首页 > 最新文献

HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science最新文献

英文 中文
Ernst Mach’s Contribution to the Philosophy of Science in Light of Mary B. Hesse’s Postempiricism 从玛丽·黑塞的后经验主义看恩斯特·马赫对科学哲学的贡献
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2021-06-28 DOI: 10.1086/715876
Pietro Gori
Ernst Mach’s definition of the relationship between thoughts and facts is well known, but the question of how Mach conceived of their actual relationship has received much less attention. This paper aims to address this gap in light of Mary B. Hesse’s view of a postempiricist approach to natural science. As this paper will show, this view is characterized by a constructivist conception of the relationship between theory and facts that seems to be consistent with Mach’s observations on scientific knowledge. The paper first explores Hesse’s account of postempiricism and her project of a new epistemology. It then considers Ernst Mach’s conception of facts as the middle term of a triad of concepts that includes thoughts and elements as extreme terms. Finally, the paper will offer concluding remarks on Mach’s contribution to the debate on scientific realism and his attempt to redefine the notions of correspondence and objectivity in science.
恩斯特·马赫关于思想和事实之间关系的定义是众所周知的,但是马赫是如何构想它们之间的实际关系的问题却很少受到关注。本文旨在根据玛丽·b·黑塞对自然科学的后经验主义方法的看法来解决这一差距。正如本文将表明的那样,这种观点的特点是理论与事实之间关系的建构主义概念,这似乎与马赫对科学知识的观察是一致的。本文首先探讨了黑塞对后经验主义的描述及其新认识论的构想。于是,它把恩斯特·马赫的事实概念看作是包括思想和要素在内的三个概念的中间项。最后,本文将总结马赫对科学实在论辩论的贡献,以及他试图重新定义科学中对应和客观性的概念。
{"title":"Ernst Mach’s Contribution to the Philosophy of Science in Light of Mary B. Hesse’s Postempiricism","authors":"Pietro Gori","doi":"10.1086/715876","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/715876","url":null,"abstract":"Ernst Mach’s definition of the relationship between thoughts and facts is well known, but the question of how Mach conceived of their actual relationship has received much less attention. This paper aims to address this gap in light of Mary B. Hesse’s view of a postempiricist approach to natural science. As this paper will show, this view is characterized by a constructivist conception of the relationship between theory and facts that seems to be consistent with Mach’s observations on scientific knowledge. The paper first explores Hesse’s account of postempiricism and her project of a new epistemology. It then considers Ernst Mach’s conception of facts as the middle term of a triad of concepts that includes thoughts and elements as extreme terms. Finally, the paper will offer concluding remarks on Mach’s contribution to the debate on scientific realism and his attempt to redefine the notions of correspondence and objectivity in science.","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"83 1","pages":"383 - 411"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-06-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"81175994","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Positivism in Action: The Case of Louis Rougier 行动中的实证主义:路易·鲁吉尔案例
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2021-06-28 DOI: 10.1086/715873
Fons Dewulf, M. Simons
In this paper, we investigate how the life and work of Louis Rougier relate to the broader political dimension of logical empiricist philosophy. We focus on three practical projects of Rougier in the 1930s and 1940s: first, his attempts to integrate French-speaking philosophers into an international network of scientific philosophers by organizing two Unity of Science conferences in Paris; second, his role in the renewal of liberalism through the organization of the Walter Lippmann Colloquium; and third, his attempts at political negotiations between Great Britain and the Vichy regime during the Second World War. These activities of Rougier in the 1930s and 1940s have so far never been discussed as part of a unified project on his part. Based on our investigations of these practical projects of Rougier, we argue that his relation to logical empiricist philosophers should primarily be understood on the level of action. His projects aimed to proliferate the concrete improvement of society and the lives of its citizens by expunging all metaphysical questions and speculations from the sphere of social discourse. Rougier conceived logical empiricist philosophers as allies to achieve such practical effects in society.
在本文中,我们研究路易·鲁盖尔的生活和工作如何与逻辑经验主义哲学的更广泛的政治维度相关联。我们将重点放在鲁盖尔在20世纪30年代和40年代的三个实践项目上:首先,他试图通过在巴黎组织两次科学统一会议,将讲法语的哲学家纳入一个国际科学哲学家网络;第二,他通过组织沃尔特·李普曼学术讨论会(Walter Lippmann Colloquium)在自由主义复兴中所起的作用;第三,他在第二次世界大战期间试图在英国和维希政权之间进行政治谈判。到目前为止,鲁吉尔在20世纪30年代和40年代的这些活动从未被作为一个统一项目的一部分来讨论。基于我们对鲁盖尔这些实践项目的调查,我们认为他与逻辑经验主义哲学家的关系应该主要在行动层面上理解。他的项目旨在通过从社会话语领域中消除所有形而上学的问题和猜测来促进社会和公民生活的具体改善。鲁盖尔认为逻辑经验主义哲学家是在社会中实现这种实际效果的盟友。
{"title":"Positivism in Action: The Case of Louis Rougier","authors":"Fons Dewulf, M. Simons","doi":"10.1086/715873","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/715873","url":null,"abstract":"In this paper, we investigate how the life and work of Louis Rougier relate to the broader political dimension of logical empiricist philosophy. We focus on three practical projects of Rougier in the 1930s and 1940s: first, his attempts to integrate French-speaking philosophers into an international network of scientific philosophers by organizing two Unity of Science conferences in Paris; second, his role in the renewal of liberalism through the organization of the Walter Lippmann Colloquium; and third, his attempts at political negotiations between Great Britain and the Vichy regime during the Second World War. These activities of Rougier in the 1930s and 1940s have so far never been discussed as part of a unified project on his part. Based on our investigations of these practical projects of Rougier, we argue that his relation to logical empiricist philosophers should primarily be understood on the level of action. His projects aimed to proliferate the concrete improvement of society and the lives of its citizens by expunging all metaphysical questions and speculations from the sphere of social discourse. Rougier conceived logical empiricist philosophers as allies to achieve such practical effects in society.","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"3 1","pages":"461 - 487"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-06-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"89531299","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Christiaan Huygens’s Natural Theology in His Cosmotheoros and Other Late Writings 克里斯蒂安·惠更斯在他的宇宙论和其他后期作品中的自然神学
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2021-06-28 DOI: 10.1086/715878
Ludovica Marinucci
Christiaan Huygens’s late writings, ranging from 1686 to 1695, bear witness to his philosophical and theological reflections. In his Cosmotheoros, which was intended for publication, and other late writings that can be regarded as its preparatory drafts, Huygens deals with issues central to seventeenth-century philosophical debates: God’s power, divine and human intelligence, probabilistic epistemology, natural theology, and the plurality of worlds. This paper explains how Huygens’s reflections on animals and their souls, rational or not, play a key role in his epistemological reflections on natural theology. The issue of animal generation, as well as of animal souls, is crucial to identifying elements of continuity between the scientific topics of Huygens’s works, and may be considered as the point of intersection between his understanding of mechanism and of the teleology of nature. This neglected perspective on Huygens’s philosophical-natural animism reveals key elements of his model of rationality and of his attitude towards religion, demonstrating his involvement in the debate over animism, in which he seems to have been strongly influenced by English Protestant empiricism.
克里斯蒂安·惠更斯的晚期作品,从1686年到1695年,见证了他的哲学和神学思考。在他准备出版的《宇宙论》和其他后期作品中,惠更斯处理了17世纪哲学辩论的核心问题:上帝的力量、神与人的智慧、概率认识论、自然神学和世界的多元性。本文阐述了惠更斯对动物及其灵魂的思考(无论理性与否)在他对自然神学的认识论反思中所起的关键作用。动物的产生,以及动物的灵魂的问题,对于确定惠更斯作品的科学主题之间的连续性要素是至关重要的,并且可以被认为是他对机制和自然目的论的理解之间的交叉点。对惠更斯的哲学-自然万物有灵论的这种被忽视的观点揭示了他的理性模型和他对宗教的态度的关键要素,表明他参与了关于万物有灵论的辩论,在这场辩论中,他似乎受到了英国新教经验主义的强烈影响。
{"title":"Christiaan Huygens’s Natural Theology in His Cosmotheoros and Other Late Writings","authors":"Ludovica Marinucci","doi":"10.1086/715878","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/715878","url":null,"abstract":"Christiaan Huygens’s late writings, ranging from 1686 to 1695, bear witness to his philosophical and theological reflections. In his Cosmotheoros, which was intended for publication, and other late writings that can be regarded as its preparatory drafts, Huygens deals with issues central to seventeenth-century philosophical debates: God’s power, divine and human intelligence, probabilistic epistemology, natural theology, and the plurality of worlds. This paper explains how Huygens’s reflections on animals and their souls, rational or not, play a key role in his epistemological reflections on natural theology. The issue of animal generation, as well as of animal souls, is crucial to identifying elements of continuity between the scientific topics of Huygens’s works, and may be considered as the point of intersection between his understanding of mechanism and of the teleology of nature. This neglected perspective on Huygens’s philosophical-natural animism reveals key elements of his model of rationality and of his attitude towards religion, demonstrating his involvement in the debate over animism, in which he seems to have been strongly influenced by English Protestant empiricism.","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"1 1","pages":"642 - 659"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-06-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"75981169","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
A Cosmological Controversy in the Renaissance: Marsilio Ficino’s and Giovanni Pico della Mirandola’s Contrasting Views on the Animation of the Heavens 文艺复兴时期的宇宙论之争:马西利奥·菲西诺和乔瓦尼·皮科·德拉·米兰多拉对天堂的动画的不同看法
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2021-06-28 DOI: 10.1086/715884
H. D. Rutkin
In the early twenty-first century, we often ask whether there is life (intelligent or otherwise) in the cosmos, but almost never whether the heavens themselves are actually alive or animated, that is, infused somehow with a soul, the anima mundi, or some such entity. This was not the case in the Middle Ages, the Renaissance, or the early modern period. Although Aristotelians normally answered no to this question, Marsilio Ficino (1433–99) took a decidedly Platonic turn when he answered the question positively, insistently, and consistently in a broad range of works over his entire philosophical career. By contrast, Giovanni Pico della Mirandola (1463–94), Ficino’s younger contemporary, began by embracing the new Platonic position but joined the Aristotelian fold in his later works. In this essay, I will briefly compare and contrast Ficino’s solid and consistent position with the changing trajectory of Pico’s views over the course of his short but intense career. This essay is an exploration of central themes and some preliminary reflections thereon. These essentially Platonic views of a living universe provide the conceptual and literary foundations for understanding this issue in the early modern period.
在21世纪初,我们经常问宇宙中是否有生命(智慧的或其他的),但几乎从来没有问过天堂本身是否真的有生命或有生气,也就是说,以某种方式注入了灵魂,宇宙万物,或其他类似的实体。在中世纪、文艺复兴或近代早期,情况并非如此。虽然亚里士多德学派通常对这个问题的回答是否定的,但马西利奥·菲西诺(1433-99)在他整个哲学生涯的广泛著作中,积极、坚持、一致地回答了这个问题,他果断地转向了柏拉图式。相比之下,与菲西诺同时代的乔瓦尼·皮科·德拉·米兰多拉(Giovanni Pico della Mirandola, 1463-94)一开始接受了新的柏拉图主义立场,但在他后来的作品中加入了亚里士多德的阵营。在这篇文章中,我将简要地比较菲西诺坚定而一致的立场与皮科在其短暂而激烈的职业生涯中不断变化的观点轨迹。本文是对中心主题的探索和一些初步的思考。这些本质上是柏拉图式的关于生命宇宙的观点,为在近代早期理解这个问题提供了概念和文学基础。
{"title":"A Cosmological Controversy in the Renaissance: Marsilio Ficino’s and Giovanni Pico della Mirandola’s Contrasting Views on the Animation of the Heavens","authors":"H. D. Rutkin","doi":"10.1086/715884","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/715884","url":null,"abstract":"In the early twenty-first century, we often ask whether there is life (intelligent or otherwise) in the cosmos, but almost never whether the heavens themselves are actually alive or animated, that is, infused somehow with a soul, the anima mundi, or some such entity. This was not the case in the Middle Ages, the Renaissance, or the early modern period. Although Aristotelians normally answered no to this question, Marsilio Ficino (1433–99) took a decidedly Platonic turn when he answered the question positively, insistently, and consistently in a broad range of works over his entire philosophical career. By contrast, Giovanni Pico della Mirandola (1463–94), Ficino’s younger contemporary, began by embracing the new Platonic position but joined the Aristotelian fold in his later works. In this essay, I will briefly compare and contrast Ficino’s solid and consistent position with the changing trajectory of Pico’s views over the course of his short but intense career. This essay is an exploration of central themes and some preliminary reflections thereon. These essentially Platonic views of a living universe provide the conceptual and literary foundations for understanding this issue in the early modern period.","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"16 1","pages":"604 - 620"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-06-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"79167234","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
“Stahl Was Often Closer to the Truth”: Kant’s Second Thoughts on Animism, Monadology, and Hylozoism “斯塔尔往往更接近真理”:康德对万物有灵论、一元论和动物论的再思考
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2021-06-28 DOI: 10.1086/715879
P. Pecere
In the Dreams of a Spirit-Seer, Elucidated by Dreams of Metaphysics (1766), Kant remarks that Stahl, with his admission of immaterial forces for the explanation of organisms, was “closer to the truth than Hoffmann and Boerhaave, to name but a few,” although the latter adopted a “more philosophical method.” This puzzling statement is very significant for the understanding of Kant’s reception of animism, as it documents Kant’s reaction to the issues raised by the Leibniz-Stahl controversy and his striking preference for Stahl’s nonmechanistic account of organisms. Kant agrees with Stahl that organisms suggest the existence of immaterial thinking beings, but at the same time, the example of this speculative hypothesis leads him to question the explanatory power of metaphysical hypotheses in natural philosophy in general, as well as the possibility of empirically distinguishing among different hypotheses, such as monadology, materialism, and hylozoism. After the analysis of Kant’s skeptical conclusions in the Dreams of a Spirit-Seer, I discuss how this earlier connection of medicine, life sciences, and metaphysics leaves traces in Kant’s later work, by analyzing Kant’s discussion of Samuel Sömmering’s claim that matter “can be animated” in On the Organ of the Soul (1796) and the preliminary drafts for this essay.
在《形而上学之梦》(1766)中,康德评论道,斯塔尔承认非物质力量可以解释生物体,“比霍夫曼和布尔哈夫更接近真理,仅举几例”,尽管后者采用了“更哲学的方法”。这个令人困惑的陈述对于理解康德对万物有灵论的接受是非常重要的,因为它记录了康德对莱布尼茨-斯塔尔争论所引起的问题的反应,以及他对斯塔尔关于有机体的非机械描述的惊人偏好。康德同意斯塔尔关于有机体暗示非物质思维存在的观点,但同时,这种思辨假设的例子使他质疑一般自然哲学中形而上学假设的解释能力,以及在经验上区分不同假设的可能性,如一元论、唯物主义和水合说。在分析了康德在《灵魂预见者之梦》中的怀疑论结论之后,我将通过分析康德在《论灵魂的器官》(1796)中对塞缪尔Sömmering关于物质“可以被赋予生命”的主张的讨论,以及本文的初步草稿,来讨论医学、生命科学和形而上学之间的早期联系如何在康德后来的作品中留下痕迹。
{"title":"“Stahl Was Often Closer to the Truth”: Kant’s Second Thoughts on Animism, Monadology, and Hylozoism","authors":"P. Pecere","doi":"10.1086/715879","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/715879","url":null,"abstract":"In the Dreams of a Spirit-Seer, Elucidated by Dreams of Metaphysics (1766), Kant remarks that Stahl, with his admission of immaterial forces for the explanation of organisms, was “closer to the truth than Hoffmann and Boerhaave, to name but a few,” although the latter adopted a “more philosophical method.” This puzzling statement is very significant for the understanding of Kant’s reception of animism, as it documents Kant’s reaction to the issues raised by the Leibniz-Stahl controversy and his striking preference for Stahl’s nonmechanistic account of organisms. Kant agrees with Stahl that organisms suggest the existence of immaterial thinking beings, but at the same time, the example of this speculative hypothesis leads him to question the explanatory power of metaphysical hypotheses in natural philosophy in general, as well as the possibility of empirically distinguishing among different hypotheses, such as monadology, materialism, and hylozoism. After the analysis of Kant’s skeptical conclusions in the Dreams of a Spirit-Seer, I discuss how this earlier connection of medicine, life sciences, and metaphysics leaves traces in Kant’s later work, by analyzing Kant’s discussion of Samuel Sömmering’s claim that matter “can be animated” in On the Organ of the Soul (1796) and the preliminary drafts for this essay.","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"47 1","pages":"660 - 678"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-06-28","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"90276600","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
Hélène Metzger on Precursors: A Historian and Philosopher of Science Confronts Her Evil Demon 《先驱:一位历史学家和科学哲学家面对她的恶魔》
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2021-05-12 DOI: 10.1086/715155
Cristina Chimisso, N. Jardine
The historian and philosopher of science Hélène Metzger (1889–1944) delivered “Le rôle des précurseurs dans l’évolution de la science” in 1939 as a lecture of the Institut d’Histoire des Sciences et Techniques of the University of Paris, later published in their journal Thalès. In this talk, Metzger not only attacks the notion of “precursor” and a history of science focused on “great men” and their discoveries, but also makes a strong case for the philosophical value of the history of science. We here offer a translation of this witty and subtle essay in the historiography of science, followed by our commentary.
1939年,历史学家和科学哲学家梅茨格(1889-1944)在巴黎大学科学与技术历史研究所的演讲中发表了“Le rôle des pracimcurseurs dans l’samvolution de la science”,后来发表在他们的期刊《thal》上。在这次演讲中,梅茨格不仅抨击了“先驱者”的概念和专注于“伟人”及其发现的科学史,而且还为科学史的哲学价值提出了强有力的论据。我们在这里提供这篇科学史学中机智而微妙的文章的翻译,然后是我们的评论。
{"title":"Hélène Metzger on Precursors: A Historian and Philosopher of Science Confronts Her Evil Demon","authors":"Cristina Chimisso, N. Jardine","doi":"10.1086/715155","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/715155","url":null,"abstract":"The historian and philosopher of science Hélène Metzger (1889–1944) delivered “Le rôle des précurseurs dans l’évolution de la science” in 1939 as a lecture of the Institut d’Histoire des Sciences et Techniques of the University of Paris, later published in their journal Thalès. In this talk, Metzger not only attacks the notion of “precursor” and a history of science focused on “great men” and their discoveries, but also makes a strong case for the philosophical value of the history of science. We here offer a translation of this witty and subtle essay in the historiography of science, followed by our commentary.","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"81 1","pages":"331 - 353"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-05-12","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"83896175","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
A Hot Mess: Girolamo Cardano, the Inquisition, and the Soul 一团乱麻:吉罗拉莫·卡尔达诺、宗教裁判所和灵魂
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2021-04-14 DOI: 10.1086/714435
J. Regier
Girolamo Cardano makes a number of surprising, even shocking claims about the soul in his De subtilitate, one of the most widely read works of natural philosophy in the sixteenth century. When he was finally investigated by the Roman Inquisition and the Index, these claims did not go unnoticed. This study will narrow in on three passages marked as heretical by the first Holy Office censor of De subtilitate. It will consider the Inquisition’s priorities and ask about materialism, determinism, and conceptual inconsistency in Cardano’s views on the soul. The study will give special attention to the claim made by Cardano that souls can be reduced to celestial heat. In addition to De subtilitate, several of Cardano’s other works will be considered for added perspective, especially Contradicentium medicorum libri duodecim.
吉罗拉莫·卡尔达诺(Girolamo Cardano)在他的《论灵魂》(De subtilitate)中提出了许多令人惊讶,甚至震惊的关于灵魂的主张,这是16世纪最广泛阅读的自然哲学著作之一。当他最终被罗马宗教裁判所和索引调查时,这些说法并没有被忽视。本研究将集中在三段经文上,这三段经文被第一个神圣办公室审查员标记为异端。它将考虑宗教裁判所的优先事项,并询问唯物主义,决定论,以及卡尔达诺关于灵魂的观点中的概念不一致。这项研究将特别关注卡尔达诺的说法,即灵魂可以被还原为天热。除了De subtilitate之外,卡尔达诺的其他几部作品也将被考虑为额外的视角,特别是《十二十二指肠图书馆的医学矛盾》。
{"title":"A Hot Mess: Girolamo Cardano, the Inquisition, and the Soul","authors":"J. Regier","doi":"10.1086/714435","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/714435","url":null,"abstract":"Girolamo Cardano makes a number of surprising, even shocking claims about the soul in his De subtilitate, one of the most widely read works of natural philosophy in the sixteenth century. When he was finally investigated by the Roman Inquisition and the Index, these claims did not go unnoticed. This study will narrow in on three passages marked as heretical by the first Holy Office censor of De subtilitate. It will consider the Inquisition’s priorities and ask about materialism, determinism, and conceptual inconsistency in Cardano’s views on the soul. The study will give special attention to the claim made by Cardano that souls can be reduced to celestial heat. In addition to De subtilitate, several of Cardano’s other works will be considered for added perspective, especially Contradicentium medicorum libri duodecim.","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"23 1","pages":"547 - 563"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-04-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"81878816","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2
The Senses of Touch and Movement and the Argument for Active Powers 触觉和运动的感觉以及主动能力的论证
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2021-03-18 DOI: 10.1086/713086
Roger Smith
The paper posits a relationship between the sensory modality of touch, including a sense of active movement, and early modern knowledge of active powers in nature. It seeks to appreciate the strength and appeal of knowledge built on the active-passive distinction, including that which was retrospectively labeled animist. Using statements by Descartes, Hobbes, Locke, Spinoza, Leibniz, and Stahl, rather than detailed new readings of texts, the paper asks whether scholars drew on phenomenal, or conscious, awareness of activity as effort encountering resistance when they reasoned about activity in the world. How were there relations and analogies between descriptions of psyche’s relation to body, of the relation of living forces to matter, of relations among material objects, of God’s relationship to His creation, and of relations involving causal agency generally? It is possible to understand what were later called animistic theories as belonging to the mainstream of the new natural philosophy, not to a residue of unscientific argument. Early modern theories of active and vital powers cannot be dismissed because they were based, in error, on mere analogy to human action. Rather, they had a central position in reasoning grounded in phenomenal awareness of action-resistance when a person is “in touch.”
这篇论文假设了触摸的感觉形态(包括主动运动的感觉)与现代早期对自然界主动力量的认识之间的关系。它试图欣赏建立在主动-被动区别上的知识的力量和吸引力,包括那些被追溯标记为万物有灵论的知识。本文利用笛卡尔、霍布斯、洛克、斯宾诺莎、莱布尼茨和斯塔尔的陈述,而不是详细解读文本,询问学者们在对世界上的活动进行推理时,是否利用了现象性的,或有意识的,对活动的意识,即遇到阻力的努力。心灵与身体的关系,生命力量与物质的关系,物质对象之间的关系,上帝与他的创造物的关系,以及一般涉及因果代理的关系,这些描述之间是如何存在关系和类比的?可以把后来被称为万物有灵论的理论理解为属于新自然哲学的主流,而不是非科学论证的残余。不能因为早期的现代理论仅仅是错误地建立在对人类行为的类比之上,就对其不予理会。相反,当一个人“接触”时,它们在推理中处于中心地位,其基础是对行动阻力的惊人意识。
{"title":"The Senses of Touch and Movement and the Argument for Active Powers","authors":"Roger Smith","doi":"10.1086/713086","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/713086","url":null,"abstract":"The paper posits a relationship between the sensory modality of touch, including a sense of active movement, and early modern knowledge of active powers in nature. It seeks to appreciate the strength and appeal of knowledge built on the active-passive distinction, including that which was retrospectively labeled animist. Using statements by Descartes, Hobbes, Locke, Spinoza, Leibniz, and Stahl, rather than detailed new readings of texts, the paper asks whether scholars drew on phenomenal, or conscious, awareness of activity as effort encountering resistance when they reasoned about activity in the world. How were there relations and analogies between descriptions of psyche’s relation to body, of the relation of living forces to matter, of relations among material objects, of God’s relationship to His creation, and of relations involving causal agency generally? It is possible to understand what were later called animistic theories as belonging to the mainstream of the new natural philosophy, not to a residue of unscientific argument. Early modern theories of active and vital powers cannot be dismissed because they were based, in error, on mere analogy to human action. Rather, they had a central position in reasoning grounded in phenomenal awareness of action-resistance when a person is “in touch.”","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"1 1","pages":"679 - 699"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-03-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"89568154","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Heavenly Animation as the Foundation for Fracastoro’s Homocentrism: Aristotelian-Platonic Eclecticism beyond the School of Padua 《天堂动画》是弗拉卡斯托罗同心论的基础:帕多瓦学派之外的亚里士多德-柏拉图折衷主义
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2021-03-18 DOI: 10.1086/714349
P. Omodeo
This essay deals with Girolamo Fracastoro’s ensouled cosmology. His Homocentrica sive de stellis (1538), an astronomy of concentric spheres, was discussed by the Padua School of Aristotelians. Since the polemics over the immortality of the human soul, which had famously opposed Pomponazzi to Nifo, psychological discussions—including those about heavenly spheres’ souls—raised heated controversies. Fracastoro discussed the foundations of his homocentric planetary theory in a dialogue titled Fracastorius, sive de anima (1555). In a 1531 exchange with Gasparo Contarini, Fracastoro discussed celestial physics, including problems linked to mathematical analysis of physical causation. Contarini expressed his doubts over Fracastoro’s lack of consideration of Aristotelian viewpoints on heavenly souls and intelligences. Fracastoro offered an account of cosmic animation in his later dialogue “On the Soul,” taking a different path than his Paduan teachers. He picked up the Platonic idea of the “world soul,” freely connecting it with Aristotelian views about the ensouled cosmos of concentric spheres, resulting in an eclectic composition of Platonic, Aristotelian, and Averroistic elements. Fracastoro grounded his renewed mathematical astronomy on an understanding of the cosmos as a living whole. His animated homocentric cosmos represented a development of Aristotelian premises and a step beyond this legacy.
本文论述吉罗拉莫·弗拉卡斯托罗的灵魂宇宙论。他的同心圆理论(1538年)被帕多瓦学派的亚里士多德所讨论。自从关于人类灵魂不朽的争论以来,心理学的讨论——包括那些关于天体灵魂的讨论——引发了激烈的争论。弗拉卡斯托罗在一篇名为《弗拉卡斯托罗,巨大的生命》(1555)的对话中讨论了他的同心圆行星理论的基础。在1531年与加斯帕罗·康塔里尼的一次交流中,弗拉卡斯托罗讨论了天体物理学,包括与物理因果关系的数学分析有关的问题。孔塔里尼对弗拉卡斯托洛缺乏考虑亚里士多德关于天堂灵魂和智慧的观点表示怀疑。弗拉卡斯托罗在他后来的对话《论灵魂》(On the Soul)中提供了一种宇宙动画的描述,与他的帕多瓦老师走了一条不同的道路。他接受了柏拉图关于“世界灵魂”的观点,自由地将其与亚里士多德关于同心圆的充满灵魂的宇宙的观点联系起来,从而形成了柏拉图、亚里士多德和阿威罗伊主义元素的折衷组合。弗拉卡斯托罗将他更新的数学天文学建立在对宇宙作为一个活生生的整体的理解之上。他那充满活力的同心宇宙代表了亚里士多德前提的发展,并超越了这一遗产。
{"title":"Heavenly Animation as the Foundation for Fracastoro’s Homocentrism: Aristotelian-Platonic Eclecticism beyond the School of Padua","authors":"P. Omodeo","doi":"10.1086/714349","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/714349","url":null,"abstract":"This essay deals with Girolamo Fracastoro’s ensouled cosmology. His Homocentrica sive de stellis (1538), an astronomy of concentric spheres, was discussed by the Padua School of Aristotelians. Since the polemics over the immortality of the human soul, which had famously opposed Pomponazzi to Nifo, psychological discussions—including those about heavenly spheres’ souls—raised heated controversies. Fracastoro discussed the foundations of his homocentric planetary theory in a dialogue titled Fracastorius, sive de anima (1555). In a 1531 exchange with Gasparo Contarini, Fracastoro discussed celestial physics, including problems linked to mathematical analysis of physical causation. Contarini expressed his doubts over Fracastoro’s lack of consideration of Aristotelian viewpoints on heavenly souls and intelligences. Fracastoro offered an account of cosmic animation in his later dialogue “On the Soul,” taking a different path than his Paduan teachers. He picked up the Platonic idea of the “world soul,” freely connecting it with Aristotelian views about the ensouled cosmos of concentric spheres, resulting in an eclectic composition of Platonic, Aristotelian, and Averroistic elements. Fracastoro grounded his renewed mathematical astronomy on an understanding of the cosmos as a living whole. His animated homocentric cosmos represented a development of Aristotelian premises and a step beyond this legacy.","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"42 1","pages":"585 - 603"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-03-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"86108809","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Matter Is Not Enough 物质是不够的
IF 0.4 Q3 HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Pub Date : 2021-03-18 DOI: 10.1086/713085
Francesco Paolo de Ceglia
What is life, and where does it come from? The question is very old, but it reemerged in the seventeenth century with the crisis of the Aristotelian-Galenic paradigm. Matter was now stripped of any impulse and capacity for self-organization; therefore, it was necessary to find something that would take into account the strength and information that it seemed to hold, especially in what were considered vital phenomena. Georg Ernst Stahl and Friedrich Hoffmann, both professors in Halle and responsible for two of the most famous medical systems of the first half of the eighteenth century, offered solutions to the problem that only appear to be very different. The first invoked the soul as an ideal place of production of the energy that allowed the human body to fight the putrefactive forces in the natural world; the second referred to the concept of ether, to which he attributed modes of action basically similar to those that tradition attributed to vegetative and sensitive souls. This paper highlights the positions of the two physicians, setting them in the climate of the revisitation of ancient certainties that characterized natural philosophy in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries.
什么是生命,生命从何而来?这个问题很老了,但它在17世纪随着亚里士多德-盖伦范式的危机而重新出现。物质现在失去了自我组织的冲动和能力;因此,有必要找到一种方法,考虑到它似乎具有的力量和信息,特别是在被认为是至关重要的现象中。乔治·恩斯特·斯塔尔(Georg Ernst Stahl)和弗里德里希·霍夫曼(Friedrich Hoffmann)都是哈雷大学的教授,负责18世纪上半叶两个最著名的医疗体系,他们为这个问题提供了看似非常不同的解决方案。第一种是将灵魂作为生产能量的理想场所,使人体能够与自然界的腐朽力量作斗争;第二个是乙醚的概念,他认为乙醚的行为方式与传统上认为植物性和敏感灵魂的行为方式基本相似。这篇论文强调了两位医生的立场,将他们置于十七世纪和十八世纪自然哲学特征的古代确定性的重访气氛中。
{"title":"Matter Is Not Enough","authors":"Francesco Paolo de Ceglia","doi":"10.1086/713085","DOIUrl":"https://doi.org/10.1086/713085","url":null,"abstract":"What is life, and where does it come from? The question is very old, but it reemerged in the seventeenth century with the crisis of the Aristotelian-Galenic paradigm. Matter was now stripped of any impulse and capacity for self-organization; therefore, it was necessary to find something that would take into account the strength and information that it seemed to hold, especially in what were considered vital phenomena. Georg Ernst Stahl and Friedrich Hoffmann, both professors in Halle and responsible for two of the most famous medical systems of the first half of the eighteenth century, offered solutions to the problem that only appear to be very different. The first invoked the soul as an ideal place of production of the energy that allowed the human body to fight the putrefactive forces in the natural world; the second referred to the concept of ether, to which he attributed modes of action basically similar to those that tradition attributed to vegetative and sensitive souls. This paper highlights the positions of the two physicians, setting them in the climate of the revisitation of ancient certainties that characterized natural philosophy in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries.","PeriodicalId":42878,"journal":{"name":"HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science","volume":"35 1","pages":"502 - 527"},"PeriodicalIF":0.4,"publicationDate":"2021-03-18","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":null,"resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":"88519177","PeriodicalName":null,"FirstCategoryId":null,"ListUrlMain":null,"RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":"","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":"","EPubDate":null,"PubModel":null,"JCR":null,"JCRName":null,"Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
期刊
HOPOS-The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science
全部 Acc. Chem. Res. ACS Applied Bio Materials ACS Appl. Electron. Mater. ACS Appl. Energy Mater. ACS Appl. Mater. Interfaces ACS Appl. Nano Mater. ACS Appl. Polym. Mater. ACS BIOMATER-SCI ENG ACS Catal. ACS Cent. Sci. ACS Chem. Biol. ACS Chemical Health & Safety ACS Chem. Neurosci. ACS Comb. Sci. ACS Earth Space Chem. ACS Energy Lett. ACS Infect. Dis. ACS Macro Lett. ACS Mater. Lett. ACS Med. Chem. Lett. ACS Nano ACS Omega ACS Photonics ACS Sens. ACS Sustainable Chem. Eng. ACS Synth. Biol. Anal. Chem. BIOCHEMISTRY-US Bioconjugate Chem. BIOMACROMOLECULES Chem. Res. Toxicol. Chem. Rev. Chem. Mater. CRYST GROWTH DES ENERG FUEL Environ. Sci. Technol. Environ. Sci. Technol. Lett. Eur. J. Inorg. Chem. IND ENG CHEM RES Inorg. Chem. J. Agric. Food. Chem. J. Chem. Eng. Data J. Chem. Educ. J. Chem. Inf. Model. J. Chem. Theory Comput. J. Med. Chem. J. Nat. Prod. J PROTEOME RES J. Am. Chem. Soc. LANGMUIR MACROMOLECULES Mol. Pharmaceutics Nano Lett. Org. Lett. ORG PROCESS RES DEV ORGANOMETALLICS J. Org. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. J. Phys. Chem. A J. Phys. Chem. B J. Phys. Chem. C J. Phys. Chem. Lett. Analyst Anal. Methods Biomater. Sci. Catal. Sci. Technol. Chem. Commun. Chem. Soc. Rev. CHEM EDUC RES PRACT CRYSTENGCOMM Dalton Trans. Energy Environ. Sci. ENVIRON SCI-NANO ENVIRON SCI-PROC IMP ENVIRON SCI-WAT RES Faraday Discuss. Food Funct. Green Chem. Inorg. Chem. Front. Integr. Biol. J. Anal. At. Spectrom. J. Mater. Chem. A J. Mater. Chem. B J. Mater. Chem. C Lab Chip Mater. Chem. Front. Mater. Horiz. MEDCHEMCOMM Metallomics Mol. Biosyst. Mol. Syst. Des. Eng. Nanoscale Nanoscale Horiz. Nat. Prod. Rep. New J. Chem. Org. Biomol. Chem. Org. Chem. Front. PHOTOCH PHOTOBIO SCI PCCP Polym. Chem.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
0
微信
客服QQ
Book学术公众号 扫码关注我们
反馈
×
意见反馈
请填写您的意见或建议
请填写您的手机或邮箱
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
现在去查看 取消
×
提示
确定
Book学术官方微信
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术
文献互助 智能选刊 最新文献 互助须知 联系我们:info@booksci.cn
Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。
Copyright © 2023 Book学术 All rights reserved.
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号 京ICP备2023020795号-1