treating them as an unfortunate afterthought, we must take a systemic approach that addresses the now-revealed need – the right to provide care to our loved ones in ways which don't undermine our mental, physical, social and financial health.

We can see this in the example of the Older Women's Co-Housing (OWCH) project in north London. Twenty-five women aged 50 and over live ‘together but alone’ in a smartly designed complex of private apartments and shared spaces. While they must have care arrangements in place for intensive care needs, there is also a lot of interpersonal care taking place, as within a family. They have health buddies and, when needed, have created rotas to provide support.13 Importantly, there are 25 of them, a far broader base for care than provided by the nuclear family. Theirs is the kind of collective care we need but which sits uneasily with current policies. We lack a way to articulate this kind of arrangement: for example, if the OWCH residents were completing a census, they would tick the box for living alone because they have private apartments. But they don't; th

就护理而言,在进步的政治空间中假设了两种需求:接受护理的人需要得到支持,以及随之而来的社会结构性需求,即国家提供的社会化服务,以满足第一种需求。这就是呼吁建立一种类似于英国国民健康保险制度(NHS)的全民保健服务的逻辑基础,而且人们普遍认为,如果护理的“负担”落在了无偿的家人和朋友身上,那是由于国家提供的资源不足。这600万无薪照顾者被贴上了这样的标签:要么是过去和过时安排的残余,需要取消,要么是未来社会支出进一步下降的令人担忧的预兆。在这种“需要解释”下,关心被解释为对我们资本主义生活的自然秩序的冲击——使我们远离生产性活动——也就是雇佣劳动——并阻止女性追求自由,即职业概念。第二,许多接受照护者不接受来自家庭单位以外的人的支持。有一项研究试图理解邻居和体弱多病的老人之间的关怀关系,他们问邻居为什么以及如何帮助老人调查发现,在某些情况下,这是因为老年人拒绝了政府提供的服务,甚至撒谎以避免被认为需要帮助。其他国家则干脆拒绝支持,或者在项目到位后取消。当我们忘记需要照顾的人也是人,因此有偏好和自决的要求时,我们就无法设计出一个真正人性化的系统。这四个因素加起来构成了一个事实,而这个事实在当前的政策处方和我们如何理解我们对护理的需求中是缺失的:无论我们的服务变得多么好,这600万人中的大多数人都是护理人员,这一点不会改变。我们不能忽视照顾者,或者把他们当作事后才想到的不幸的人来对待,我们必须采取一种系统的方法来解决现在暴露出来的需求——在不损害我们的精神、身体、社会和经济健康的情况下,为我们所爱的人提供照顾的权利。我们可以在伦敦北部的老年妇女共同住房(OWCH)项目中看到这一点。25位50岁及以上的女性住在一个由私人公寓和共享空间组成的精心设计的综合体里。虽然他们必须有适当的护理安排,以满足重症监护的需要,但也有很多人际护理,就像在家庭中一样。他们有健康伙伴,并在需要时成立轮岗组织提供支持重要的是,有25个这样的家庭,这是一个比核心家庭更广泛的照顾基础。他们的集体关怀是我们所需要的,但与现行政策格格不入。我们缺乏一种方式来表达这种安排:例如,如果OWCH的居民正在完成人口普查,他们会勾选独自生活,因为他们有私人公寓。但他们没有;他们的日常生活中还有其他24个人,一个支持他们的网准备好了。OWCH是一个伟大的成功故事,也是世界各地共同住房运动的一部分,包括丹麦、荷兰和美国。但这一成功背后隐藏着一个令人不安的事实:由于财政和监管方面的障碍,OWCH花了几十年的时间才建成。英国的其他合租社区也面临着障碍规划许可、建筑监管、房地产价格、融资模式和房地产实践都在这里发挥作用。就像工作时间和收入一样,我们需要政府提供物质基础设施、空间和支持,以实现护理。如果我们坚持我们最初的、有缺陷的护理“需求解释”,我们就会模糊政府这些系统性的、想象中的角色。在试图结束无薪照顾者的极度痛苦时,我们将犯下善意的侮辱,忽视照顾的现实,支持理论上有吸引力,但实际上没有根据的解决方案。未来的护理工作将不再仅仅是一种有报酬的工作,它将爱情和生活经验都排除在外。在这个世界里,关怀被嵌入到我们日常生活的节奏、权利和结构中。
{"title":"Committing a benevolent insult?","authors":"Emily Kenway","doi":"10.1111/newe.12349","DOIUrl":"10.1111/newe.12349","url":null,"abstract":"<p>In the case of care, two needs are assumed in progressive political spaces: the need of the person receiving care to be supported, and the consequent structural need of society to have a state-provided socialised service which meets that first need. This is the logic underpinning calls for a universal care service kindred to the NHS and the general sense that, if the ‘burden’ of care is falling on unpaid family and friends, it's due to the under-resourcing of state provision. Those 6 million unpaid carers are labelled as either a vestige of past and archaic arrangements that need to be removed, or a worrisome harbinger of things to come, in which social spending dips even further. Under this ‘need interpretation’, care is construed as impinging on the natural order of our capitalist lives – taking us away from productive activities – that is, wage labour – and preventing women from pursuing freedom, located in the notion of the career.</p><p>Second, many care receivers do not accept support from people outside of their family unit. One study that sought to understand caring relationships between neighbours and frail older people asked why and how the former were stepping in to support the latter.8 It found that, in some instances, it was because the older people had refused offers of government services, even lying to avoid being deemed needy. Others had simply refused support or cancelled it once it was in place. When we forget that people with care needs are <i>people</i>, and therefore have preferences and claims to self-determination, we fail to design a system that is truly human.</p><p>These four factors add up to one truth, which is absent from current policy prescriptions and how we understand our need for care: however good our services become, it won't change whether most of those 6 million people are carers. Instead of ignoring carers, or treating them as an unfortunate afterthought, we must take a systemic approach that addresses the now-revealed need – the right to provide care to our loved ones in ways which don't undermine our mental, physical, social and financial health.</p><p>We can see this in the example of the Older Women's Co-Housing (OWCH) project in north London. Twenty-five women aged 50 and over live ‘together but alone’ in a smartly designed complex of private apartments and shared spaces. While they must have care arrangements in place for intensive care needs, there is also a lot of interpersonal care taking place, as within a family. They have health buddies and, when needed, have created rotas to provide support.13 Importantly, there are 25 of them, a far broader base for care than provided by the nuclear family. Theirs is the kind of collective care we need but which sits uneasily with current policies. We lack a way to articulate this kind of arrangement: for example, if the OWCH residents were completing a census, they would tick the box for living alone because they have private apartments. But they don't; th","PeriodicalId":37420,"journal":{"name":"IPPR Progressive Review","volume":"30 2","pages":"115-120"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0,"publicationDate":"2023-08-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/epdf/10.1111/newe.12349","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44242086","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"OA","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
IPPR Progressive Review
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1