首页 > 最新文献

Journal of Literary Theory最新文献

英文 中文
The Implied Fictional Narrator 隐含的虚构叙述者
IF 0.2 Pub Date : 2020-02-28 DOI: 10.1515/JLT-2020-0007
J. Bareis
Abstract The role of the narrator in fiction has recently received renewed interest from scholars in philosophical aesthetics and narratology. Many of the contributions criticise how the term is used – both outside of narrative literature as well as within the field of fictional narrative literature. The central part of the attacks has been the ubiquity of fictional narrators, see e. g. Kania (2005), and pan-narrator theories have been dismissed, e. g. by Köppe and Stühring (2011). Yet, the fictional narrator has been a decisive tool within literary narratology for many years, in particular during the heyday of classical literary narratology. For scholars like Genette (1988) and Cohn (1999), the category of the fictional narrator was at the centre of theoretical debates about the demarcation of fiction and non-fiction. Arguably, theorising about the fictional narrator necessitates theorising about fiction in general. From this, it follows that any account on which the fictional narrator is built ideally would be a theory of fiction compatible with all types of fictional narrative media – not just narrative fiction like novels and short stories. In this vein, this paper applies a transmedial approach to the question of fictional narrators in different media based on the transmedial theory of fiction in terms of make-believe by Kendall Walton (1990). Although the article shares roughly the same theoretical point of departure as Köppe and Stühring, that is, an analytical-philosophical theory of fiction as make-believe, it offers a diametrically different solution. Building on the distinction between direct and indirect fictional truths as developed by Kendall Walton in his seminal theory of fiction as make-believe (1990), this paper proposes the fictional presence of a narrator in all fictional narratives. Importantly, ›presence‹ in terms of being part of a work of fiction needs to be understood as exactly that: fictional presence, meaning that the question of what counts as a fictional truth is of great importance. Here, the distinction between direct and indirect fictional truths is crucial since not every fictional narrative – not even every literary fictional narrative – makes it directly fictionally true that it is narrated. To exemplify: not every novel begins with words like »Call me Ishmael«, i. e., stating direct fictional truths about its narrator. Indirect, implied fictional truths can also be part of the generation of the fictional truth of a fictional narrator. Therefore, the paper argues that every fictional narrative makes it (at least indirectly) fictionally true that it is narrated. More specifically, the argument is made that any theory of fictional narrative that accepts fictional narrators in some cases (as e. g. suggested by proponents of the so-called optional narrator theory, such as Currie [2010]), has to accept fictional narrators in all cases of fictional narratives. The only other option is to remove the category of fictio
小说中叙述者的角色近来受到哲学美学和叙事学学者的重新关注。许多贡献都批评了这个词的使用方式——无论是在叙事文学之外,还是在虚构叙事文学领域。攻击的核心部分是虚构的叙述者无处不在,见e。 g.卡尼亚(2005),泛叙述者理论被否定。 g.Köppe和Stühring(2011)。然而,多年来,小说叙述者一直是文学叙事学中的决定性工具,尤其是在古典文学叙事学的鼎盛时期。对于像Genette(1988)和Cohn(1999)这样的学者来说,虚构叙述者的类别是关于小说和非小说划分的理论辩论的中心。可以说,关于虚构叙述者的理论化需要关于一般小说的理论化。由此可知,理想情况下,虚构叙述者所基于的任何叙述都将是一种与所有类型的虚构叙事媒体兼容的小说理论,而不仅仅是小说和短篇小说等叙事小说。在这方面,本文基于Kendall Walton(1990)的虚构跨领域理论,将跨领域方法应用于不同媒体中的虚构叙述者问题。尽管这篇文章与科佩和斯特林有着大致相同的理论出发点,即虚构小说的分析哲学理论,但它提供了一个截然不同的解决方案。根据肯德尔·沃尔顿在其开创性的虚构理论(1990)中提出的直接和间接虚构真相之间的区别,本文提出在所有虚构叙事中都有叙述者的虚构存在。重要的是,›作为小说作品的一部分,需要准确地理解为:虚构的存在,这意味着什么是虚构的真相的问题非常重要。在这里,直接和间接虚构真相之间的区别至关重要,因为并不是每一个虚构叙事——甚至不是每一种文学虚构叙事——都能使其直接虚构真实。举个例子:并不是每本小说都以“叫我以实玛利”这样的词开头。 e.直接叙述叙述者的虚构真相。间接的、隐含的虚构真相也可能是虚构叙述者虚构真相产生的一部分。因此,本文认为,每一个虚构的叙事都使它(至少间接地)在虚构上是真实的。更具体地说,任何在某些情况下接受虚构叙述者的虚构叙事理论(如e。 g.由所谓的可选叙述者理论的支持者提出,如Currie[2010]),在所有虚构叙事的情况下都必须接受虚构叙述者。唯一的其他选择是完全取消虚构叙述者的类别。由于虚构叙述者的类别在叙事学史上被证明是非常有用的,因此这种删除是不幸的。相反,提出了一种解决方案,强调接受者在产生虚构真相,特别是在产生隐含虚构真相方面的积极作用。一旦从虚构真相的角度理解了虚构叙事者的叙事类别,就可以完全掌握方法论的后果:如果没有在虚构游戏中产生虚构真相,就没有虚构叙事——也就没有虚构的叙事者。叙事的虚构性完全取决于它们被用作虚构游戏中的道具这一事实。如果不以这种方式使用,它们只不过是纸上的黑点、银通过光的氧化,或任何其他包含表征的人工制品的技术描述。虚构的叙述者总是基于虚构的真相,他们是虚构游戏的结果,因此虚构叙述者的唯一证据总是仅仅是虚构的。如果无法想象虚构作品是叙事的,那么这部作品就不是叙事。在论文的第一部分,讨论了支持和反对虚构叙述者的常见论点,如分析性的、现实主义的、跨领域的和所谓的证据论点;此外,虚构电影中的不可靠叙事将成为捍卫虚构叙事中无处不在的虚构叙述者的重要组成部分。如果不可靠叙事的类别依赖于作者、叙事者和读者的相互作用,那么在非传统口头叙事小说(如小说电影)中,不可靠叙事问题就变得非常有问题。
{"title":"The Implied Fictional Narrator","authors":"J. Bareis","doi":"10.1515/JLT-2020-0007","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/JLT-2020-0007","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract The role of the narrator in fiction has recently received renewed interest from scholars in philosophical aesthetics and narratology. Many of the contributions criticise how the term is used – both outside of narrative literature as well as within the field of fictional narrative literature. The central part of the attacks has been the ubiquity of fictional narrators, see e. g. Kania (2005), and pan-narrator theories have been dismissed, e. g. by Köppe and Stühring (2011). Yet, the fictional narrator has been a decisive tool within literary narratology for many years, in particular during the heyday of classical literary narratology. For scholars like Genette (1988) and Cohn (1999), the category of the fictional narrator was at the centre of theoretical debates about the demarcation of fiction and non-fiction. Arguably, theorising about the fictional narrator necessitates theorising about fiction in general. From this, it follows that any account on which the fictional narrator is built ideally would be a theory of fiction compatible with all types of fictional narrative media – not just narrative fiction like novels and short stories. In this vein, this paper applies a transmedial approach to the question of fictional narrators in different media based on the transmedial theory of fiction in terms of make-believe by Kendall Walton (1990). Although the article shares roughly the same theoretical point of departure as Köppe and Stühring, that is, an analytical-philosophical theory of fiction as make-believe, it offers a diametrically different solution. Building on the distinction between direct and indirect fictional truths as developed by Kendall Walton in his seminal theory of fiction as make-believe (1990), this paper proposes the fictional presence of a narrator in all fictional narratives. Importantly, ›presence‹ in terms of being part of a work of fiction needs to be understood as exactly that: fictional presence, meaning that the question of what counts as a fictional truth is of great importance. Here, the distinction between direct and indirect fictional truths is crucial since not every fictional narrative – not even every literary fictional narrative – makes it directly fictionally true that it is narrated. To exemplify: not every novel begins with words like »Call me Ishmael«, i. e., stating direct fictional truths about its narrator. Indirect, implied fictional truths can also be part of the generation of the fictional truth of a fictional narrator. Therefore, the paper argues that every fictional narrative makes it (at least indirectly) fictionally true that it is narrated. More specifically, the argument is made that any theory of fictional narrative that accepts fictional narrators in some cases (as e. g. suggested by proponents of the so-called optional narrator theory, such as Currie [2010]), has to accept fictional narrators in all cases of fictional narratives. The only other option is to remove the category of fictio","PeriodicalId":42872,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Literary Theory","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2020-02-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1515/JLT-2020-0007","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"45750372","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
When Not Communicating. The Critical Potential of the Literary Text and the Limits of Interpretation 不沟通时。文学文本的批判潜力与阐释的局限
IF 0.2 Pub Date : 2020-02-28 DOI: 10.1515/jlt-2020-0004
A. Iannarone
Abstract Today, as announced by this special issue, the contest of interpretation against aesthetic experience appears urgent and timely. For surely a critical profession should clarify its sense of how to proceed before actually engaging to do so. But how are we to have any such sense in advance of an encounter with the literary text, ostensible object of the discipline? I argue that it is only within the limits of critique, as met with in the objectivity of the artwork, that we might be confident of our interpretations. To paraphrase Hegel, literary interpretation misses an advantage enjoyed by the natural sciences (Hegel 1959, 33). Although recourse may be made to individual works of formal writing in »evidence« of a theory, still, no literary interpretation can presume its methods to be already accepted. Moreover, purely »systematic or theoretical« discussions of interpretation ring hollow when and, indeed, because they are empty of perceptible content. For the honest reader, the literary artwork remains sensibly resilient or resistant to, not to say frustrating of, systematic discussions – and this must be taken into account. As readers (rather than philosophers) of literature we are in luck, for even (or especially) without determining the meaning of a given work, we have before us something that remains »outside« of us. In sustaining his or her attention to this external object (and in coming to regard it as an »artwork«), and thus compelled to see the qualitative distance within and structuring experience, the reader finds that the text is more than just some thing or technical device to conceal meaning. It is what Adorno calls »the objectivity« of the artwork produced by the »movement of the mind« of the subject that, I argue, critiques the apparent choice of independent meaning or independent sensuousness as alternative bases for interpretive practice (Adorno 1983, 19). The literary work, as it becomes objective for its reader, becomes too a limit upon how that reader interprets it, that is, a limit upon the merely subjective. The trouble with the question of whether to privilege the sensuousness or the meaning of art, is that it is framed as though this were still a choice to be made, as if the one could be isolated from, and be taken without concern for the other. Perhaps we cannot be reminded too often, as Claudia Brodsky reminds us, that not since the »first modern redefinition« of the »aesthetic« in Kant’s Third Critique could »specific content« be »considered in isolation from form«. No more can the critical project be put back into the bottle, than the »dynamism« of form articulated through Kant’s analysis of aesthetic judgment be reduced once more to either static form or content. The consideration of »meaning« isolated from form must remain, alas, the advantage of the natural sciences. If, as Brodsky continues with Kant’s definition, »dynamic, ›purposive‹ form causes our pleasure in the aesthetic«, then the consideration of sen
摘要今天,正如本期特刊所宣布的那样,解读与审美体验的较量显得紧迫而及时。当然,一个批判性的专业在真正参与之前应该澄清它对如何进行的感觉。但是,在遇到文学文本,这个学科表面上的对象之前,我们怎么能有这样的感觉呢?我认为,只有在艺术作品客观性的批评范围内,我们才能对自己的解释充满信心。套用黑格尔的话,文学解释忽略了自然科学所享有的优势(黑格尔1959,33)。尽管在一种理论的“证据”中可以求助于正式写作的个别作品,但任何文学解释都不能认为其方法已经被接受。此外,纯粹的“系统的或理论的”解释讨论听起来是空洞的,事实上,因为它们缺乏可感知的内容。对于诚实的读者来说,文学作品对系统性的讨论保持着理智的弹性或抵抗力,更不用说令人沮丧了——这一点必须考虑在内。作为文学的读者(而不是哲学家),我们很幸运,因为即使(或特别是)在没有确定给定作品的意义的情况下,我们面前也有一些“外部”的东西。在保持他或她对这个外部对象的关注(并将其视为一件“艺术品”)的过程中,我们不得不看到内部和结构体验的质的距离,读者发现文本不仅仅是某种东西或技术手段来隐藏意义。我认为,正是阿多诺所说的由主体的“心灵运动”产生的艺术作品的“客观性”,批评了将独立意义或独立感性作为解释实践的替代基础的明显选择(阿多诺1983,19)。当文学作品对读者来说变得客观时,它对读者解读它的方式也变得过于有限,也就是说,对仅仅是主观的限制。是对艺术的感性还是意义给予特权的问题的问题在于,它被框定为这仍然是一个需要做出的选择,就好像一个可以与另一个隔离开来,并且可以在不考虑另一个的情况下进行。正如克劳迪娅·布罗德斯基(Claudia Brodsky)提醒我们的那样,也许我们不能经常被提醒,自从康德的《第三批判》中对美学的“第一次现代重新定义”以来,就不能“孤立地”考虑具体的内容。正如康德对审美判断的分析所表达的形式的“动态性”再次被简化为静态的形式或内容一样,这个关键项目再也不能被放回瓶子里了。遗憾的是,对“意义”与形式隔绝的考虑必须保留自然科学的优势。如果,正如布罗德斯基继续康德的定义一样,“动态的,›目的性的”形式引起了我们在美学中的快乐“,那么对与形式隔离的感官体验的考虑仍然与“美学”的原始、古老的含义“联系在一起”,“与任何感官体验有关”(布罗德斯基1997376)。如果随后似乎(外部)“意义的揭示”和(内部)“审美愉悦”之间存在着无法沟通的矛盾,我们必须记住,在对可感知对象的分析中,如果审美不完全从视野中消失,这两者就无法分离——因为,根据现代定义,当我们称某事物为“美学”对象时,它们相互暗示的外观就是我们的意思。康德对美感的激进分析及其对主体性和形式客体不能相互隔离的暗示,使古代定义中隐含的主体和客体之间干净、绝对的决裂变得不可挽回地复杂。即使当“美学”的古老含义被用来再次谈论与形式隔绝的感觉时,作为文学的阐释者和评论家,这种考虑对我们来说并不有利,而是导致了其他更积极的学科,对形式对象和感知主体的双重运动没有购买力。这种批判性的重新定义对文学解释实践的影响仍然没有解决,或者即使在理论上已经解决,也没有被吸收到实践中。本期特刊的编辑们提出了美学与阐释之间的僵局或危机,作为我们今天的主题。在康德和阿多诺之间的动态形式或双重运动的美学传统中,我找到了另一个激进的阐释传统,即黑人美学批判。
{"title":"When Not Communicating. The Critical Potential of the Literary Text and the Limits of Interpretation","authors":"A. Iannarone","doi":"10.1515/jlt-2020-0004","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/jlt-2020-0004","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Today, as announced by this special issue, the contest of interpretation against aesthetic experience appears urgent and timely. For surely a critical profession should clarify its sense of how to proceed before actually engaging to do so. But how are we to have any such sense in advance of an encounter with the literary text, ostensible object of the discipline? I argue that it is only within the limits of critique, as met with in the objectivity of the artwork, that we might be confident of our interpretations. To paraphrase Hegel, literary interpretation misses an advantage enjoyed by the natural sciences (Hegel 1959, 33). Although recourse may be made to individual works of formal writing in »evidence« of a theory, still, no literary interpretation can presume its methods to be already accepted. Moreover, purely »systematic or theoretical« discussions of interpretation ring hollow when and, indeed, because they are empty of perceptible content. For the honest reader, the literary artwork remains sensibly resilient or resistant to, not to say frustrating of, systematic discussions – and this must be taken into account. As readers (rather than philosophers) of literature we are in luck, for even (or especially) without determining the meaning of a given work, we have before us something that remains »outside« of us. In sustaining his or her attention to this external object (and in coming to regard it as an »artwork«), and thus compelled to see the qualitative distance within and structuring experience, the reader finds that the text is more than just some thing or technical device to conceal meaning. It is what Adorno calls »the objectivity« of the artwork produced by the »movement of the mind« of the subject that, I argue, critiques the apparent choice of independent meaning or independent sensuousness as alternative bases for interpretive practice (Adorno 1983, 19). The literary work, as it becomes objective for its reader, becomes too a limit upon how that reader interprets it, that is, a limit upon the merely subjective. The trouble with the question of whether to privilege the sensuousness or the meaning of art, is that it is framed as though this were still a choice to be made, as if the one could be isolated from, and be taken without concern for the other. Perhaps we cannot be reminded too often, as Claudia Brodsky reminds us, that not since the »first modern redefinition« of the »aesthetic« in Kant’s Third Critique could »specific content« be »considered in isolation from form«. No more can the critical project be put back into the bottle, than the »dynamism« of form articulated through Kant’s analysis of aesthetic judgment be reduced once more to either static form or content. The consideration of »meaning« isolated from form must remain, alas, the advantage of the natural sciences. If, as Brodsky continues with Kant’s definition, »dynamic, ›purposive‹ form causes our pleasure in the aesthetic«, then the consideration of sen","PeriodicalId":42872,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Literary Theory","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2020-02-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1515/jlt-2020-0004","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44220596","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Interpretation and Aesthetic Appreciation 诠释与审美
IF 0.2 Pub Date : 2020-02-28 DOI: 10.1515/jlt-2020-0001
Wouter T. C. Bisschop
Abstract In order to talk and think sensibly about the various ways of engaging with texts, we need to distinguish them by reference to relevant differences and commonalities between them. This paper focusses on the conceptual relations between three ways of engaging with texts that figure prominently in literary scholarship: textual interpretation, literary interpretation, and aesthetic appreciation. Rather than giving a full analysis of these three terms, this paper has two specific concerns. First, it is argued that literary interpretation is best understood as a species of textual interpretation. Second, and relatedly, some theorists argue that the discriminating feature of literary interpretation is its aim of aesthetic appreciation. Aesthetic appreciation may refer to either (i) a judgement about or (ii) an experience of or (iii) an attempt to identify and evaluate the aesthetic properties of something. The idea that appreciative judgements or experiences are the main aims of literary interpretation should not lead to a conceptual confusion of literary interpretation with aesthetic evaluation (or appreciative acts), even if there is a sense in which the idea is correct. Aesthetic appreciation is, at most, a secondary aim of literary interpretation and may function as a motivation to engage in literary interpretation. This aligns well with the idea that aesthetic appreciation has a significance independent from interpretation. Their conceptual distinction notwithstanding, it is argued that there are interesting evidential relations between (literary) interpretation and aesthetic appreciation. These relations of support, evidence, or justification may go either way.
摘要为了明智地谈论和思考与文本接触的各种方式,我们需要参考它们之间的相关差异和共性来区分它们。本文着重探讨了在文学学术中占据突出地位的三种文本处理方式之间的概念关系:文本解读、文学解读和审美。本文没有对这三个术语进行全面的分析,而是有两个具体的问题。首先,有人认为,文学解释最好被理解为一种文本解释。其次,一些理论家认为文学阐释的辨别特征是其审美目的。审美欣赏可以指(i)对事物的判断,或(ii)对事物体验,或(iii)试图识别和评估事物的审美特性。欣赏性判断或体验是文学阐释的主要目的的观点不应导致文学阐释与审美评价(或欣赏行为)在概念上的混淆,即使这种观点是正确的。审美至多是文学阐释的次要目的,并可能成为从事文学阐释的动机。这与审美具有独立于阐释的意义的观点非常一致。尽管它们在概念上有区别,但有人认为(文学)解释和审美之间存在着有趣的证据关系。这些支持、证据或正当性的关系可以是任意一种。
{"title":"Interpretation and Aesthetic Appreciation","authors":"Wouter T. C. Bisschop","doi":"10.1515/jlt-2020-0001","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/jlt-2020-0001","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract In order to talk and think sensibly about the various ways of engaging with texts, we need to distinguish them by reference to relevant differences and commonalities between them. This paper focusses on the conceptual relations between three ways of engaging with texts that figure prominently in literary scholarship: textual interpretation, literary interpretation, and aesthetic appreciation. Rather than giving a full analysis of these three terms, this paper has two specific concerns. First, it is argued that literary interpretation is best understood as a species of textual interpretation. Second, and relatedly, some theorists argue that the discriminating feature of literary interpretation is its aim of aesthetic appreciation. Aesthetic appreciation may refer to either (i) a judgement about or (ii) an experience of or (iii) an attempt to identify and evaluate the aesthetic properties of something. The idea that appreciative judgements or experiences are the main aims of literary interpretation should not lead to a conceptual confusion of literary interpretation with aesthetic evaluation (or appreciative acts), even if there is a sense in which the idea is correct. Aesthetic appreciation is, at most, a secondary aim of literary interpretation and may function as a motivation to engage in literary interpretation. This aligns well with the idea that aesthetic appreciation has a significance independent from interpretation. Their conceptual distinction notwithstanding, it is argued that there are interesting evidential relations between (literary) interpretation and aesthetic appreciation. These relations of support, evidence, or justification may go either way.","PeriodicalId":42872,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Literary Theory","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2020-02-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1515/jlt-2020-0001","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46174397","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Poetik der Kritik – Ästhetik des Deutens 批评诗学——阐释美学
IF 0.2 Pub Date : 2020-02-28 DOI: 10.1515/jlt-2020-0003
R. Görner
Abstract Some of the mainly unchartered territories in literary criticism are the implications of Susan Sontag’s frontal attack on traditional hermeneutical practices in Against Interpretation (1969). This contribution to investigations into the modes of interpretation attempts to draw constructive consequences from this provocation and investigate the notion of a ›poetics of criticism‹ emanating into what can be called the ›aesthetics of interpretation‹. In so doing, it explores the Romantic backdrop of this discourse through examining Friedrich Schlegel’s plea for a ›poetization‹ of critique and his demand to turn critical approaches into aesthetic, if not artistic, acts. Then, these reflections examine notions of perception or Anschauung as a cornerstone of comprehension; discuss poetic renderings of thought with Nietzsche, who epitomizes the fusion of reflection and aesthetic production; single out one of Gottfried Benn’s early poems (»Kreislauf«) as an object for putting aesthetic interpretation into practice given the specific character of this Expressionistic text; and, finally, assess elements of theories of recognition in terms of aesthetic practice with specific reference to a paragraph in early Adorno, which highlights cognitive transformation processes as matters of aesthetic experience. Thus, this essay illustrates the interrelationship between critical theory and practice as an aesthetic act, which takes into account the significance of Sontag’s challenge, exemplifying the necessity of finding a language register that can claim to strive towards adequacy in relation to the (artistic) object of criticism without compromising analytical rigour. The argument developed in this contribution towards an aesthetics of interpretation begins with a critical appreciation of various forms and modes of criticism in literature and other aspects of artistic expression. It centres on the significance of the dialogue as an explorative means of critical discourse, ranging from Friedrich Schlegel to Hugo von Hofmannsthal and indeed Hans Magnus Enzensberger. With the (fictive) dialogue as an instrument of aesthetic judgement, ›experience‹ entered the stage of literary criticism negotiating ambivalences and considering alternative points of view often generated from the texts under consideration. In terms of the ambivalences mentioned above, this investigation into the nature of criticism considers the notion of criticism as a form of art and an extrapolation of aesthetic reason as propagated already by Henry Kames, once even quoted by Hegel in connection with the establishing of a rationale for the critical appreciation of artistic products. It discusses the interplay of distance from, and empathy with, objects of aesthetic criticism asking to what extent the act of interpretation (Wolfgang Iser) can acquire a creative momentum of its own without distorting its true mission, namely to assess the characteristics and aesthetic qualities of specific (poet
苏珊·桑塔格在《反对解释》(1969)中对传统解释学实践的正面攻击暗示了文学批评中一些主要的未知领域。这种对解释模式的研究的贡献试图从这种挑衅中得出建设性的结果,并研究一种“批评的诗学”的概念,这种概念可以被称为“解释的美学”。在此过程中,本书通过考察弗里德里希·施莱格尔(Friedrich Schlegel)对批评“诗化”的请求,以及他将批评方法转化为美学(如果不是艺术的话)行为的要求,探索了这一话语的浪漫背景。然后,这些反思考察了知觉概念或作为理解基石的安适性;与尼采讨论思想的诗意呈现,尼采是反思与美学生产融合的缩影;挑选出戈特弗里德·本恩的一首早期诗歌(《Kreislauf》)作为将美学解释付诸实践的对象,考虑到这首表现主义文本的具体特征;最后,根据早期阿多诺的一段话,从美学实践的角度评估认知理论的要素,这段话强调了作为审美经验问题的认知转化过程。因此,本文阐述了作为一种美学行为的批判理论与实践之间的相互关系,它考虑到了桑塔格挑战的重要性,举例说明了找到一种语言域的必要性,这种语言域可以声称在不损害分析严谨性的情况下,努力实现与(艺术)批评对象的适当性。在对阐释美学的贡献中发展起来的论点始于对文学和艺术表现的其他方面的各种形式和批评模式的批判性欣赏。它集中于对话作为一种批判性话语的探索手段的重要性,从弗里德里希·施莱格尔到雨果·冯·霍夫曼斯塔尔,甚至汉斯·马格努斯·恩岑斯伯格。随着(虚构的)对话作为审美判断的工具,“经验”进入了文学批评的阶段,讨论矛盾心理,并考虑经常从所考虑的文本中产生的替代观点。就上述矛盾而言,对批评本质的调查将批评的概念视为一种艺术形式和审美理性的外推,这一概念已经被亨利·卡姆斯传播,甚至一度被黑格尔引用,以建立对艺术产品的批判性欣赏的基本原理。它讨论了与审美批评对象的距离和共情的相互作用,要求解释行为(沃尔夫冈·伊瑟尔)在不扭曲其真正使命的情况下,在多大程度上能够获得自己的创造性动力,即评估特定(诗歌)文本或其他艺术对象的特征和美学品质。在仔细研究了尼采的几首诗和罗兰·巴特(Roland Barthes)对构成值得批评的文本实体的语言材料的分割的坚持之后,本文研究了戈特弗里德·本恩(Gottfried Benn)的一首早期诗歌(《Kreislauf》,1912),从其文本和结构动态、作为一种消极色情形式的尴尬性感方面进行了研究。在详细的语言学和诗歌研究的基础上,它展示了文学批评在何时何地以及如何有意义地识别结构特征作为审美经验的分母。最后一部分致力于将阿多诺的观点工具化,即概念可以不可避免地转化为图像,从而使认知理论获得一定的可信度,作为美学实践的潜在肥沃基础——无论是在文学批评还是诗歌创作中。本文最后引用了保罗·策兰的一句话,即语言获得了自己的存在,诗歌中出现了一些存在主义的意义,这篇文章说明了解释依赖于认知和感官过程的成功相互作用,这使得批评介于审美分析和语境化之间,以及隐喻性或文学性地使用语言图像之间。最后,它建议将审美批评视为一种评估实际创作过程及其结果的方法,就好像它们参与了自己的“对话”一样。因此,口译可以看作是一个产生自己的动态和程序的过程。诗学(poetics),无论是与它的对象有关,还是以并置的形式。如果是后者,则“解释”获得更多独特性的可能性更大。 然而,最终,解释的(准表演的)质量取决于它的风格特征,使用的语言的充分性和概念的严谨性,而不忽视它的基本功能,即使艺术作品与接受者之间以及接受者之间进行对话。
{"title":"Poetik der Kritik – Ästhetik des Deutens","authors":"R. Görner","doi":"10.1515/jlt-2020-0003","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/jlt-2020-0003","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract Some of the mainly unchartered territories in literary criticism are the implications of Susan Sontag’s frontal attack on traditional hermeneutical practices in Against Interpretation (1969). This contribution to investigations into the modes of interpretation attempts to draw constructive consequences from this provocation and investigate the notion of a ›poetics of criticism‹ emanating into what can be called the ›aesthetics of interpretation‹. In so doing, it explores the Romantic backdrop of this discourse through examining Friedrich Schlegel’s plea for a ›poetization‹ of critique and his demand to turn critical approaches into aesthetic, if not artistic, acts. Then, these reflections examine notions of perception or Anschauung as a cornerstone of comprehension; discuss poetic renderings of thought with Nietzsche, who epitomizes the fusion of reflection and aesthetic production; single out one of Gottfried Benn’s early poems (»Kreislauf«) as an object for putting aesthetic interpretation into practice given the specific character of this Expressionistic text; and, finally, assess elements of theories of recognition in terms of aesthetic practice with specific reference to a paragraph in early Adorno, which highlights cognitive transformation processes as matters of aesthetic experience. Thus, this essay illustrates the interrelationship between critical theory and practice as an aesthetic act, which takes into account the significance of Sontag’s challenge, exemplifying the necessity of finding a language register that can claim to strive towards adequacy in relation to the (artistic) object of criticism without compromising analytical rigour. The argument developed in this contribution towards an aesthetics of interpretation begins with a critical appreciation of various forms and modes of criticism in literature and other aspects of artistic expression. It centres on the significance of the dialogue as an explorative means of critical discourse, ranging from Friedrich Schlegel to Hugo von Hofmannsthal and indeed Hans Magnus Enzensberger. With the (fictive) dialogue as an instrument of aesthetic judgement, ›experience‹ entered the stage of literary criticism negotiating ambivalences and considering alternative points of view often generated from the texts under consideration. In terms of the ambivalences mentioned above, this investigation into the nature of criticism considers the notion of criticism as a form of art and an extrapolation of aesthetic reason as propagated already by Henry Kames, once even quoted by Hegel in connection with the establishing of a rationale for the critical appreciation of artistic products. It discusses the interplay of distance from, and empathy with, objects of aesthetic criticism asking to what extent the act of interpretation (Wolfgang Iser) can acquire a creative momentum of its own without distorting its true mission, namely to assess the characteristics and aesthetic qualities of specific (poet","PeriodicalId":42872,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Literary Theory","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2020-02-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1515/jlt-2020-0003","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"46494116","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Aesthetic Appreciation and the Dependence Between Deep and Surface Interpretation 审美与深层解读与表层解读的依赖
IF 0.2 Pub Date : 2020-02-28 DOI: 10.1515/jlt-2020-0006
Bartosz Stopel
Abstract The article traces the relationship between what is called surface, aesthetic interpretation and deep, semantic, theory-driven interpretation of literature. The former is identified with how interpretation is typically understood in analytic philosophy of art, whereas the latter as belonging to continental literary theory, thus framing the discussion within the relevant debates that the two eminent philosophical schools engage in. Specifically, the article argues in favor of a number of claims. It discusses the notion of surface interpretation, understood as the informed practice involved in general attention to a literary work with an aim of attaining an aesthetically rewarding experience (appreciation). Surface interpretation locates a literary work in a specific art-historical context and at minimum acknowledges the author’s categorial intentions pertinent to genre, general aims and representational content of the work. The article also argues against the notion that appreciation, which is supposed to be the main aim of surface interpretation, is purely perceptual (Carroll, Lamarque) and that consequently aesthetic experience does not involve affective experiences. Grounding appreciation in affective experiences (Levinson) leads me to acknowledge an important continuity between fully formed aesthetic experience and more instinctive or »effortless« ways of attending to a work, such as when one »just enjoys« the emotions afforded by, say, a horror story rather than with full aesthetic attention to the work, where the affective component dominates, but which are less structured to be properly called aesthetic within the conceptual framework I offer here. As a result, I divide the pleasures of attending to an artwork into the instinctive, hedonic ones and the properly aesthetic ones, which both constitute two basic modes of reading. The aesthetic mode is not fully separate from the hedonic one, but on the contrary, by tapping directly into the hardwired human cognitive-affective architecture, it provides a general framework and parameters for the emergence of the higher-order aesthetic mode where more prominence is given to art-historical knowledge and more attention to the design and form/content interrelation. Importantly, aesthetic mode does not operate with the absence of the hedonic one, though they can simultaneously produce different evaluations (e. g. hedonically positive, aesthetically/artistically negative). The two modes could be said to have distinct model readers with corresponding levels of competence. The hedonic reader, as opposed to the aesthetic one, would be largely oblivious to art-historical contexts and would be more selective in terms of attention to the work, relying on direct affect-triggering textual cues. Interpretive effort would be reduced, too. I also discuss my model with reference to the psycho-historical framework for the study of art appreciation as developed by Bullot and Reber which attempts to explain
如果理论驱动的解释不付出表面解释的代价,它可能会有缺陷或被拉长。其次,我认为表面和深层的解读都是根据价值最大化原则(戴维斯)进行的,这可以凌驾于作者对作品意义细节的意图之上。在深度解读中使用特定的理论框架是非习惯模式隔离原则的延伸,通过尝试识别更多增加作品复杂性的模式,同时忠实于作品的基本内容,有助于增强作品的体验。采取语义阅读的立场已经意味着采取潜在的美学立场,更遥远的是,采取享乐的立场。最后,理论驱动的解读形成了第三种阅读模式,这种模式从部分受限的审美模式中产生了一个相应的更有能力的模范读者。
{"title":"Aesthetic Appreciation and the Dependence Between Deep and Surface Interpretation","authors":"Bartosz Stopel","doi":"10.1515/jlt-2020-0006","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/jlt-2020-0006","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract The article traces the relationship between what is called surface, aesthetic interpretation and deep, semantic, theory-driven interpretation of literature. The former is identified with how interpretation is typically understood in analytic philosophy of art, whereas the latter as belonging to continental literary theory, thus framing the discussion within the relevant debates that the two eminent philosophical schools engage in. Specifically, the article argues in favor of a number of claims. It discusses the notion of surface interpretation, understood as the informed practice involved in general attention to a literary work with an aim of attaining an aesthetically rewarding experience (appreciation). Surface interpretation locates a literary work in a specific art-historical context and at minimum acknowledges the author’s categorial intentions pertinent to genre, general aims and representational content of the work. The article also argues against the notion that appreciation, which is supposed to be the main aim of surface interpretation, is purely perceptual (Carroll, Lamarque) and that consequently aesthetic experience does not involve affective experiences. Grounding appreciation in affective experiences (Levinson) leads me to acknowledge an important continuity between fully formed aesthetic experience and more instinctive or »effortless« ways of attending to a work, such as when one »just enjoys« the emotions afforded by, say, a horror story rather than with full aesthetic attention to the work, where the affective component dominates, but which are less structured to be properly called aesthetic within the conceptual framework I offer here. As a result, I divide the pleasures of attending to an artwork into the instinctive, hedonic ones and the properly aesthetic ones, which both constitute two basic modes of reading. The aesthetic mode is not fully separate from the hedonic one, but on the contrary, by tapping directly into the hardwired human cognitive-affective architecture, it provides a general framework and parameters for the emergence of the higher-order aesthetic mode where more prominence is given to art-historical knowledge and more attention to the design and form/content interrelation. Importantly, aesthetic mode does not operate with the absence of the hedonic one, though they can simultaneously produce different evaluations (e. g. hedonically positive, aesthetically/artistically negative). The two modes could be said to have distinct model readers with corresponding levels of competence. The hedonic reader, as opposed to the aesthetic one, would be largely oblivious to art-historical contexts and would be more selective in terms of attention to the work, relying on direct affect-triggering textual cues. Interpretive effort would be reduced, too. I also discuss my model with reference to the psycho-historical framework for the study of art appreciation as developed by Bullot and Reber which attempts to explain ","PeriodicalId":42872,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Literary Theory","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2020-02-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1515/jlt-2020-0006","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"49132002","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
Historisierung des Diskurses und Potenzierung ästhetischer Erfahrungen in der Literatur der (Post-)Moderne 文学作品著作史诗化及美学体验的潜力
IF 0.2 Pub Date : 2020-02-28 DOI: 10.1515/jlt-2020-0002
Corinna Dziudzia
Abstract The paper is based on the assumption that modern art centralises aesthetic experience in a specific way, why it as well be may regarded – in contrast to the rather forced interpretation of art already opposed by Susan Sontag (Sontag 2001, 10) – as an appropriate mode for encountering art. However, the theoretical discourse on aesthetic experience is characterised by opposite poles, which will be examined in the first part of this paper. On the one hand, there is the utopian conception around 1800, in which the reflection on aesthetic experience originally is rooted, in Friedrich Schiller’s On the Aesthetic Education of Man (cf. Noetzel 2006, 198) or Friedrich Schlegel’s imaginations of a life in art in Lucinde (cf. Dziudzia 2015, 38sqq.). On the other hand, the reflections in the German discourse at the beginning of the 20th century are marked in a conspicuously negative way, which can still be seen until the 1980s. In the theoretical first part of the essay, a few cursory positions on the ›problem of the aesthetic human being‹ will be considered initially, which reject aesthetic views in everyday life and evaluate such tendencies as forms of social decay. Concerned about morality on the surface, these positions indeed aim at criticising individual lifestyles in a modern world, which, in particular, are opposed to conservative and collectivist ideas of society and morality. These discourse positions, which are ultimately ideologically grounded, then lead to the deliberate reflections on aesthetic experience, as they unfold most notably from the 1970s onwards, where they form the implicit background. As will be shown, the explicitly negative evaluation expressed in the earlier positions then shapes the assessments of aesthetic experience of Hans-Robert Jauß (cf. Jauß 2007), Peter Bürger (cf. Bürger 1977) and Rüdiger Bubner (cf. Bubner 1989) as a fundamental, rather implicit scepticism. For the most part, their positions seem to make it impossible to think of the aesthetic experience as enrichment or to evaluate it positively, as is common in the US-American discourse, for instance. The latter stance, which is, in essence, initiated by John Dewey and his consciously non-strict separation between art and everyday life as well as his decidedly anti-elitist understanding of art and aesthetics, is more in keeping with the utopian concepts of around 1800. However, his writings only find late distribution in Germany (cf. Dewey 1980). In contrast to Dewey’s position – and Susan Sontag’s explicit rejection of the interpretation as a violent act and the omittance of the sensual experience of the artwork (Sontag 2001) – the critical condemnation of aesthetic experience, which ultimately remains unfounded in the German discourse (because of its implicit ideological origin), now appears challenged. In fact, attentive observation in an aesthetic stance becomes part of the aesthetic programme in modern art across the board (cf. Dziudzia 2015b). Bürger r
摘要本文基于这样一种假设,即现代艺术以一种特定的方式集中了审美体验,为什么它也可以被视为一种合适的遭遇艺术的模式——与苏珊·桑塔格(Susan Sontag,2001,10)已经反对的对艺术的强制性解释相反,这将在本文的第一部分中进行研究。一方面,1800年左右的乌托邦概念,对审美体验的反思最初植根于弗里德里希·席勒的《论人的美育》(参见Noetzel 2006198)或弗里德里希·斯莱格尔的《卢辛德的艺术生活想象》(参见Dziudzia 201538平方克)。另一方面,20世纪初德国话语中的反思以一种明显的消极方式出现,这种消极方式直到20世纪80年代仍然可见。在本文的理论第一部分,我们将初步考虑美学人的›问题的一些粗略立场,这些立场拒绝日常生活中的美学观点,并将这些倾向视为社会腐朽的形式。这些立场表面上关注道德,实际上旨在批评现代世界中的个人生活方式,尤其是反对保守和集体主义的社会和道德观。这些话语立场最终是以意识形态为基础的,然后导致对审美体验的刻意反思,因为它们从20世纪70年代开始最为明显地展开,在那里它们形成了隐含的背景。如图所示,早期立场中表达的明确的负面评价将Hans-Robert Jauß(参见Jauł2007)、Peter Bürger(参见Bürger 1977)和Rüdiger Bubner(参见Bubner 1989)对美学体验的评估塑造为一种基本的、相当含蓄的怀疑。在大多数情况下,他们的立场似乎使人们无法将审美体验视为丰富或积极评价,例如,在美国话语中很常见。后一种立场,本质上是由约翰·杜威发起的,他有意识地不严格地将艺术与日常生活分开,以及他对艺术和美学的绝对反精英主义理解,更符合1800年左右的乌托邦概念。然而,他的著作在德国的发行时间较晚(参见杜威1980)。与杜威的立场——以及苏珊·桑塔格明确拒绝将这一解释视为暴力行为,并忽略了艺术作品的感官体验(桑塔格,2001年)——相反,对审美体验的批判谴责,最终在德国话语中仍然是没有根据的(因为其隐含的意识形态起源),现在似乎受到了挑战。事实上,以美学立场进行的专注观察已成为现代艺术美学计划的一部分(参见Dziudzia 2015b)。Bürger对此进行了反思,并提出了一个富有成效的建议——尤其是在对Marcel Proust《寻找逝去的时间》的研究中——将›审美感知(他称之为)作为一种文学技巧来把握。在他的概念中,Bürger将媒体称为美学体验的一个特定的›投影区域,尤其是在1900年前后的文学中。继比尔格之后,现代文学中的›想象时尚(参见Schmitz-Emans 2001)被进一步认为是›指数化的美学体验,这种体验不仅在1900年左右形成,而且在最近的文学中也形成。因此,在论文的第二部分,以及对2007年出版的德国当代小说《月亮与少女》的示范阅读中,我们将展示审美体验是如何找到复杂形式的。在人物和叙述者层面的相互作用中,特别是在借助于其中所观察到的媒介电影的情况下,想象的时尚的具体塑造中,美学经验的理论概念的矛盾心理暗示了这一点。
{"title":"Historisierung des Diskurses und Potenzierung ästhetischer Erfahrungen in der Literatur der (Post-)Moderne","authors":"Corinna Dziudzia","doi":"10.1515/jlt-2020-0002","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/jlt-2020-0002","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract The paper is based on the assumption that modern art centralises aesthetic experience in a specific way, why it as well be may regarded – in contrast to the rather forced interpretation of art already opposed by Susan Sontag (Sontag 2001, 10) – as an appropriate mode for encountering art. However, the theoretical discourse on aesthetic experience is characterised by opposite poles, which will be examined in the first part of this paper. On the one hand, there is the utopian conception around 1800, in which the reflection on aesthetic experience originally is rooted, in Friedrich Schiller’s On the Aesthetic Education of Man (cf. Noetzel 2006, 198) or Friedrich Schlegel’s imaginations of a life in art in Lucinde (cf. Dziudzia 2015, 38sqq.). On the other hand, the reflections in the German discourse at the beginning of the 20th century are marked in a conspicuously negative way, which can still be seen until the 1980s. In the theoretical first part of the essay, a few cursory positions on the ›problem of the aesthetic human being‹ will be considered initially, which reject aesthetic views in everyday life and evaluate such tendencies as forms of social decay. Concerned about morality on the surface, these positions indeed aim at criticising individual lifestyles in a modern world, which, in particular, are opposed to conservative and collectivist ideas of society and morality. These discourse positions, which are ultimately ideologically grounded, then lead to the deliberate reflections on aesthetic experience, as they unfold most notably from the 1970s onwards, where they form the implicit background. As will be shown, the explicitly negative evaluation expressed in the earlier positions then shapes the assessments of aesthetic experience of Hans-Robert Jauß (cf. Jauß 2007), Peter Bürger (cf. Bürger 1977) and Rüdiger Bubner (cf. Bubner 1989) as a fundamental, rather implicit scepticism. For the most part, their positions seem to make it impossible to think of the aesthetic experience as enrichment or to evaluate it positively, as is common in the US-American discourse, for instance. The latter stance, which is, in essence, initiated by John Dewey and his consciously non-strict separation between art and everyday life as well as his decidedly anti-elitist understanding of art and aesthetics, is more in keeping with the utopian concepts of around 1800. However, his writings only find late distribution in Germany (cf. Dewey 1980). In contrast to Dewey’s position – and Susan Sontag’s explicit rejection of the interpretation as a violent act and the omittance of the sensual experience of the artwork (Sontag 2001) – the critical condemnation of aesthetic experience, which ultimately remains unfounded in the German discourse (because of its implicit ideological origin), now appears challenged. In fact, attentive observation in an aesthetic stance becomes part of the aesthetic programme in modern art across the board (cf. Dziudzia 2015b). Bürger r","PeriodicalId":42872,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Literary Theory","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2020-02-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1515/jlt-2020-0002","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47318506","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Deduktive Schlüsse in der literaturwissenschaftlichen Praxis 文学实践中的演绎结论
IF 0.2 Pub Date : 2019-09-06 DOI: 10.1515/jlt-2019-0005
Stefan Descher
Abstract It is sometimes suggested that deductive reasoning has no place in literary studies, particularly when it comes to the justification of literary interpretations. The thesis is that deductive arguments (almost) never occur and deductive reasoning plays no or at most a marginal role in the actual practice of interpretation. In this essay I will argue that this thesis is false. Using counterexamples, it can be shown that deductive arguments are de facto used in the practice of literary interpretation. Although only an exemplary and not comprehensive investigation of argumentative practices in literary studies can be made here, it can also be made plausible that deductive arguments are not exceptions, but a normal, regularly encountered and legitimate phenomenon of this practice. Furthermore, it can be shown that the thesis criticized here is based on a too narrow understanding of deductive reasoning. Finally, I will argue that (from a methodological point of view) it would be an unnecessary restriction to exclude deductions from our methodological toolbox: to abandon deductive reasoning from the practice of interpretation would be tantamount to renouncing a useful method of justifying (and refuting) interpretive hypotheses. Therefore, a fundamental methodological scepticism about deductive reasoning is unfounded. The essay is structured as follows: First, I will present a current example of how the sceptical attitude towards deductions in literary studies is motivated (Section 1). I will show that the concept of deduction underlying this scepticism is usually based on the assumption that deductive arguments contain ›general rules‹ or ›law-like assertions‹ in their premises. Second, I will confront the concept of deduction assumed there with the understanding of deductive arguments as it is usually assumed in logic (Section 2). It will become apparent that a conception of deductive arguments based on general rules or law-like assertions is (though not false) too narrow. After a short caveat concerning the reconstruction of ›real‹ arguments in general (Section 3), I will present some examples of deductive arguments in interpretations of literary texts (Section 4). These arguments have the logical form of arguments from modus ponens, modus tollens and disjunctive syllogism. The examples not only show that deductive reasoning actually occurs in the practice of literary interpretation, but also make it plausible that deductive arguments are an unproblematic and legitimate method of justifying and/or refuting interpretations. After considering what causes may have led to the dissemination of the thesis that deductions do not occur in practice (Section 5), I conclude with a plea to accept deductive arguments as a legitimate tool of justification among many others (Section 6).
摘要有时有人认为,演绎推理在文学研究中没有立足之地,尤其是在文学解释的正当性方面。这篇论文认为,演绎论点(几乎)从未发生过,演绎推理在实际的解释实践中不起作用,或者最多起到边缘作用。在这篇文章中,我认为这篇论文是错误的。通过反例,可以表明演绎论点在文学阐释实践中是事实上使用的。虽然这里只能对文学研究中的议论文实践进行一次典型而非全面的调查,但也可以说,演绎论点并非例外,而是这种实践中一种正常、经常遇到的合法现象。此外,可以表明,本文所批评的是基于对演绎推理过于狭隘的理解。最后,我认为(从方法论的角度来看)将推论排除在我们的方法工具箱之外是不必要的限制:从解释实践中放弃演绎推理就等于放弃了一种证明(和反驳)解释假设的有用方法。因此,对演绎推理的基本方法论怀疑是没有根据的。本文的结构如下:首先,我将举一个当前的例子,说明文学研究中对推理的怀疑态度是如何被激发的(第1节)。我将表明,这种怀疑论背后的演绎概念通常是基于这样的假设,即演绎论点在其前提中包含›一般规则或›类似法律的断言。其次,我将面对在那里假设的演绎概念,理解演绎论点,因为它通常是在逻辑中假设的(第2节)。很明显,基于一般规则或类似法律的断言的演绎论点的概念过于狭隘(尽管不是错误的)。在对›真实论点的一般重建提出简短的警告后(第3节),我将介绍一些演绎论点在文学文本解释中的例子(第4节)。这些论点具有推理推理、推理推理和析取三段论的逻辑形式。这些例子不仅表明演绎推理实际上发生在文学解释的实践中,而且使人们相信演绎论证是一种证明和/或反驳解释的无问题和合法的方法。在考虑了哪些原因可能导致推论在实践中没有发生这一论点的传播后(第5节),我最后恳求接受演绎论点作为一种合法的辩护工具(第6节)。
{"title":"Deduktive Schlüsse in der literaturwissenschaftlichen Praxis","authors":"Stefan Descher","doi":"10.1515/jlt-2019-0005","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/jlt-2019-0005","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract It is sometimes suggested that deductive reasoning has no place in literary studies, particularly when it comes to the justification of literary interpretations. The thesis is that deductive arguments (almost) never occur and deductive reasoning plays no or at most a marginal role in the actual practice of interpretation. In this essay I will argue that this thesis is false. Using counterexamples, it can be shown that deductive arguments are de facto used in the practice of literary interpretation. Although only an exemplary and not comprehensive investigation of argumentative practices in literary studies can be made here, it can also be made plausible that deductive arguments are not exceptions, but a normal, regularly encountered and legitimate phenomenon of this practice. Furthermore, it can be shown that the thesis criticized here is based on a too narrow understanding of deductive reasoning. Finally, I will argue that (from a methodological point of view) it would be an unnecessary restriction to exclude deductions from our methodological toolbox: to abandon deductive reasoning from the practice of interpretation would be tantamount to renouncing a useful method of justifying (and refuting) interpretive hypotheses. Therefore, a fundamental methodological scepticism about deductive reasoning is unfounded. The essay is structured as follows: First, I will present a current example of how the sceptical attitude towards deductions in literary studies is motivated (Section 1). I will show that the concept of deduction underlying this scepticism is usually based on the assumption that deductive arguments contain ›general rules‹ or ›law-like assertions‹ in their premises. Second, I will confront the concept of deduction assumed there with the understanding of deductive arguments as it is usually assumed in logic (Section 2). It will become apparent that a conception of deductive arguments based on general rules or law-like assertions is (though not false) too narrow. After a short caveat concerning the reconstruction of ›real‹ arguments in general (Section 3), I will present some examples of deductive arguments in interpretations of literary texts (Section 4). These arguments have the logical form of arguments from modus ponens, modus tollens and disjunctive syllogism. The examples not only show that deductive reasoning actually occurs in the practice of literary interpretation, but also make it plausible that deductive arguments are an unproblematic and legitimate method of justifying and/or refuting interpretations. After considering what causes may have led to the dissemination of the thesis that deductions do not occur in practice (Section 5), I conclude with a plea to accept deductive arguments as a legitimate tool of justification among many others (Section 6).","PeriodicalId":42872,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Literary Theory","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2019-09-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1515/jlt-2019-0005","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48453043","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Fiktive Figuren als Träger von Wissen und als epistemische Autoritäten 作为知识载体和认识权威的虚构人物
IF 0.2 Pub Date : 2019-09-06 DOI: 10.1515/jlt-2019-0006
Rico Hauswald
Abstract This essay examines the question of whether and under what conditions a fictitious character can be an epistemic authority for (real) readers; more precisely: it asks whether and under what conditions readers can acquire (propositional) knowledge from the character, thus learning something from it. In answering this question, the essay brings together two debates that have so far hardly been related to each other: an epistemological debate on the concept of epistemic authority and a literary-theoretical debate on aesthetic cognitivism, i. e., the discourse about what can be learned from the reception of fictional texts. In order for a person to be an epistemic authority for another person, two conditions must be met: 1) the first person must have an advantage in knowledge over the second person that the second person recognizes and acknowledges as such; and 2) the second person must have appropriate access to this knowledge. In order to clarify to what extent a fictitious character and a real reader can be related in this way, I first examine what it means to attribute knowledge to a fictitious character. To do so, I suggest the following analysis: In story S, character C knows that p if and only if C believes in S that p; p is true in S; and C is justified in S to believe that p (this suggestion, based on the classical definition of knowledge, can easily be adapted for other suggested analyses: all that is required is that all conditions in the analysis – whatever they might be – lie inside the scope of the fiction operator). Furthermore, a knowledge attribution of the form »In S, C knows whether p« is true if and only if in S, C knows that p or knows that not-p. On the question of the correctness-conditions for knowledge attributions of the form »In S, C knows that p« and »In S, C knows whether p«, I will then enter the debate about fictional truths. This is necessary for two reasons. On the one hand, the attribution of knowledge is nothing but the assertion of a particular fictional truth. And on the other hand, an attribution of knowledge involves another fictional fact, namely the fact p (which I call the »underlying fact«). The view that is largely held in the discussion about fictional truth following Lewis is that what is true in a story does not result solely from the explicit assertions in the text, but also from plausible consequences [Plausibilitätsschlüssen] that we can be further justified in drawing. More precisely, the following possibilities arise for both facts – the underlying fact as well as the attribution of knowledge: Either the text explicitly contains a reference to the fact. Or it does not contain such an explicit reference, but the question of whether the fact obtains can still be answered on the basis of plausibility conclusions. Or there are no explicit references and plausibility conclusions cannot be drawn. In this case, there is a point of indeterminacy. These distinctions result in a number of possible co
摘要:本文探讨了一个虚构人物是否以及在什么条件下可以成为(真实)读者的认知权威的问题;更准确地说:它问读者是否以及在什么条件下可以从人物身上获得(命题)知识,从而从中学到一些东西。为了回答这个问题,本文汇集了迄今为止几乎没有相互关联的两场辩论:关于认识论权威概念的认识论辩论和关于审美认知主义的文学理论辩论。即关于从接受虚构文本中学到什么的论述。为了让一个人成为另一个人的知识权威,必须满足两个条件:1)第一个人必须在知识方面比第二个人有优势,第二个人承认并承认这一点;第二个人必须有适当的途径获得这些知识。为了弄清楚虚拟人物和真实读者在多大程度上可以通过这种方式联系起来,我首先考察将知识归因于虚拟人物的含义。为此,我建议进行以下分析:在故事S中,角色C知道p当且仅当C相信S;p在S中为真;而C在S中有理由相信p(这个基于经典知识定义的建议,可以很容易地适用于其他建议的分析:所需要的只是分析中的所有条件-无论它们是什么-都在虚构算子的范围内)。更进一步,形式的知识归因"在S中,C知道p是否"为真当且仅当在S中,C知道p或知道非p。关于"在S中,C知道p "和"在S中,C是否知道p "这种形式的知识归因的正确性条件,我将进入关于虚构真理的辩论。这是必要的,原因有二。一方面,知识的归属只不过是对特定的虚构真理的断言。另一方面,知识的归因涉及到另一个虚构的事实,即事实p(我称之为"潜在事实")。在刘易斯之后关于虚构真相的讨论中,大部分人持有的观点是,故事中的真实并不仅仅来自文本中明确的断言,而且还来自我们可以进一步证明其合理性的合理结果[Plausibilitätsschlüssen]。更准确地说,这两种事实——潜在的事实和知识的归属——都有以下两种可能:要么文本明确地包含了对事实的引用。或者它不包含这样一个明确的指称,但事实是否成立的问题仍然可以根据似是而非的结论来回答。或者没有明确的参考文献,无法得出合理的结论。在这种情况下,有一个不确定点。这些区别导致了与不同类型的情况相对应的许多可能的组合,我将对其中一些有趣的实例进行更详细的研究。一个特别值得注意的例子是,当文本中有一个关于潜在事实的不确定点时,正如我用一个例子说明的那样,这并不排除知识可以归因于与所讨论的命题有关的角色的可能性。这种说法通常是关于不确定的段落,甚至连上帝都不知道所讨论的事实是否得到了——这是正确的。因此,如果我们有权将所讨论的知识归因于一个人物,这表明虚构的人物不仅可以比读者或作者知道得更多,甚至比上帝知道得更多。这种情况也说明,更多的知识并不一定要与更多的知识权威齐头并进。对于读者来说,不确定的段落仍然是不可解的,读者在这方面无法从人物身上学到任何东西。这让我想到了一个问题:读者在什么条件下可以从一个角色身上学到一些读者所不具备的知识。假设一个虚构的角色和一个真实的读者之间存在着某种知识的转移,这个观点的一个基本问题是,两者属于不同的本体论领域,也就是说,读者是真实的,而这个角色只是虚构的。如果一个角色要成为读者的认知权威,这将是一个跨虚构的认知权威的例子,它必须与“普通”的认知权威、虚构的认知权威和虚构的真理的认知权威区分开来。 我建议使用假装理论和扩展假装算子来分析跨虚构的认知权威:当读者发现自己处于扩展假装中并假装是虚构世界的一部分时,他们至少具有想象能力与角色互动,因此角色可以成为读者想象的认知权威。我还讨论了认知主义的争论,并认为一个角色的(虚构的)知识不仅会影响虚构的内部,也会影响虚构的外部对象和真理。认知主义认为读者可以从阅读虚构文本中获得关于现实的命题性知识,对此,一个主要的反对意见是,虚构文本不是可靠的来源,读者通过阅读可能形成的信念不能被证明是正确的。我反对这种反对意见,并认为读者也可以通过将知识归因于虚构人物,甚至从故事中人物的言语行为中获得关于现实的知识。最后,我将处理一个可能的反对意见,即角色的认知权威完全依赖于作者的认知权威,这里的反对意见是,如果读者学到一些东西,实际上是从作者那里学到的。相反,我认为虚构的人物可以获得一种独立的认识权威,这种权威不能被简化为作者的权威。
{"title":"Fiktive Figuren als Träger von Wissen und als epistemische Autoritäten","authors":"Rico Hauswald","doi":"10.1515/jlt-2019-0006","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/jlt-2019-0006","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract This essay examines the question of whether and under what conditions a fictitious character can be an epistemic authority for (real) readers; more precisely: it asks whether and under what conditions readers can acquire (propositional) knowledge from the character, thus learning something from it. In answering this question, the essay brings together two debates that have so far hardly been related to each other: an epistemological debate on the concept of epistemic authority and a literary-theoretical debate on aesthetic cognitivism, i. e., the discourse about what can be learned from the reception of fictional texts. In order for a person to be an epistemic authority for another person, two conditions must be met: 1) the first person must have an advantage in knowledge over the second person that the second person recognizes and acknowledges as such; and 2) the second person must have appropriate access to this knowledge. In order to clarify to what extent a fictitious character and a real reader can be related in this way, I first examine what it means to attribute knowledge to a fictitious character. To do so, I suggest the following analysis: In story S, character C knows that p if and only if C believes in S that p; p is true in S; and C is justified in S to believe that p (this suggestion, based on the classical definition of knowledge, can easily be adapted for other suggested analyses: all that is required is that all conditions in the analysis – whatever they might be – lie inside the scope of the fiction operator). Furthermore, a knowledge attribution of the form »In S, C knows whether p« is true if and only if in S, C knows that p or knows that not-p. On the question of the correctness-conditions for knowledge attributions of the form »In S, C knows that p« and »In S, C knows whether p«, I will then enter the debate about fictional truths. This is necessary for two reasons. On the one hand, the attribution of knowledge is nothing but the assertion of a particular fictional truth. And on the other hand, an attribution of knowledge involves another fictional fact, namely the fact p (which I call the »underlying fact«). The view that is largely held in the discussion about fictional truth following Lewis is that what is true in a story does not result solely from the explicit assertions in the text, but also from plausible consequences [Plausibilitätsschlüssen] that we can be further justified in drawing. More precisely, the following possibilities arise for both facts – the underlying fact as well as the attribution of knowledge: Either the text explicitly contains a reference to the fact. Or it does not contain such an explicit reference, but the question of whether the fact obtains can still be answered on the basis of plausibility conclusions. Or there are no explicit references and plausibility conclusions cannot be drawn. In this case, there is a point of indeterminacy. These distinctions result in a number of possible co","PeriodicalId":42872,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Literary Theory","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2019-09-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1515/jlt-2019-0006","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"48367980","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Gattungsgeschichte und ihr Gattungsbegriff am Beispiel der Novellen 瞧见了就知道
IF 0.2 Pub Date : 2019-09-06 DOI: 10.1515/jlt-2019-0009
Juliane Schröter
Abstract The discussion of genre theory since the middle of the twentieth century has been marked, among other things, by two conflicting endeavors: on the one hand, there are attempts to semantically regulate generic terms for the purpose of a clear scientific language by defining them as types of texts (cf. Fricke 2010, Fishelov 1991, Zymner 2003); and on the other hand, there are attempts to accustom literary studies to the factual indeterminacy of generic terms and to comprehend this indeterminacy by adapting Wittgenstein’s concept of family resemblance or the semantics of prototypes (cf. Strube 1986, Hempfer 2010a). The essay is intended to show that both positions – that of strictly regulating and of merely descriptively comprehending practice – as they have been advocated so far hinder the foundation of genre-historical research. This essay aims to more precisely formulate the productive ideas from both positions and thus to provide a robust foundation for the historical study of genres. This foundation is to be structured by two core questions that until now have not been clearly separated: first, how one ought to define, before and during historiographic and empirical work, the concept of the genre that is to be examined; and second, how one can synthesize the historically changing semantics of a genre at the end of this empirical work. Answering these two questions becomes a problem when one is dealing with historically discontinuous and heterogeneous genres. This essay pursues this problem using the example of novella history, because research here is particularly divided as to how the concept of the novella can best be understood. The guiding idea of the essay is to reverse the usual sequence of steps: in genre theory, the dogma is often advocated that the concept of genre must be defined a priori, i. e., before the investigation begins and independently of empirical work. The first section of this essay rejects this dogma and recommends that we make the use of the concept of a specific genre dependent on the concrete epistemological interest of the investigation. With the help of an argument by Kendall L. Walton, the essay shows that aesthetic innovations and the historical development of literary procedures can only be understood if a hermeneutic interest in the references of individual texts to historically established generic expectations is at the forefront of the investigation (cf. Walton 1970). The essay recommends that generic historiography serve this hermeneutic interest. It aims to answer the first core question of how the concept of genre ought be used before and during historiographic work for two central procedures: for reconstruction from, on the one hand, historical poetics (second section); and, on the other hand, from text groups (third section). In both procedures, the thesis is that the concept of the genre to be examined should not be regulated before or independently of empirical work by defining a concept of a t
摘要二十世纪中叶以来对体裁理论的讨论主要有两个相互冲突的努力:一方面,为了清晰的科学语言,试图通过将通用术语定义为文本类型来对其进行语义调节(参见Fricke 2010,Fishelov 1991,Zymner 2003);另一方面,有人试图使文学研究习惯于通用术语的事实不确定性,并通过改编维特根斯坦的家族相似性概念或原型语义来理解这种不确定性(参见Strube 1986,Hempfer 2010a)。这篇文章旨在表明,迄今为止所倡导的两种立场——严格规范实践和仅仅描述性理解实践——都阻碍了流派历史研究的基础。本文旨在从这两个角度更准确地阐述富有成效的思想,从而为体裁的历史研究提供坚实的基础。这一基础将由两个核心问题构成,这两个问题到目前为止还没有明确分开:首先,在史学和实证工作之前和期间,人们应该如何定义要研究的流派的概念;第二,如何在这部经验著作的结尾综合一个流派的历史变化语义。当处理历史上不连续和异质的流派时,回答这两个问题就成了一个问题。本文以中篇小说史为例来探讨这个问题,因为这里的研究对于如何最好地理解中篇小说的概念存在特别的分歧。这篇文章的指导思想是颠倒通常的步骤顺序:在体裁理论中,经常提倡必须先验地定义体裁的概念。 e.在调查开始之前,独立于实证工作。本文的第一部分拒绝接受这一教条,并建议我们根据调查的具体认识论兴趣来使用特定类型的概念。在Kendall L.Walton的一个论点的帮助下,这篇文章表明,只有当对个别文本引用历史上确立的一般期望的解释学兴趣处于调查的前沿时,才能理解美学创新和文学程序的历史发展(参见Walton 1970)。本文建议通识史学服务于这种解释学的兴趣。它旨在回答第一个核心问题,即在史学工作之前和期间,应该如何使用类型的概念,以实现两个核心程序:一方面从历史诗学重建(第二部分);另一方面,来自文本组(第三节)。在这两个程序中,论文都认为,在实证工作之前或独立于实证工作,不应通过定义文本类型的概念来规范待审查类型的概念。因此,在从文本组重建一般期望的情况下,依赖于所谓归纳程序的变体。为了消除归纳法在方法论上的不足,本文从数量论的角度对归纳法进行了重新表述,使归纳法符合基本要求。归纳程序的问题在于,在流派名称的历史使用不一致的情况下,它不适合从文本组中推断出一般特征。这个问题在中篇小说中尤为突出,因为历史上被称为中篇小说的文本似乎只有一个共同点,即它们被称为中篇小说。归纳程序的集合理论重新表述应该允许通过使用分类谓词来重建历史上与流派名称相关的一般期望。然而,这一程序的目的并不是在史学工作之前确定流派的概念。相反,目的是通过交叉将在相关历史情况下作为中篇小说传播的文本集与分类集联系起来。这些交叉点中的每一个——例如,被称为中篇小说的文本和虚构期刊散文的交叉点——都可以根据定义集合的相关文本特征来描述(例如,虚构期刊散文)。重要的是,不要像通常所做的那样,将这种交集概括地定义为中篇小说。这样的定义将导致相应类型的分类概念,而这反过来将不再适合理解通用标签的历史使用,从而不适合理解历史文学传播中类型的语义。
{"title":"Gattungsgeschichte und ihr Gattungsbegriff am Beispiel der Novellen","authors":"Juliane Schröter","doi":"10.1515/jlt-2019-0009","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/jlt-2019-0009","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract The discussion of genre theory since the middle of the twentieth century has been marked, among other things, by two conflicting endeavors: on the one hand, there are attempts to semantically regulate generic terms for the purpose of a clear scientific language by defining them as types of texts (cf. Fricke 2010, Fishelov 1991, Zymner 2003); and on the other hand, there are attempts to accustom literary studies to the factual indeterminacy of generic terms and to comprehend this indeterminacy by adapting Wittgenstein’s concept of family resemblance or the semantics of prototypes (cf. Strube 1986, Hempfer 2010a). The essay is intended to show that both positions – that of strictly regulating and of merely descriptively comprehending practice – as they have been advocated so far hinder the foundation of genre-historical research. This essay aims to more precisely formulate the productive ideas from both positions and thus to provide a robust foundation for the historical study of genres. This foundation is to be structured by two core questions that until now have not been clearly separated: first, how one ought to define, before and during historiographic and empirical work, the concept of the genre that is to be examined; and second, how one can synthesize the historically changing semantics of a genre at the end of this empirical work. Answering these two questions becomes a problem when one is dealing with historically discontinuous and heterogeneous genres. This essay pursues this problem using the example of novella history, because research here is particularly divided as to how the concept of the novella can best be understood. The guiding idea of the essay is to reverse the usual sequence of steps: in genre theory, the dogma is often advocated that the concept of genre must be defined a priori, i. e., before the investigation begins and independently of empirical work. The first section of this essay rejects this dogma and recommends that we make the use of the concept of a specific genre dependent on the concrete epistemological interest of the investigation. With the help of an argument by Kendall L. Walton, the essay shows that aesthetic innovations and the historical development of literary procedures can only be understood if a hermeneutic interest in the references of individual texts to historically established generic expectations is at the forefront of the investigation (cf. Walton 1970). The essay recommends that generic historiography serve this hermeneutic interest. It aims to answer the first core question of how the concept of genre ought be used before and during historiographic work for two central procedures: for reconstruction from, on the one hand, historical poetics (second section); and, on the other hand, from text groups (third section). In both procedures, the thesis is that the concept of the genre to be examined should not be regulated before or independently of empirical work by defining a concept of a t","PeriodicalId":42872,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Literary Theory","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2019-09-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1515/jlt-2019-0009","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"44443718","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3
On the Origin of the Epic Preterit 论史诗的起源
IF 0.2 Pub Date : 2019-09-06 DOI: 10.1515/jlt-2019-0008
Katja Mellmann
Abstract The use of past tense in narrative discourse at first glance seems to imply that the narrated events are lying in the past as compared to the act of narration. However, this intuitive notion was doubted by several scholars in the mid 20th century, among them Käte Hamburger, Harald Weinrich, Émile Benveniste, and Ann Banfield. This article investigates the temporal constitution of literary narratives from a perspective of the biological evolution of Human cognition. My analysis begins with Hamburger’s most disputed claim that in epic fiction the past tense »loses its grammatical function of designating what is past« and proceeds by testing a derived hypothesis against a cross-cultural sample of (mostly oral) folklore. Hamburger denied any temporal relation between the speaker and that which he speaks of, assuming instead a fictitious neverland in which the narrated events are situated and to which the preterit refers. If Hamburger’s model is correct, so the derived hypothesis goes, then the use of past tense in fictional narratives is merely a cultural convention, and different narrative traditions should expose different conventions. Indeed it can be shown that in other cultures stories are told in the present tense, in infinitive verb forms, or in forms indicating abstractness or remoteness. It can be followed that Hamburger was right at least in presuming that reference to the past is not a necessary constituent of verbal storytelling. Actually, instead of referring to the past, the epic preterit rather seems to indicate a change in the modality of speaking, thus adhering to the category of grammatical mood rather than tense. In some languages of oral cultures, however, this presumed mood shows up instead as a way of indicating the source of information. This kind of source information – fully grammaticalized in a quarter of the world’s languages – is called ›evidentiality‹ by linguists. In a phylogenetic perspective on the evolution of cognition, source information only becomes necessary with extended inferential and communicative capabilities and may thus have emerged as a cognitive tool in early humans when entering the ›cognitive niche‹. Evidentiality markers in language may thus be the linguistic reflex of a very ancient cognitive scope category in the innate architecture of the human mind, one which served to separate first-hand experience from reported knowledge. In oral storytelling, evidentiality is marked not only by specific verb forms but also by specific formulas (›they say‹/›it is said‹), intonations, or rhetorical devices. From this perspective, the phenomenon observed by Hamburger and others can be said to originate in the beginning of Tradition – that is, of verbal transmission of cultural knowledge. My hypothesis is that literary narratives in literate cultures still use this ancient cognitive scope operator of ›tradition‹ when employing the epic preterit. Admittedly, in literate cultures it often suffices to put »A n
摘要叙事性话语中过去时的使用乍一看似乎暗示着所叙述的事件与叙述行为相比是在过去。然而,这种直观的观念在20世纪中期受到了一些学者的质疑,其中包括Käte Hamburger, Harald Weinrich, Émile Benveniste和Ann Banfield。本文从人类认知的生物进化角度考察文学叙事的时间构成。我的分析从汉堡最有争议的主张开始,即在史诗小说中,过去时“失去了表示过去的语法功能”,然后通过对跨文化(主要是口头)民间传说样本的检验来验证一个衍生的假设。汉堡包否认说话者和他所说的事物之间有任何时间上的关系,而是假设一个虚构的梦幻岛,叙述的事件发生在那里,而偏爱者所指的是这个梦幻岛。如果Hamburger的模型是正确的,那么由此衍生出的假设就是,在小说叙事中使用过去时仅仅是一种文化惯例,不同的叙事传统应该暴露出不同的惯例。事实上,在其他文化中,故事是用现在时、动词不定式或表示抽象或遥远的形式讲述的。可以这样说,至少在假定对过去的提及不是口头讲故事的必要组成部分这一点上,Hamburger是正确的。实际上,史诗的先行词并不是指过去,而是指说话语气的变化,因此属于语法语气的范畴,而不是时态的范畴。然而,在一些口头文化的语言中,这种假定的情绪反而作为一种表明信息来源的方式出现。这种来源信息——被世界上四分之一的语言完全语法化——被语言学家称为“证据性”。从认知进化的系统发育角度来看,源信息只有在扩展推理和交流能力时才成为必要,因此可能在早期人类进入“认知生态位”时作为一种认知工具出现。因此,语言中的证据性标记可能是人类思维固有架构中一个非常古老的认知范围类别的语言反射,它有助于将第一手经验与报告的知识分开。在口述故事中,证据性不仅通过特定的动词形式,而且通过特定的公式(他们说/据说)、语调或修辞手段来标记。从这个角度来看,汉堡包和其他人观察到的现象可以说起源于传统的开始-即文化知识的口头传播。我的假设是,文学文化中的文学叙事在使用史诗偏好时仍然使用“传统”这个古老的认知范围算子。诚然,在文学文化中,为了表明叙事性小说的绝对差异性,在标题页上写上“作者”往往就足够了。然而,作者仍然采用了额外的手段来唤起一种“喃喃低语”的气氛——正如托马斯·曼(Thomas Mann)曾经所说的那样——这种气氛创造了一种印象,即在所讲述的个人故事背后有一个客观的传统世界。我以文学第一人称叙事为例,因为同叙事叙事——与汉堡的异叙事叙事的经典案例相反——显示了说话者和他所说的对象之间的连续时空关系,因此需要额外的手段或努力来表明第一手经验的普通世界和文学世界之间的断裂。由于Hamburger曾经将史诗般的偏好视为虚构的信号,所以我在论文的最后几段简要地讨论了虚构的概念。我认为“虚构性”是文学社会中较晚的文化概念,它与“传统”的认知范畴并不相同,但最终由于后者的存在而成为可能。
{"title":"On the Origin of the Epic Preterit","authors":"Katja Mellmann","doi":"10.1515/jlt-2019-0008","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1515/jlt-2019-0008","url":null,"abstract":"Abstract The use of past tense in narrative discourse at first glance seems to imply that the narrated events are lying in the past as compared to the act of narration. However, this intuitive notion was doubted by several scholars in the mid 20th century, among them Käte Hamburger, Harald Weinrich, Émile Benveniste, and Ann Banfield. This article investigates the temporal constitution of literary narratives from a perspective of the biological evolution of Human cognition. My analysis begins with Hamburger’s most disputed claim that in epic fiction the past tense »loses its grammatical function of designating what is past« and proceeds by testing a derived hypothesis against a cross-cultural sample of (mostly oral) folklore. Hamburger denied any temporal relation between the speaker and that which he speaks of, assuming instead a fictitious neverland in which the narrated events are situated and to which the preterit refers. If Hamburger’s model is correct, so the derived hypothesis goes, then the use of past tense in fictional narratives is merely a cultural convention, and different narrative traditions should expose different conventions. Indeed it can be shown that in other cultures stories are told in the present tense, in infinitive verb forms, or in forms indicating abstractness or remoteness. It can be followed that Hamburger was right at least in presuming that reference to the past is not a necessary constituent of verbal storytelling. Actually, instead of referring to the past, the epic preterit rather seems to indicate a change in the modality of speaking, thus adhering to the category of grammatical mood rather than tense. In some languages of oral cultures, however, this presumed mood shows up instead as a way of indicating the source of information. This kind of source information – fully grammaticalized in a quarter of the world’s languages – is called ›evidentiality‹ by linguists. In a phylogenetic perspective on the evolution of cognition, source information only becomes necessary with extended inferential and communicative capabilities and may thus have emerged as a cognitive tool in early humans when entering the ›cognitive niche‹. Evidentiality markers in language may thus be the linguistic reflex of a very ancient cognitive scope category in the innate architecture of the human mind, one which served to separate first-hand experience from reported knowledge. In oral storytelling, evidentiality is marked not only by specific verb forms but also by specific formulas (›they say‹/›it is said‹), intonations, or rhetorical devices. From this perspective, the phenomenon observed by Hamburger and others can be said to originate in the beginning of Tradition – that is, of verbal transmission of cultural knowledge. My hypothesis is that literary narratives in literate cultures still use this ancient cognitive scope operator of ›tradition‹ when employing the epic preterit. Admittedly, in literate cultures it often suffices to put »A n","PeriodicalId":42872,"journal":{"name":"Journal of Literary Theory","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.2,"publicationDate":"2019-09-06","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"https://sci-hub-pdf.com/10.1515/jlt-2019-0008","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"47796921","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
期刊
Journal of Literary Theory
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1